Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Cladistic classification and functional explanation.P. E. Griffiths - 1994 - Philosophy of Science 61 (2):206-227.
    I adopt a cladistic view of species, and explore the possibility that there exists an equally valuable cladistic view of organismic traits. This suggestion seems to run counter to the stress on functional views of biological traits in recent work in philosophy and psychology. I show how the tension between these two views can be defused with a multilevel view of biological explanation. Despite the attractions of this compromise, I conclude that we must reject it, and adopt an essentially cladistic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • The scientist as child.Alison Gopnik - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (4):485-514.
    This paper argues that there are powerful similarities between cognitive development in children and scientific theory change. These similarities are best explained by postulating an underlying abstract set of rules and representations that underwrite both types of cognitive abilities. In fact, science may be successful largely because it exploits powerful and flexible cognitive devices that were designed by evolution to facilitate learning in young children. Both science and cognitive development involve abstract, coherent systems of entities and rules, theories. In both (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Reduction by molecular genetics.William K. Goosens - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (1):73-95.
    Taking reduction in the traditional deductive sense, the programmatic claim that most of genetics can be reduced by molecular genetics is defended as feasible and significant. Arguments by Ruse and Hull that either the relationship is replacement or at best a weaker form of reduction are shown to rest on a mixture of historical and logical confusions about the nature of the theories involved.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Homology and a generative theory of biological form.Brian Goodwin - 1993 - Acta Biotheoretica 41 (4):305-314.
    Homology continues to be a concept of central importance in the study of phylogenetic relations, but its relation to ontogenetic processes remains problematical. A definition of homology in terms of equivalent morphogenetic processes is defined and applied to the comparative study of tetrapod limbs. This allows for a consistent treatment of relations of similarity and difference of appendage structure in vertebrates, and the distinction between fishes fins and tetrapod limbs in terms of the concept of equivalence is described. The role (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Using relations within conceptual systems to translate across conceptual systems.R. Goldstone - 2002 - Cognition 84 (3):295-320.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The Material Basis of Evolution.Richard Goldschmidt - 1941 - Philosophy of Science 8 (3):394-395.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • A mobility gradient in the organization of vertebrate movement: The perception of movement through symbolic language.Ilan Golani - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):249-266.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Information, arbitrariness, and selection: Comments on Maynard Smith.Peter Godfrey-Smith - 2000 - Philosophy of Science 67 (2):202-207.
    Maynard Smith is right that one of the most striking features of contemporary biology is the ever-increasing prominence of the concept of information, along with related concepts like representation, programming, and coding. Maynard Smith is also right that this is surely a phenomenon which philosophers of science should examine closely. We should try to understand exactly what sorts of theoretical commitment are made when biological systems are described in these terms, and what connection there is between semantic descriptions in biology (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Mechanisms and the nature of causation.Stuart S. Glennan - 1996 - Erkenntnis 44 (1):49--71.
    In this paper I offer an analysis of causation based upon a theory of mechanisms-complex systems whose internal parts interact to produce a system's external behavior. I argue that all but the fundamental laws of physics can be explained by reference to mechanisms. Mechanisms provide an epistemologically unproblematic way to explain the necessity which is often taken to distinguish laws from other generalizations. This account of necessity leads to a theory of causation according to which events are causally related when (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   435 citations  
  • Evo-devo, devo-evo, and devgen-popgen.Scott F. Gilbert - 2003 - Biology and Philosophy 18 (2):347-352.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • The scientist as adult.Ronald N. Giere - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (4):538-541.
    My concern is with the possible implications of research in developmental psychology for understanding the workings of modern science. I agree both with Gopnik's general naturalistic orientation and with her more specific claims about scientists as cognitive agents. Neither the formal structure of propositions nor the social structure of scientific communities provides sufficient resources for the understanding we seek. So I agree that the empirical study of human cognition is not only relevant, but necessary, for understanding how science works.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Species concepts, individuality, and objectivity.Michael Ghiselin - 1987 - Biology and Philosophy 2 (2):127-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • Insides and Essences: Early Understandings of the Non- Obvious.Susan A. Gelman & Henry M. Wellman - 1991 - Cognition 38 (3):213-244.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   180 citations  
  • Categories and induction in young children.Susan A. Gelman & Ellen M. Markman - 1986 - Cognition 23 (3):183-209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   219 citations  
  • How to be an anti-reductionist about developmental biology: Response to Laubichler and Wagner.Greg Frost-Arnold - 2004 - Biology and Philosophy 19 (1):75-91.
    Alexander Rosenberg recently claimed (1997) that developmental biology is currently being reduced to molecular biology. cite several concrete biological examples that are intended to impugn Rosenberg's claim. I first argue that although Laubichler and Wagner's examples would refute a very strong reductionism, a more moderate reductionism would escape their attacks. Next, taking my cue from the antireductionist's perennial stress on the importance of spatial organization, I describe one form an empirical finding that refutes this moderate reductionism would take. Finally, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Conceptual change and reference.Dagfinn Follesdal - 1997 - In Christoph Hubig (ed.), Cognitio Humana - Dynamik des Wissens Und der Werte: Xvii. Deutscher Kongreß Für Philosophie Leipzig 23.–27. September 1996, Kongreßband: Vorträge Und Kolloquien. De Gruyter. pp. 351-367.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Elm and the Expert: Mentalese and Its Semantics.Jerry A. Fodor - 1994 - MIT Press.
    This book is largely a reconsideration of the arguments that are supposed to ground this consensus.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   251 citations  
  • The Elm and the Expert: Mentalese and Its Semantics. [REVIEW]Samuel Guttenplan - 1995 - Philosophy 70 (272):293-298.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Replies to critics.Jerry A. Fodor - 2000 - Mind and Language 15 (2-3):350-374.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Reply to Critics.Jerry Fodor - 1993 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (3):673-682.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • There are no recognitional concepts, not even RED.Jerry Fodor - 1998 - Philosophical Issues 9:1-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Holism: A Consumer Update.Jerry Fodor - 1993 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 46:303-322.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Language, Thought and Compositionality.Jerry A. Fodor - 2002 - Mind and Language 16 (1):1-15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Having concepts: A brief refutation of the twentieth century.Jerry Fodor - 2004 - Mind and Language 19 (1):29-47.
    A certain ‘pragmatist’ view of concept possession has defined the mainstream of Anglophone philosophy of language/mind for decades: namely, that to have the concept C is to be able to distinguish Cs from non‐Cs, and/or to recognize the validity of certain C‐involving inferences. The present paper offers three arguments why no such account could be viable. An alternative ‘Cartesian’ view is outlined, according to which having C is being able to think about Cs ‘as such’. Some consequences of the proposed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Language, thought and compositionality.Jerry A. Fodor - 2001 - Mind and Language 16 (1):1-15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Language, Thought and Compositionality.Jerry Fodor - 2001 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 48:227-242.
    Consider the task under which I labour: These are supposed to be talks in the millennial spirit. My charge is to find, somewhere in the philosophical landscape, a problem of whose current status I can give some coherent account, and to point the direction in which it seems to me that further research might usefully proceed, And I'm to try to sound reasonably cheerful and optimistic in the course of doing so. No sooner did I begin to ponder these terms (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong.Jerry A. Fodor - 1998 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    The renowned philosopher Jerry Fodor, a leading figure in the study of the mind for more than twenty years, presents a strikingly original theory on the basic constituents of thought. He suggests that the heart of cognitive science is its theory of concepts, and that cognitive scientists have gone badly wrong in many areas because their assumptions about concepts have been mistaken. Fodor argues compellingly for an atomistic theory of concepts, deals out witty and pugnacious demolitions of rival theories, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   616 citations  
  • Science as child's play: Tales from the crib.Arthur Fine - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (4):534-37.
    Child's play? Certainly Alison Gopnik is in good company in pointing to connections between science and child development. To mention just a few luminaries: in psychology, Freud looked at the developmental connection between children's play and adult work; in philosophy, Thomas Reid may have been the first to ground the faculty of reasoning in developmental stages that “unfold themselves by degrees; so that it [the child] is inspired with the various principles of common sense”. As for connecting commonsense reasoning and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Logic, Meaning, and Conceptual Role.Hartry H. Field - 1977 - Journal of Philosophy 74 (7):378-409.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   183 citations  
  • How to compare theories: Reference and change.Arthur Fine - 1975 - Noûs 9 (1):17-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Theory change and the indeterminacy of reference.Hartry Field - 1973 - Journal of Philosophy 70 (14):462-481.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   224 citations  
  • On the "meaning" of scientific terms.Paul K. Feyerabend - 1965 - Journal of Philosophy 62 (10):266-274.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • What is a Gene?Raphael Falk - 1986 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 17 (2):133.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Species pluralism and anti-realism.Marc Ereshefsky - 1998 - Philosophy of Science 65 (1):103-120.
    Species pluralism gives us reason to doubt the existence of the species category. The problem is not that species concepts are chosen according to our interests or that pluralism and the desire for hierarchical classifications are incompatible. The problem is that the various taxa we call 'species' lack a common unifying feature.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • Reference of theoretical terms.Berent Enç - 1976 - Noûs 10 (3):261-282.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Realism, naturalism, and culturally generated kinds.Crawford L. Elder - 1989 - Philosophical Quarterly 39 (157):425-444.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Michael Dummett, Frege: Philosophy of Language. [REVIEW]Hidé Ishiguro - 1974 - Philosophy 49 (190):438-442.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   506 citations  
  • Holism, language acquisition, and algebraic logic.Eli Dresner - 2002 - Linguistics and Philosophy 25 (4):419-452.
    In the first section of this paper I present a well known objection to meaning holism, according to which holism is inconsistent with natural language being learnable. Then I show that the objection fails if language acquisition includes stages of partial grasp of the meaning of at least some expressions, and I argue that standard model theoretic semantics cannot fully capture such stages. In the second section the above claims are supported through a review of current research into language acquisition. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Can scientific development and children's cognitive development be the same process?Stephen M. Downes - 1999 - Philosophy of Science 66 (4):565-578.
    In this paper I assess Gopnik and Meltzoff's developmental psychology of science as a contribution to the understanding of scientific development. I focus on two specific aspects of Gopnik and Meltzoff's approach: the relation between their views and recapitulationist views of ontogeny and phylogeny in biology, and their overall conception of cognition as a set of veridical processes. First, I discuss several issues that arise from their appeal to evolutionary biology, focusing specifically on the role of distinctions between ontogeny and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Reference and definite descriptions.Keith S. Donnellan - 1966 - Philosophical Review 75 (3):281-304.
    Definite descriptions, I shall argue, have two possible functions. 1] They are used to refer to what a speaker wishes to talk about, but they are also used quite differently. Moreover, a definite description occurring in one and the same sentence may, on different occasions of its use, function in either way. The failure to deal with this duality of function obscures the genuine referring use of definite descriptions. The best known theories of definite descriptions, those of Russell and Strawson, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   747 citations  
  • Proper names and identifying descriptions.Keith S. Donnellan - 1970 - Synthese 21 (3-4):335 - 358.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   205 citations  
  • Identity and natural kinds.Frederick Doepke - 1992 - Philosophical Quarterly 42 (166):89-94.
    That no member of a natural kind can switch kinds is a consequence of David Wiggins’ view that the identity conditions for such things are given by the natural kind itself. If dog is a natural kind, then dogs must be dogs and one dog cannot ‘turn into’ something else, say, by gradually ‘becoming’ a mass of tissue (as Marjorie Price had held). Were such a transition to involve the persistence of the same thing, then the thing in question would (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Localism and analyticity.Michael Devitt - 1993 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (3):641-646.
    In their discussion of semantic holism, Fodor and Lepore claim that Quine showed that any inferential properties constituting a meaning cannot be distinguished on epistemic grounds like apriority. But they often write as if Quine showed that such properties cannot be distinguished at all. The paper argues that Quine did not show the latter. It goes on to propose a criterion for distinguishing the constitutive properties: they are the ones that determine reference. Fodor is not in a position to reject (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A critique of the case for semantic holism.Michael Devitt - 1993 - Philosophical Perspectives 7:281-306.
    At its most extreme, semantic holism is the doctrine that all the inferential properties of an expression constitute its meaning. Holism is supported by the consideration that there is no principled basis for localism's distinction among these properties. The paper rejects four arguments for this. (1) The argument from confirmation holism is dismissed quickly because it rests on verificationism. (2) The argument from the rejection of analyticity fails because it saddles the localist with unacceptable epistemic assumptions. Localism is not committed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A Critique of the Case for Semantic Holism.Michael Devitt - 1993 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 46 (1):17-60.
    At its most extreme, semantic holism is the doctrine that all the inferential properties of an expression constitute its meaning. Holism is supported by the consideration that there is no principled basis for localism's distinction among these properties. The paper rejects four arguments for this. (1) The argument from confirmation holism is dismissed quickly because it rests on verificationism. (2) The argument from the rejection of analyticity fails because it saddles the localist with unacceptable epistemic assumptions. Localism is not committed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Natural Shiftiness of Natural Kinds.Ronald de Sousa - 1984 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14 (4):561-580.
    The Philosophical search for Natural Kinds is motivated by the hope of finding ontological categories that are independent of our interests. Other requirements, of varying importance, are commonly made of kinds that claim to be natural. But no such categories are to be found. Virtually any kind can be termed ‘natural’ relative to some set of interests and epistemic priorities. Science determines those priorities at any particular stage of its progress, and what kinds are most ‘natural’ in that sense is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The Changing Role of the Embryo in Evolutionary Thought: Roots of Evo-Devo.Ron Amundson - 2005 - Cambridge University Press.
    In this book Ron Amundson examines two hundred years of scientific views on the evolution-development relationship from the perspective of evolutionary developmental biology. This perspective challenges several popular views about the history of evolutionary thought by claiming that many earlier authors had made history come out right for the Evolutionary Synthesis. The book starts with a revised history of nineteenth-century evolutionary thought. It then investigates how development became irrelevant with the Evolutionary Synthesis. It concludes with an examination of the contrasts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   156 citations  
  • Classification, Evolution, and the Nature of Biology.Alec L. Panchen - 1992 - Cambridge University Press.
    Historically, naturalists who propose theories of evolution, including Darwin and Wallace, have done so in order to explain the apparent relationship of natural classification. This book begins by exploring the intimate historical relationship between patterns of classification and patterns of phylogeny. It is a circular argument, however, to use the data for classification and the concept of homology as evidence for evolution, when evolution is the theory explaining the phenomenon of natural classification. Alec Panchen presents other evidence for evolution in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Representing and Intervening.Ian Hacking - 1983 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 35 (4):381-390.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   759 citations  
  • The Rationality of Science.W. Newton-Smith - 1981 - Boston: Routledge.
    First published in 2002. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor & Francis, an informa company.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   198 citations