Switch to: Citations

References in:

Basic Actions Reloaded

Philosophy Compass 12 (9):e12435 (2017)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Intention.G. E. M. Anscombe - 1957 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 57:321-332.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1007 citations  
  • The problem of action.Harry G. Frankfurt - 1997 - In Alfred R. Mele (ed.), The philosophy of action. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 157-62.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   195 citations  
  • Argument for token identity.Christopher Peacocke - 1979 - In Holistic Explanation: Action, Space, Interpretation. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • What we can do.Arthur C. Danto - 1963 - Journal of Philosophy 60 (15):435-445.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • I—Ursula Coope: Aristotle on Action.Ursula Coope - 2007 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 81 (1):109-138.
    When I raise my arm, what makes it the case that my arm's going up is an instance of my raising my arm? In this paper, I discuss Aristotle's answer to this question. His view, I argue, is that my arm's going up counts as my raising my arm just in case it is an exercise of a certain kind of causal power of mine. I show that this view differs in an interesting way both from the Davidsonian ‘standard causal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Aristotle on action.Ursula Coope - 2007 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 81 (1):109–138.
    When I raise my arm, what makes it the case that my arm's going up is an instance of my raising my arm? In this paper, I discuss Aristotle's answer to this question. His view, I argue, is that my arm's going up counts as my raising my arm just in case it is an exercise of a certain kind of causal power of mine. I show that this view differs in an interesting way both from the Davidsonian ‘standard causal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • I’m just sitting around doing nothing: on exercising intentional agency in omitting to act.Andrei A. Buckareff - 2018 - Synthese 195 (10):4617-4635.
    In some recent work on omissions, it has been argued that the causal theory of action cannot account for how agency is exercised in intentionally omitting to act in the same way it explains how agency is exercised in intentional action. Thus, causalism appears to provide us with an incomplete picture of intentional agency. I argue that causalists should distinguish causalism as a general theory of intentional agency from causalism as a theory of intentional action. Specifically, I argue that, while (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Action-Individuation and Doxastic Agency.Andrei A. Buckareff - 2011 - Theoria 77 (4):312-332.
    In this article, I challenge the dominant view of the importance of the debate over action-individuation. On the dominant view, it is held that the conclusions we reach about action-individuation make little or no difference for other debates in the philosophy of action, much less in other areas of philosophy. As a means of showing that the dominant view is mistaken, I consider the implications of accepting a given theory of action-individuation for thinking about doxastic agency. In particular, I am (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Danto on basic actions.Myles Brand - 1968 - Noûs 2 (2):187-190.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Agent-causation.John Bishop - 1983 - Mind 92 (January):61-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Expressive Actions.Monika Betzler - 2009 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 52 (3):272-292.
    Actions expressing emotions (such as caressing the clothes of one's dead friend in grief, or tearing apart a photograph out of jealousy) pose a notorious challenge to action theorists. They are thought to be intentional in that they are in some sense under the agent's control. They are not thought to be done for a reason, however, because they cannot be explained by considerations that favor them from the agent's point of view. This seems to be the case, at least, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Actions are not events.Kent Bach - 1980 - Mind 89 (353):114-120.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Does Philosophy of Action Rest on a Mistake?Andrew Sneddon - 2001 - Metaphilosophy 32 (5):502-522.
    Philosophers of action tend to take for granted the concept of basic actions – actions that are done at will, or directly – as opposed to others that are performed in other ways. This concept does foundational work in action theory; many theorists, especially causalists, take part of their task to be showing that normal, complex actions necessarily stem from basic ones somehow. The case for the concept of basic actions is driven by a family of observations and a cluster (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Agents and their actions.Maria Alvarez & John Hyman - 1998 - Philosophy 73 (2):219-245.
    In the past thirty years or so, the doctrine that actions are events has become an essential, and sometimes unargued, part of the received view in the philosophy of action, despite the efforts of a few philosophers to undermine the consensus. For example, the entry for Agency in a recently published reference guide to the philosophy of mind begins with the following sentence: A central task in the philosophy of action is that of spelling out the differences between events in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Actions in their circumstances.Jennifer Hornsby - 2011 - In Anton Ford, Jennifer Hornsby & Frederick Stoutland (eds.), Essays on Anscombe's Intention. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Life and action: elementary structures of practice and practical thought.Michael Thompson - 2008 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    Part I: The representation of life -- Can life be given a real definition? -- The representation of the living individual -- The representation of the life-form itself -- Part II: Naive action theory -- Types of practical explanation -- Naive explanation of action -- Action and time -- Part III: Practical generality -- Two tendencies in practical philosophy -- Practices and dispositions as sources of the goodness of individual actions -- Practice and disposition as sources of individual action.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   374 citations  
  • Must There Be Basic Action?Douglas Lavin - 2012 - Noûs 47 (2):273-301.
    The idea of basic action is a fixed point in the contemporary investigation of the nature of action. And while there are arguments aimed at putting the idea in place, it is meant to be closer to a gift of common sense than to a hard-won achievement of philosophical reflection. It first appears at the stage of innocuous description and before the announcement of philosophical positions. And yet, as any decent magician knows, the real work so often gets done in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Norm and action.Georg Henrik von Wright - 1963 - New York,: Humanities.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   134 citations  
  • Practical reflection.J. David Velleman - 1985 - Philosophical Review 94 (1):33-61.
    “What do you see when you look at your face in the mirror?” asks J. David Velleman in introducing his philosophical theory of action. He takes this simple act of self-scrutiny as a model for the reflective reasoning of rational agents: our efforts to understand our existence and conduct are aided by our efforts to make it intelligible. Reflective reasoning, Velleman argues, constitutes practical reasoning. By applying this conception, _Practical Reflection_ develops philosophical accounts of intention, free will, and the foundation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   129 citations  
  • The Right Structure for a Causal Theory of Action.Rowland Stout - 2002 - Facta Philosophica 4 (1):11-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Basic actions and causality.Frederick Stoutland - 1968 - Journal of Philosophy 65 (16):467-475.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Processes, Continuants, and Individuals.Helen Steward - 2013 - Mind 122 (487):fzt080.
    The paper considers and opposes the view that processes are best thought of as continuants, to be differentiated from events mainly by way of the fact that the latter, but not the former, are entities with temporal parts. The motivation for the investigation, though, is not so much the defeat of what is, in any case, a rather implausible claim, as the vindication of some of the ideas and intuitions that the claim is made in order to defend — and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Actions as processes.Helen Steward - 2012 - Philosophical Perspectives 26 (1):373-388.
    The paper argues that actions should be thought of as processes and not events. A number of reasons are offered for thinking that the things that it is most plausible to suppose we are trying to cotton on to with the generic talk of ‘actions’ in which philosophy indulges cannot be events. A framework for thinking about the event-process distinction which can help us understand how we ought to think about the ontology of processes we need instead is then developed, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Bodily Movement and Its Significance.Will Small - 2016 - Philosophical Topics 44 (1):183-206.
    I trace the development of one aspect of Fred Stoutland’s thought about action by considering the central role given by contemporary philosophy of action to bodily movement. Those who tell the so-called standard story of action think that actions are bodily movements (arm raisings, leg bendings, etc.) caused by beliefs and desires, that cause further effects in the world (switch flippings, door movements, etc.) in virtue of which they can be described (as flippings of switches, shuttings of doors, etc.). Those (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Basic Actions and Individuation.Constantine Sandis - 2010 - In Timothy O'Connor & Constantine Sandis (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Action. Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 10–17.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Basic Actions Action Individuation References Further reading.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Holistic Explanation: Action, Space, Interpretation.Christopher Peacocke - 1979 - New York: Clarendon Press.
    INTRODUCTION The philosophy of action and the philosophy of space and time may well seem to be unconnected areas. I will argue that in each of these areas ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Review of Reasonably Vicious, by Candace Vogler. [REVIEW]Elijah Millgram - 2006 - European Journal of Philosophy 14 (3):430–434.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reasonably Vicious, by Candace Vogler. [REVIEW]Elijah Millgram - 2006 - European Journal of Philosophy 14 (3):430-434.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Arational actions.Rosalind Hursthouse - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy 88 (2):57-68.
    According to the standard account of actions and their explanations, intentional actions are actions done because the agent has a certain desire/belief pair that explains the action by rationalizing it. Any explanation of intentional action in terms of an appetite or occurrent emotion is hence assumed to be elliptical, implicitly appealing to some appropriate belief. In this paper, I challenge this assumption with respect to the " arational " actions of my title---a significant subset of the set of intentional actions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   138 citations  
  • Knowledge and Abilities in Action.Jennifer Hornsby - 2007 - In Christian Kanzian (ed.), Cultures. Conflict - Analysis - Dialogue: Proceedings of the 29th International Ludwig Wittgenstein-Symposium in Kirchberg, Austria. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 165-180.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hornsby on the phenomenology of speech.Jennifer Hornsby & Jason Stanley - 2005 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 79 (1):131–145.
    The central claim is that the semantic knowledge exercised by people when they speak is practical knowledge. The relevant idea of practical knowledge is explicated, applied to the case of speaking, and connected with an idea of agents’ knowledge. Some defence of the claim is provided.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Jennifer Hornsby.Jennifer Hornsby - 2005 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 79 (1):107-130.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Basic Activity.Jennifer Hornsby - 2013 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 87 (1):1-18.
    I present a view of activity, taking it that an agent is engaged in activity so long as an action of hers is occurring. I suggest that this view (a) helps in understanding what goes wrong in an argument in Thompson (2008) known sometimes as the ‘initial segment argument’, and (b) enables us to see that there could be an intelligible conception of what is basic when agents' knowledge is allowed into an account of that.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • What good is a diachronic will?Luca Ferrero - 2009 - Philosophical Studies 144 (3):403-430.
    There are two standard conceptions of the functioning of and rationale for the diachronic will, i.e., for an agent's capacity to settle on her future conduct in advance. According to the pragmatic-instrumentalist view, the diachronic will benefits us by increasing the long-term satisfaction of our rational preferences. According to the cognitive view, it benefits us by satisfying our standing desire for self-knowledge and self-understanding. Contrary to these views, I argue for a constitutive view of the diachronic will: the rationale for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Slip-Proof Actions.Santiago Amaya - 2016 - In Roman Altshuler & Michael J. Sigrist (eds.), Time and the Philosophy of Action. Routledge. pp. 21-36.
    Most human actions are complex, but some of them are basic. Which are these? In this paper, I address this question by invoking slips, a common kind of mistake. The proposal is this: an action is basic if and only if it is not possible to slip in performing it. The argument discusses some well-established results from the psychology of language production in the context of a philosophical theory of action. In the end, the proposed criterion is applied to discuss (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Basic Actions.Arthur C. Danto - 1965 - American Philosophical Quarterly 2 (2):141 - 148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • The Argument from Slips.Santiago Amaya - 2015 - In Andrei Buckareff, Carlos Moya & Sergi Rosell (eds.), Agency, Freedom, and Moral Responsibility. pp. 13-29.
    Philosophers of perception are familiar with the argument from illusion, at least since Hume formulated it to challenge a naïve form of realism. In this paper, I present an analogous argument but in the domain of action. It focuses on slips, a common kind of mistake. But, otherwise, it is structurally similar. The argument challenges some contemporary views about the nature of action inspired by Wittgenstein. The discussion shows how thinking about these common mistakes helps illuminate aspects of human agency (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Non-Intentional Actions.David K. Chan - 1995 - American Philosophical Quarterly 32 (2):139 - 151.
    The aim of the paper is to show that there are actions which are non-intentional. An account is first given which links intentional and unintentional action to acting for a reason, or appropriate causation by an intention. Mannerisms and habitual actions are then presented as examples of behavior which are actions, but which are not done in the course of acting for a reason. This account has advantages over that of Hursthouse's "arational actions," which are allegedly intentional actions done for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • On Action.Carl Ginet - 1990 - Mind 100 (3):390-394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   252 citations  
  • Natural Agency.John Bishop - 1989 - Mind 100 (2):287-290.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • Determinism, intentional action, and bodily movements.Frederick Stoutland - 2009 - In Constantine Sandis (ed.), New Essays on the Explanation of Action. Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Sub-intentional actions and the over-mentalization of agency.Helen Steward - 2009 - In Constantine Sandis (ed.), New Essays on the Explanation of Action. Palgrave-Macmillan.
    This paper argues, by attention to the category of sub-intentional agency, that many conceptions of the nature of agency are 'over-mentalised', in that they insist that an action proper must be produced by something like an intention or a reason or a desire. Sub-intentional actions provide counterexamples to such conceptions. Instead, it is argued, we should turn to the concept of a two-way power in order to home in on the essential characteristics of actions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Analytical Philosophy of Action.Arthur C. Danto - 1973 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 7 (1):187-191.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Actions.J. Hornsby - 1982 - Mind 91 (361):147-149.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   128 citations  
  • Analytic Philosophy of Action.Arthur C. Danto - 1975 - Mind 84 (334):304-306.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Search for Basic Actions.Annette Baier - 1971 - American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (2):161 - 170.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • He buttered the toast while baking a fresh loaf.Constantine Sandis - forthcoming - Philosophy and Public Issues - Filosofia E Questioni Pubbliche.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation