Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Herophilus: The Art of Medicine in Early Alexandria.Heinrich von Staden - 1990 - Phronesis 35 (2):194-215.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristotle on pneuma and animal self-motion.Sylvia Berryman - 2002 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 23:85-97.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • (1 other version)Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind Still Credible? (A Draft).Myles Burnyeat - 1992 - In Martha Craven Nussbaum & Amélie Rorty (eds.), Essays on Aristotle's De anima. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 15-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Aristotle and the atomists on motion in a void.David J. Furley - 1976 - In Peter K. Machamer & Robert G. Turnbull (eds.), Motion and Time, Space and Matter. Ohio State University Press. pp. 83--100.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Aristotle on teleology.Monte Ransome Johnson - 2005 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Monte Johnson examines one of the most controversial aspects of Aristiotle's natural philosophy: his teleology. Is teleology about causation or explanation? Does it exclude or obviate mechanism, determinism, or materialism? Is it focused on the good of individual organisms, or is god or man the ultimate end of all processes and entities? Is teleology restricted to living things, or does it apply to the cosmos as a whole? Does it identify objectively existent causes in the world, or is it merely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • (1 other version)Cause and explanation in ancient Greek thought.R. J. Hankinson - 1998 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    R. J. Hankinson traces the history of ancient Greek thinking about causation and explanation, from its earliest beginnings through more than a thousand years to the middle of the first millennium of the Christian era. He examines ways in which the Ancient Greeks dealt with questions about how and why things happen as and when they do, about the basic constitution and structure of things, about function and purpose, laws of nature, chance, coincidence, and responsibility.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Embryological models in ancient philosophy.Devin Henry - 2005 - Phronesis 50 (1):1 - 42.
    Historically embryogenesis has been among the most philosophically intriguing phenomena. In this paper I focus on one aspect of biological development that was particularly perplexing to the ancients: self-organisation. For many ancients, the fact that an organism determines the important features of its own development required a special model for understanding how this was possible. This was especially true for Aristotle, Alexander, and Simplicius, who all looked to contemporary technology to supply that model. However, they did not all agree on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Aristotle's De motu animalium.Martha Craven Nussbaum - 1978 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 43 (2):378-378.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • Galen's criticism of Aristotle's conception theory.Anthony Preus - 1977 - Journal of the History of Biology 10 (1):65-85.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Conception of Final Causality.Allan Gotthelf - 1976 - Review of Metaphysics 30 (2):226 - 254.
    What precisely does aristotle mean when he asserts that something is (or comes to be) "for" "the" "sake" "of" something? I suggest that the answer to this question may be found by examining aristotle's position on the problem of reduction in biology, As it arises within his own scientific "and" "philosophical" context. I discuss the role of the concepts of "nature" and "potential" in aristotelian scientific explanation, And reformulate the reduction problem in that light. I answer the main question by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Necessity, Cause, and Blame: Perspectives on Aristotle’s Theory.Richard Sorabji - 1980 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    A discussion of Aristotle’s thought on determinism and culpability, Necessity, Cause, and Blame also reveals Richard Sorabji’s own philosophical commitments. He makes the original argument here that Aristotle separates the notions of necessity and cause, rejecting both the idea that all events are necessarily determined as well as the idea that a non-necessitated event must also be non-caused. In support of this argument, Sorabji engages in a wide-ranging discussion of explanation, time, free will, essence, and purpose in nature. He also (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Herophilus: The Art of Medicine in Early Alexandria: Edition, Translation and Essays.Heinrich von Staden (ed.) - 1989 - Cambridge University Press.
    Herophilus, a contemporary of Euclid, practiced medicine in Alexandria in the third century B.C., and seems to have been the first Western scientist to dissect the human body. He made especially impressive contributions to many branches of anatomy and also developed influential views on many other aspects of medicine. Von Staden assembles the fragmentary evidence concerning one of the more important scientists of ancient Greece. Part 1 of the book presents the Greek and Latin texts accompanied by English translation and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought.R. J. Hankinson - 1998 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    'A fascinating book. It contains a sweeping survey of approaches to causation and explanation from the Presocratic philosophers to the Neo-platonist philosophers. Hankinson pays a visit to every major figure and movement in between: the sophists, Plato, Aristotle, the Stoics, the Sceptics, the Epicureans and a variety of medical writers, early and late... impressive... Hankinson's observations are regularly intriguing, at times refreshingly trenchant, and in some cases straightforwardly arresting... the history itself is excellent: clear, intelligently conceived and executed, and broadly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • War Demokrits Weltbild mechanistisch und antiteleologisch?Ulrike Hirsch - 1990 - Phronesis 35 (1):225-244.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Ancient Automata and Mechanical Explanation.Sylvia Berryman - 2003 - Phronesis 48 (4):344 - 369.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The Presocratic Philosophers: A Critical History with a Selection of Texts.G. S. Kirk & J. E. Raven - 1983 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by J. E. Raven & Malcolm Schofield.
    This book traces the intellectual revolution initiated by Thales in the sixth century BC to its culmination in the metaphysics of Parmenides.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Science and philosophy in Aristotle'sGeneration of Animals.Anthony Preus - 1970 - Journal of the History of Biology 3 (1):1-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Aristotle's De Motu Animalium.D. W. Hamlyn - 1980 - Philosophical Quarterly 30 (120):246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • Greek Science and Mechanism I. Aristotle on Nature and Chance.D. M. Balme - 1939 - Classical Quarterly 33 (3-4):129-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Necessity, Cause and Blame: Perspectives on Aristotle's Theory.Richard Sorabji - 1981 - Philosophy 56 (218):584-585.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Explaining Various Forms of Living.Julius Moravcsik & Alan Code - 1992 - In Martha C. Nussbaum & Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (eds.), Essays on Aristotle's de Anima. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Aristotle did not see a sharp contrast between the psychological and the physical. He viewed the physical as just the natural, and treats the psychological as part of the physical. This essay attempts to explain why this is so, and presents observations about Aristotle’s framework. It explores the relation of hylomorphism to functionalism, and argues against funtionalist interpretations of Aristotle due to the belief that Aristotle was confronting a different set of concerns and issues.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Was Aristotle's biology sexist?Johannes Morsink - 1979 - Journal of the History of Biology 12 (1):83-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Galen and the Mechanical Philosophy.Sylvia Berryman - 2002 - Apeiron 35 (3):235 - 253.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • In defense of dispositions.D. H. Mellor - 1974 - Philosophical Review 83 (2):157-181.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   123 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristotelian Teleology.Lindsay Judson - 2005 - In David Sedley (ed.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Xxix: Winter 2005. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristotle's System of the Physical World. A comparison with his predecessors.Friedrich Solmsen - 1960 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 153:283-285.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Aristotle's System of the Physical World: A Comparison with His Predecessors.Friedrich Solmsen - 1970 - Cornell University Press.
    Examining in detail Aristotle's treatment of physical, cosmological, chemical, and meteorological questions, this learned study compares his arguments and conclusions with those of his precursors in order to assess his debt to them and at the same time to show clearly the nature of his own new contributions to the body of scientific thought. It also examines the interrelations of the major topics included in Aristotle's scientific work and the relations between his theology and his science. Describing his work as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Presocratic Philosophers.G. S. Kirk, J. E. Raven & M. Schofield - 1983 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (4):465-469.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Matters of Metaphysics.D. H. MELLOR - 1991 - Philosophy 67 (260):268-270.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Aristotle's System of the Physical World: A Comparison With His Predecessors. [REVIEW]John Herman Randall - 1962 - Philosophical Review 71 (4):520-523.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristotelian teleology.Lindsay Judson - 2005 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 29:341-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The warrant of induction.D. H. Mellor - 1988 - In Matters of Metaphysics. New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Aristotle on Hypothetical Necessity and Irreducibility.David Charles - 1988 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 69 (1):1.
    What is the role of "teleological explanation" in aristotle's account of psychological and biological phenomena? this paper argues that it provides a way of understanding these phenomena which is not reducible to purely material explanation, And which allows for the possibility of a full material account of the conditions under which these phenomena occur. It also offers an alternative account of hypothetical necessity to that proposed by john cooper.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • The Metaphysical Science of Aristotle's Generation of Animals and Its Feminist Critics.Daryl McGowan Tress - 1992 - Review of Metaphysics 46 (2):307 - 341.
    HOW DOES LIFE BEGIN? How is it and why is it that a child comes into being? To answer these questions about life and its origins requires a system of presuppositions about a great many metaphysical matters, such as causation and its modes of operation, relations of identity and difference, and, perhaps above all, the transition from not-being to actualized existence. In his treatise, Generation of Animals, Aristotle takes up the theme of the origins of animal and human life. His (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Aristotle's De Motu Animalium.Martha Craven Nussbaum - 1978 - Journal of the History of Biology 13 (2):351-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Matters of Metaphysics.D. H. MELLOR - 1992 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 43 (4):555-559.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Necessity, Cause, and Blame: Perspectives on Aristotle's Theory by Richard Sorabji. [REVIEW]Gareth B. Matthews - 1983 - Noûs 17 (1):135-138.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Teleological Notions.Monte Ransome Johnson - 2005 - In Aristotle on teleology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    The key term of Aristotle’s teleology is “the cause for the sake of which”. Aristotle discusses in several key texts the fact that this has two different senses: aim and beneficiary. The aim of a knife is cutting, but the beneficiary is the person who does, or orders, the cutting. Aristotle uses this distinction to show how natural things have both aims and are beneficiaries of their functions. He also shows how non-natural things, such as god, can operate as causes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Four Causes in Aristotle's Embryology.Mohan Matthen - 1989 - Apeiron 22 (4):159 - 179.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations