Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Seeing the Stove as World: Significance (Bedeutung) in the Early Wittgenstein.Maria Balaska - 2018 - Philosophical Investigations 42 (1):40-60.
    What is it to see a stove as world (als Welt) and why does the early Wittgenstein use such a curious example to describe what it means to see something as significant (bedeutend)? I argue that Wittgenstein's odd choice can be best understood in the light of a conceptual relation between value and semantic meaning. To that purpose, I draw attention to his use of the word Bedeutung to denote value, and to the direct connection he draws between seeing as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Meditation on Wittgenstein’s Lecture on Ethics.Louis E. Wolcher - 1998 - Law and Critique 9 (1):3-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Function as Use. Wittgenstein's Practical Turn in the Early Manuscripts.Florian Franken Figueiredo - 2018 - Philosophical Investigations 42 (1):66-96.
    The idea that the function of language is its use is commonly ascribed to the Later Wittgenstein. In this paper, I argue that there is textual evidence already coming from the early manuscripts proving that Wittgenstein's philosophical development is culminating in the idea of function as use around 1929–30. I interpret a passage from Ms‐107 in order to show that Wittgenstein's practical turn has sources in different stages of his philosophical development, each of which is dominated by different ideas: the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Instructions for Climbing the Ladder.Mauro Luiz Engelmann - 2018 - Philosophical Investigations 41 (4):446-470.
    I aim to present a solution to the apparent paradox of the Tractatus by means of a minimalist reading grounded in the idea that the correct logical symbolism alone “finally solves” in essentials the philosophical problems. I argue that although the sentences of the Tractatus are nonsensical, rules presented in its symbolism are not. The symbolism itself expresses only a priori rules of logic through schematic variables that do not say anything. I argue that this reading correctly expresses the ladder (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Discussion and Comments: A Response to Prof. Prasad’s ‘Wittgenstein’s Criticism of Moore’s Propositions of Certainty…’.G. Vedaparayana - 2015 - Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research 32 (1):143-155.
    This paper is a response to Prof. B. Sambasiva Prasad’s paper, entitled ‘Wittgenstein’s Criticism of Moore’s Propositions of Certainty: Some Observation’ published in this journal, Volume XX, Number-3, July–September 2003. The objective of Prasad’s paper, as he puts it, is to examine Wittgenstein’s criticism of the propositions of certainty which Moore has made in his essays ‘A Defence of Common Sense’ and ‘Proof of an External World’ with the twin aims of refuting idealism and skepticism and upholding common sense realism. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Explanation classification depends on understanding: extending the epistemic side-effect effect.Daniel A. Wilkenfeld & Tania Lombrozo - 2020 - Synthese 197 (6):2565-2592.
    Our goal in this paper is to experimentally investigate whether folk conceptions of explanation are psychologistic. In particular, are people more likely to classify speech acts as explanations when they cause understanding in their recipient? The empirical evidence that we present suggests this is so. Using the side-effect effect as a marker of mental state ascriptions, we argue that lay judgments of explanatory status are mediated by judgments of a speaker’s and/or audience’s mental states. First, we show that attributions of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Modal—Amodal Distinction in the Debate on Conceptual Format.Sabrina Haimovici - 2018 - Philosophies 3 (2):7.
    In this paper, I review the main criteria offered for distinguishing the modal and amodal approaches to conceptual format: the type of input to which the representations respond, the relation they bear to perceptual states, and the specific neural systems to which they belong. I evaluate different interpretations of them and argue that they all face difficulties. I further show that they lead to cross-classifications of certain types of representations, using approximate number representations as an example.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on Happiness: Harmony, Disharmony and Antitheodicy.Sami Pihlström - 2018 - Philosophical Investigations 42 (1):15-39.
    This paper investigates Wittgenstein's remarks on happiness and harmony in the context of Wittgensteinian antitheodicy. Philosophers of religion inspired by Wittgenstein's philosophy often criticize theodicies seeking to justify apparently meaningless evil and suffering within God's overall harmonious plan. The paper analyses Wittgenstein's early views on happiness as harmony with the world, examining whether they are incompatible with an antitheodicist approach abandoning the very project of theodicy by acknowledging a certain kind of disharmony. However, antitheodicy may also, at the transcendental meta-level, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Pedagogy of Primary Historical Sources in Mathematics: Classroom Practice Meets Theoretical Frameworks.Janet Heine Barnett, Jerry Lodder & David Pengelley - 2014 - Science & Education 23 (1):7-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Harmonic inferentialism and the logic of identity.Stephen Read - 2016 - Review of Symbolic Logic 9 (2):408-420.
    Inferentialism claims that the rules for the use of an expression express its meaning without any need to invoke meanings or denotations for them. Logical inferentialism endorses inferentialism specically for the logical constants. Harmonic inferentialism, as the term is introduced here, usually but not necessarily a subbranch of logical inferentialism, follows Gentzen in proposing that it is the introduction-rules whch give expressions their meaning and the elimination-rules should accord harmoniously with the meaning so given. It is proposed here that the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Confusion, Irrationality and the Ends of Philosophy: Horwich's Wittgenstein Inspired Metaphilosophy.Charles M. K. Djordjevic - 2018 - Philosophical Investigations 41 (3):329-365.
    This paper focuses on Horwich's metaphilosophical interpretation of Wittgenstein. Specifically, it focuses on Horwich's charge that all philosophy is irrational. First, I coordinate the various aspects of Horwich's metaphilosophical program to make sense of his charge of irrationality against philosophy. Second, I argue that this metaphilosophical program misfires in two distinct ways. However, third, I close by calling attention to what I posit to be a critical insight of Horwich's account.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Social Space and the Question of Objectivity/ Der soziale Raum und die Frage nach der Objektivität.James Mensch - 2017 - Gestalt Theory 39 (2-3):249-262.
    In speaking of the social dimensions of human experience, we inevitably become involved in the debate regarding how they are to be studied. Should we embrace the first-person perspective, which is that of the phenomenologists, and begin with the experiences composing our directly experienced lifeworld? Alternately, should we follow the lead of natural scientists and take up the third-person perspective? This is the perspective that asserts that we must begin with what is true for everyone, i.e., with what is available (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Anatomia da Linguagem: Podemos Compreender Jogos de Linguagem a Partir de Redes Corticais?Inês Hipólito - 2017 - Kairos 18 (1):84-109.
    There is today much interest in research of neuronal substrata in metaphor processing. It has been suggested that the right hemisphere yields a key role in the comprehension of figurative language and, particularly, in metaphors. Figurative language is included in pragmatics, a branch of linguistics that researches the use of language, in opposition to the study of the system of language. There lingers, though, an open debate in respect to the identification of the specific aspects concerning semantics, as opposed to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wahrheit, Wirklichkeit und Logik in der Sprache der Physik.Peter Mittelstaedt - 1983 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 14 (1):24-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Self-Awareness of the Mind: Phenomenal World and the Mind Beyond.Ja-Kyoung Han - 2015 - Diogenes 62 (2):16-25.
    What we regard as real are the objects of the phenomenal world which we perceive. We regard those that we see objectively, as in the third person perspective, as real. What then is the mind that pe...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Process Re-engineering and formal ontology.David W. Rodick - 2015 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 41 (6):557-576.
    John Dewey viewed philosophy as an intelligent means of realizing change, emphasizing the ubiquity of process, context and relations. The revolution in Organizational Behavior known as Process Re-engineering (PR) is an approach to organizational thinking recognizing the importance of process, context and relations at all levels of organizational activity. Because Dewey’s philosophy affords primacy to process and change, context and relations, it is fundamentally aligned with PR. Compelling connections between PR and Dewey’s philosophy are established concerning primacy of process, importance (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Role of the Disquotational Schema in Wittgenstein's Reflections on Truth.Pasquale Frascolla - 2016 - Philosophical Investigations 40 (3):205-222.
    In the first paragraph, the focus is on the early Wittgenstein's conception of truth: the Disquotational Schema is shown to be derivable from the semantic and ontological principles of the picture theory. Then, the article scrutinises the way the Disquotational Schema provides the basis for what the later Wittgenstein takes as a philosophically appropriate description of the practice of making assertions. The general abstract notion of truth makes room for a situated notion of warranted assertibility as the key-notion. Last, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Simulation Methods for an Abductive System in Science.Tom Addis, Jan Townsend Addis, Dave Billinge, David Gooding & Bart-Floris Visscher - 2008 - Foundations of Science 13 (1):37-52.
    We argue that abduction does not work in isolation from other inference mechanisms and illustrate this through an inference scheme designed to evaluate multiple hypotheses. We use game theory to relate the abductive system to actions that produce new information. To enable evaluation of the implications of this approach we have implemented the procedures used to calculate the impact of new information in a computer model. Experiments with this model display a number of features of collective belief-revision leading to consensus-formation, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Hermeneutic and Analytic Philosophy. Two Complementary Versions of the Linguistic Turn?Jürgen Habermas - 1999 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 44:413-441.
    In a series of lectures on German philosophy ‘since Kant’, the names of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel and their critical reference to Kant are, of course, a must. No less a must, though, would seem to be Wilhelm von Humboldt, a philosopher and linguist who, together with Herder and Hamann, formed the alliterating triumvirate of a romanticist critique of Kant. The response, within the discipline, to transcendental philosophy from this side was, in contrast to the idealistic mainstream, long in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Vorprung durch Logik: The German Analytic Tradition.Hans-Johann Glock - 1999 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 44:137-166.
    Although at present analytic philosophy is practiced mainly in the English-speaking world, it is to a considerable part the invention of German speakers. Its emergence owes much to Russell, Moore, and American Pragmatism, but even more to Frege, Wittgenstein, and the logical positivists of the Vienna Circle. No one would think of analytic philosophy as a specifically Anglophone phenomenon, if the Nazis had not driven many of its pioneers out of central Europe.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wittgenstein et son œuvre posthume. [REVIEW]Mathieu Marion - 1996 - Dialogue 35 (4):777-790.
    Wittgenstein est mort en 1951 et on attend toujours une édition de ses œuvres complètes. Ce n'est qu'en 1994 que sont parus, accompagnés d'un volume d'introduction à l'ensemble du projet d'édition de la main du directeur de publication, Michael Nedo, les deux premiers d'une série de quinze volumes, les Wiener Ausgabe, qui reproduiront l'intégralité des écrits de Wittgenstein, de son retour à Cambridge en janvier 1929 à la première version du Big Typescript en 1933, avec index et concordances. D'après le (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Variable Names and Constant Names in Wittgenstein's Tractatus.Leo K. C. Cheung - 2005 - Philosophical Investigations 28 (1):14-42.
    In this paper, I argue that the Tractatus classifies names into constant names and variable names. A variable name, via the application of the existential quantifier against the background of picturing, picks out and denotes an unspecified object from the range of objects of the form shown by the relevant variable. A constant name labels an object picked out from a scope of the existential quantifier. I also refute two types of attempts to argue that the Tractarian relation between a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Beyond H acker's W ittgenstein: Discussion of HACKER, P eter (2012) “ W ittgenstein on Grammar, Theses and Dogmatism” Philosophical Investigations 35:1, J anuary 2012, 1–17. [REVIEW]Danièle Moyal-Sharrock - 2013 - Philosophical Investigations 36 (4):355-380.
    In “Wittgenstein on Grammar, Theses and Dogmatism,” Peter Hacker addresses what he takes to be misconceptions of Wittgenstein's philosophy with respect to (1) the periodisation of his thought and to what should properly be counted as part of his work; (2) his conception of grammar since the Big Typescript (1929–33); and (3) his conception of philosophy as grammatical investigation. I argue that Hacker's restrictive conception of what ought to be considered part of Wittgenstein's philosophy and his conservative view of Wittgensteinian (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Infinity Goes Up On Trial: Must Immortality Be Meaningless?Timothy Chappell - 2009 - European Journal of Philosophy 17 (1):30-44.
    Critically debates the distinction of different types of boredom and its impact on Williams’s argument, as well as the question of why personal identity should be threatened by eternally having new ground projects.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Logic and Language in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. [REVIEW]Michael Kremer - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (2):327-330.
    This short book comprises “four largely self-contained studies … unified by a common interpretive approach”, the “investigation of the historical development of … Wittgenstein’s early philosophy”. Proops applies this historical approach to Wittgenstein’s conception of logic, his critique of “logical assertion,” his “picture theory” of language, and his discussion of the justification of deduction. He endeavors to “bring out how Wittgenstein develops his views … as foils to the positions developed by Frege and Russell”, arguing that “it is not Frege (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reference and Unity in Kant’s Theory of Judgment.Martha I. Gibson - 1995 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25 (2):229-256.
    An account of judgment ought to explain the fact that a judgment is, or may be, about some object. A judgment may be about some object if it contains some part, or term, which is related to the object, on the one hand, and related to- ‘combined with’ — the other parts of the judgment, on the other, in such a way that the whole judgment is consequently about that object. The relation of that term to the object may be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • From What Can't Be Said to What Isn't Known.Christine McKinnon - 1991 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 (1):87-107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tolstoy and Wittgenstein.David Woodruff Smith - 2002 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 40 (3):421-435.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Logical Space and the Space of Sight: The Relevance of Wittgenstein's Arguments to Recent Issues in the Philosophy of Mind.Ludovic Soutif - 2008 - Dialogue 47 (3-4):501-536.
    In this article, I show and discuss the relevance of Wittgenstein's arguments as to the spatial structure of sight to recent issues in the philosophy of mind. The first, bearing upon the dimensionality of the manifolds at play in depiction, plays a critical role in Clark's attempt to provide an independent account ofqualiaand of their differentiative properties. The second, pertaining to the properly spatial structure formed by the data of sight, is explicitly appealed to in the debate on the realistic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Varieties of Objectivity: Reply to De Mesel.Mario Brandhorst - 2015 - Philosophical Investigations 40 (1):64-81.
    In a previous paper, I argued that the later Wittgenstein did not endorse a realist account of ethics, where a realist account is understood to involve a claim to truth as well as objectivity. In this paper, I respond to a number of critical questions that Benjamin De Mesel raises about that interpretation. I agree with him that just as there are uses for expressions such as “truth”, “fact” and “reality” in ethics, there are uses for expressions such as “objectivity” (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Philosopher's Baedeker: Wittgenstein's Tractatus as Guidebook.Kevin MacNeil - 2017 - Philosophical Investigations 40 (4):350-369.
    The Wittgenstein of the Tractatus is committed to four central and interlocking claims: a limit to sense and nonsense can be drawn in logic; a limit to meaningful and meaningless language – to meaningful and meaningless nonsense – cannot be drawn in logic; whether nonsense is meaningful is shown in its use rather than its form; the Tractatus consists largely of meaningful nonsense. Undergirding these commitments is an account of language-to-world picturing in which shared “mathematical multiplicities” play a key role. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Chains of Life: Turing, Lebensform, and the Emergence of Wittgenstein’s Later Style.Juliet Floyd - 2016 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 5 (2):7-89.
    This essay accounts for the notion of _Lebensform_ by assigning it a _logical _role in Wittgenstein’s later philosophy. Wittgenstein’s additions of the notion to his manuscripts of the _PI_ occurred during the initial drafting of the book 1936-7, after he abandoned his effort to revise _The Brown Book_. It is argued that this constituted a substantive step forward in his attitude toward the notion of simplicity as it figures within the notion of logical analysis. Next, a reconstruction of his later (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The University of Iowa Tractatus Map.David G. Stern - 2016 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 5 (2):203-220.
    Drawing on recent work on the nature of the numbering system of the _Tractatus_ and Wittgenstein’s use of that system in his composition of the _Prototractatus_, the paper sets out the rationale for the online tool called__ __ The University of Iowa Tractatus Map. The map consists of a website with a front page that links to two separate subway-style maps of the hypertextual numbering system Wittgenstein used in his _Tractatus_. One map displays the structure of the published _Tractatus_; the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Presentation as indirection, indirection as schooling: The two aspects of Benjamin’s scholastic method.Ori Rotlevy - 2016 - Continental Philosophy Review 50 (4):493-516.
    Why does Walter Benjamin claim “indirection” to be the proper method for philosophical contemplation and writing? Why is this method—embodied, according to Benjamin, in the convoluted form of scholastic treatises and in their use of citations—fundamental for understanding his Origin of German Trauerspiel as suggesting an alternative to most strands of modern philosophy? The explicit and well-studied function of this method is for the presentation of what cannot be represented in language, of what cannot be intended or approached in thinking. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Philosophical Anti-authoritarianism.Dylan B. Futter - 2016 - Philosophia 44 (4):1333-1349.
    Unlike certain commentary traditions of philosophy in which deference to an authoritative author was a central feature, there are within the analytical tradition no recognised authorities to whom the reader is required to defer. This paper takes up the question of whether this anti-authoritarian position in philosophy can be sustained. Three lines of argument are considered. According to the first, there are no credible authorities in philosophy, or, even if there were, these authorities could not be identified by the non-expert (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Conventionalism, Truth, and CosmologicaI Furniture.J. O. Wisdom - 1975 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 4 (3):441-457.
    The problem to be discussed here concerns ontology so far as it may not be formed by scientific theory. In brief terms, the problem arises in the following way. On the one hand, the world surely consists of whatever is there, irrespective of whether human beings are around or not, and irrespective especially of whether human beings have constructed any scientific theories depicting the nature of the world; on the other hand, scientific theories are subject to the limitation that we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How Philosophers Appeal to Priority to Effect Revolution.Micah D. Tillman - 2016 - Metaphilosophy 47 (2):304-322.
    This article argues that philosophers tend to employ a particular method in constructing their theories and critiquing their opponents. To substantiate this claim, the article examines the work of Nietzsche and Locke, the Empiricists and Rationalists, Heidegger, Levinas, and Derrida, and Russell and Wittgenstein, showing how each relies on a method the article labels “revolution-through-return.” The method consists in identifying the authority behind your opponent's theory, then appealing to something “prior to” that authority, from which you then proceed to derive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Book review: Alessandra Tanesini. Wittgenstein: A feminist interpretation. London: Polity press, 2004. [REVIEW]Peg O'Connor - 2006 - Hypatia 21 (3):207-210.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mathematics and Forms of Life.Severin Schroeder - 2015 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 4:111-130.
    According to Wittgenstein, mathematics is embedded in, and partly constituting, a form of life. Hence, to imagine different, alternative forms of elementary mathematics, we should have to imagine different practices, different forms of life in which they could play a role. If we tried to imagine a radically different arithmetic we should think either of a strange world or of people acting and responding in very peculiar ways. If such was their practice, a calculus expressing the norms of representation they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Frege on the Normativity and Constitutivity of Logic for Thought II.Daniele Mezzadri - 2015 - Philosophy Compass 10 (9):592-600.
    This two-part paper reviews a scholarly debate on an alleged tension in Frege's philosophy of logic. In Section 1 of Part I, I discuss Frege's view that logic is concerned with establishing norms for correct thinking and is therefore a normative science. In Section 2, I explore a different understanding of the role of logic that Frege seems to advance: logic is constitutive of the very possibility of thought, because it sets forth necessary conditions for thought. Hence, the tension the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • From words and sentences to interjections: The anatomy of exclamations in Peirce and Wittgenstein.Dinda L. Gorlée - 2015 - Semiotica 2015 (205):37-86.
    Name der Zeitschrift: Semiotica Jahrgang: 2015 Heft: 205 Seiten: 37-86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does Wittgenstein have a Method? The Challenges of Conant and Schulte.Sebastian Wyss - 2015 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 4 (1):167-193.
    Does Wittgenstein have a method? There are two challenges to an affirmative answer. One is put forth by Schulte, who claims that Wittgenstein’s method is little more than a skill, and thus not a method in any ambitious sense of that word. Another is Conant’s view that the philosophy of the later Wittgenstein entertains not one method, but a variety of methods. I tackle these challenges by questioning what I take to be their presupposed conceptions of ‘method’ and conclude that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Nothingness and Emptiness: A Buddhist Engagement with the Ontology of Jean-Paul Sartre.Steven W. Laycock - 2012 - SUNY Press.
    Using Buddhist thought, explores and challenges the philosophy of Jean-Paul Sartre.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Positivism Before Hart.Frederick Schauer - 2011 - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 24 (2):455-471.
    Many contemporary practitioners of analytic jurisprudence take their understanding of legal positivism largely from Hart, and the debates about legal positivism exist largely in a post-Hartian world. But if we examine carefully the writings and motivations of Bentham and even Austin, we will discover that there are good historical grounds for treating both a normative version of positivism and a version more focused on legal decision-making as entitled to at least co-equal claims on the positivist tradition. And even if we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wittgenstein and Nietzsche Agonal relations in language.Janet Lungstrum - 1995 - Deutsche Vierteljahrsschrift für Literaturwissenschaft Und Geistesgeschichte 69 (2):300-323.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kindness and the Good Society: Connections of the Heart.William S. Hamrick - 2002 - State University of New York Press.
    A comprehensive account of human kindness.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Discipline.Bryan S. Turner - 2006 - Theory, Culture and Society 23 (2-3):183-186.
    There are broadly five interconnected meanings of the noun ‘discipline’. Disciplinawere instructions to disciples, and hence a branch of instruction or department of knowledge. This religious context provided the modern educational notion of a ‘body of knowledge’, or a discipline such as sociology or economics. We can define discipline as a body of knowledge and knowledge for the body, because the training of the mind has inevitably involved a training of the body. Second, it signified a method of training or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Paying the price for methodological solipsism.Stephen P. Stich - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):97-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Methodological solipsism.Andrew Woodfield - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):98-99.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Fodor's guide to cognitive psychology.Jerrold J. Katz - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):85-89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark