Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. ch. 6. Time, norms, and structure in nineteenth-century philosophy of science.David Hyder - 2015 - In Michael Beaney (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of The History of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford University Press UK. pp. 250.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Cohen and Helmholtz on the Foundations of Measurement.Francesca Biagioli - 2018 - In Christian Damböck (ed.), Philosophie Und Wissenschaft Bei Hermann Cohen/Philosophy and Science in Hermann Cohen. Springer Verlag. pp. 77-100.
    It is well known that Hermann Cohen was one of the first philosophers who engaged in the debate about non-Euclidean geometries and the concept of space. His relation to Hermann von Helmholtz, who played a major role in the same debate, is an illuminating example of how some of the leading ideas of Marburg neo-Kantianism, although motivated independently of scientific debates, naturally led to the examination of scientific works and scientists’ epistemological views. This paper deals with Cohen’s view of magnitudes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • „Zwei Bedeutungen des Apriori“. Hermann Cohens Unterscheidung zwischen metaphysischem und transzendentalem a priori und die Vorgeschichte des relativierten a priori.Marco Giovanelli - 2018 - In Christian Damböck (ed.), Philosophie Und Wissenschaft Bei Hermann Cohen/Philosophy and Science in Hermann Cohen. Springer Verlag. pp. 177-203.
    In his 1920 monograph Relativitätstheorie und Erkenntnis apriori the young Reichenbach distinguished between two meanings of the a priori: ‚apodictically valid, true for all time‘ and ‚constituting the concept of object‘. At the end of the 1990s Michael Friedman drew again the attention of philosophers of science to this forgotten distinction. In the spirit of Reichenbach’s early Kantianism Friedman attempted to construct a relativized or temporally variable a priori, which is nevertheless constitutive of the object of knowledge. Friedman rejects an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Kant, Reichenbach, and the Fate of A Priori Principles.Karin de Boer - 2010 - European Journal of Philosophy 19 (4):507-531.
    Abstract: This article contends that the relation of early logical empiricism to Kant was more complex than is often assumed. It argues that Reichenbach's early work on Kant and Einstein, entitled The Theory of Relativity and A Priori Knowledge (1920) aimed to transform rather than to oppose Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. One the one hand, I argue that Reichenbach's conception of coordinating principles, derived from Kant's conception of synthetic a priori principles, offers a valuable way of accounting for the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Kant, Neo‐Kantians, and Transcendental Subjectivity.Charlotte Baumann - 2017 - European Journal of Philosophy 25 (3):595-616.
    This article discusses an interpretation of Kant's conception of transcendental subjectivity, which manages to avoid many of the concerns that have been raised by analytic interpreters over this doctrine. It is an interpretation put forward by selected C19 and early C20 neo-Kantian writers. The article starts out by offering a neo-Kantian interpretation of the object as something that is constituted by the categories and that serves as a standard of truth within a theory of judgment. The second part explicates transcendental (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Neo-Kantianism and the Roots of Anti-Psychologism.R. Lanier Anderson - 2005 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 13 (2):287-323.
    This paper explores a pair of puzzling and controversial topics in the history of late nineteenth-century philosophy: the psychologism debates, and the nature of neo-Kantianism. Each is sufficientl...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Hermann Cohen.Scott Edgar - 2010 - The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Hermann Cohen (b. 1842, d. 1919), more than any other single figure, is responsible for founding the orthodox neo-Kantianism that dominated academic philosophy in Germany from the 1870s until the end of the First World War. Earlier German philosophers finding inspiration in Kant tended either towards speculative, metaphysical idealism, or sought to address philosophical questions with the resources of the empirical sciences, especially psychology. In contrast, Cohen’s seminal interpretation of Kant offered a vision of philosophy that decisively maintained its independence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Zur mathematischen Wissenschaftsphilosophie des Marburger Neukantianismus.Thomas Mormann - 2018 - In Christian Damböck (ed.), Philosophie und Wissenschaft bei Hermann Cohen. Springer. pp. 101 - 133.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Von Marburg nach Pittsburgh: Philosophie als Transzendentalphilosophie.Ursula Renz - 2011 - Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 59 (2):249-270.
    The article reconstructs some of the basic decisions underlying Hermann Cohen′s theoretical philosophy by drawing a line to some claims of Winfrid Sellars′ and to one aspect of Robert Brandom′s philosophy. The first part is concerned with a comparison of the main theses of Cohen′s book Kants Theorie der Erfahrung and Sellars′ early essay entitled “Some remarks on Kant′s Theory of Experience,” both authors reading the Critique of Pure Reason as the discovery of a new, holistic concept of experience. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hermann Cohen.Scott Edgar - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Kant.Eric Watkins - 2009 - In Helen Beebee, Christopher Hitchcock & Peter Menzies (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Causation. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Die Ding-an-sich-Theorie Hermann Cohens.Wolfgang Ritzel - 1951 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 6 (3):426 - 434.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hermann Cohen und die Erneuerung der Kantischen Philosophie.Ernst Cassirer - 1912 - Société Française de Philosophie, Bulletin 17:252.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Interpreting Kant correctly: On the Kant of the neo-Kantians.Manfred Kühn - 2009 - In Rudolf A. Makkreel & Sebastian Luft (eds.), Neo-Kantianism in Contemporary Philosophy. Indiana University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations