Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)The conventionality of simultaneity in the light of the spinor representation of the lorentz group.Vassilios Karakostas - 1997 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 28 (2):249-276.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Coordinate-Independent 2-Component Spinor Formalism and the Conventionality of Simultaneity.Jonathan Bain - 2000 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 31 (2):201-226.
    In recent articles, Zangari (1994) and Karakostas (1997) observe that while an &unknown;-extended version of the proper orthochronous Lorentz group O + (1,3) exists for values of &unknown; not equal to zero, no similar &unknown;-extended version of its double covering group SL(2, C) exists (where &unknown;=1-2&unknown; R , with &unknown; R the non-standard simultaneity parameter of Reichenbach). Thus, they maintain, since SL(2, C) is essential in describing the rotational behaviour of half-integer spin fields, and since there is empirical evidence for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Two Challenges to the Requirement of Substantive General Covariance.J. Earman - 2006 - Synthese 148 (2):443-468.
    It is generally acknowledged that the requirement that the laws of a spacetime theory be covariant under a general coordinate transformation is a restriction on the form but not the content of the theory. The prevalent view in the physics community holds that the substantive version of general covariance – exhibited, for example, by Einstein’s general theory of relativity – consists in the requirement that diffeomorphism invariance is a gauge symmetry of the theory. This conception of general covariance is explained (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Null Cones and Einstein's Equations in Minkowski Spacetime.J. Brian Pitts & W. C. Schieve - 2004 - Foundations of Physics 34 (2):211-238.
    If Einstein's equations are to describe a field theory of gravity in Minkowski spacetime, then causality requires that the effective curved metric must respect the flat background metric's null cone. The kinematical problem is solved using a generalized eigenvector formalism based on the Segré classification of symmetric rank 2 tensors with respect to a Lorentzian metric. Securing the correct relationship between the two null cones dynamically plausibly is achieved using the naive gauge freedom. New variables tied to the generalized eigenvector (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • (1 other version)A Suggested Interpretation of the Quantum Theory in Terms of ‘Hidden’ Variables, I and II.David Bohm - 1952 - Physical Review (85):166-193.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   315 citations  
  • Empirical equivalence, artificial gauge freedom and a generalized kretschmann objection.J. Brian Pitts - unknown
    Einstein considered general covariance to characterize the novelty of his General Theory of Relativity (GTR), but Kretschmann thought it merely a formal feature that any theory could have. The claim that GTR is ``already parametrized'' suggests analyzing substantive general covariance as formal general covariance achieved without hiding preferred coordinates as scalar ``clock fields,'' much as Einstein construed general covariance as the lack of preferred coordinates. Physicists often install gauge symmetries artificially with additional fields, as in the transition from Proca's to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Gauge-invariant localization of infinitely many gravitational energies from all possible auxiliary structures.J. Brian Pitts - unknown
    The problem of finding a covariant expression for the distribution and conservation of gravitational energy-momentum dates to the 1910s. A suitably covariant infinite-component localization is displayed, reflecting Bergmann's realization that there are infinitely many gravitational energy-momenta. Initially use is made of a flat background metric (or rather, all of them) or connection, because the desired gauge invariance properties are obvious. Partial gauge-fixing then yields an appropriate covariant quantity without any background metric or connection; one version is the collection of pseudotensors (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • A new twist in the conventionality of simultaneity debate.Mark Zangari - 1994 - Philosophy of Science 61 (2):267-275.
    To date, both sides in the conventionality of simultaneity debate grant that transformations from "standard" to "nonstandard" coordinates are possible without any empirically significant effects. However, it is argued here that the very possibility of defining nonstandard coordinates vanishes if one represents special relativity, not by real four-vectors (as has been the case so far in the debate), but by complex spinors as used in the representation of half-integer spin. Thus, in the topologically simplest representation of the Lorentz group, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Probability kinematics and commutativity.Carl G. Wagner - 2002 - Philosophy of Science 69 (2):266-278.
    The so-called "non-commutativity" of probability kinematics has caused much unjustified concern. When identical learning is properly represented, namely, by identical Bayes factors rather than identical posterior probabilities, then sequential probability-kinematical revisions behave just as they should. Our analysis is based on a variant of Field's reformulation of probability kinematics, divested of its (inessential) physicalist gloss.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Slightly more realistic personal probability.Ian Hacking - 1967 - Philosophy of Science 34 (4):311-325.
    A person required to risk money on a remote digit of π would, in order to comply fully with the theory [of personal probability] have to compute that digit, though this would really be wasteful if the cost of computation were more than the prize involved. For the postulates of the theory imply that you should behave in accordance with the logical implications of all that you know. Is it possible to improve the theory in this respect, making allowance within (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  • The epistemology of geometry.Clark Glymour - 1977 - Noûs 11 (3):227-251.
    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of J STOR’s Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. J STOR’s Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non—commercial use.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Philosophie der Raum-Zeit-Lehre. [REVIEW]F. S. C. Northrop - 1931 - Philosophical Review 40 (3):281-285.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Foundations and current problems of general relativity (notes by graham dixon, petros florides and gerald lemmer).Andrzej Trautman - 1965 - In A. Trautman (ed.), Lectures on general relativity. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.,: Prentice-Hall. pp. 1--1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Bayesianism in mathematics.David Corfield - 2001 - In David Corfield & Jon Williamson (eds.), Foundations of Bayesianism. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 175--201.
    A study of the possibility of casting plausible matheamtical inference in Bayesian terms.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • World spinors—Construction and some applications.Yuval Ne'eman & Djordje Šijački - 1997 - Foundations of Physics 27 (8):1105-1122.
    The existence of a topological double-covering for the GL(n, R) and diffeomorphism groups is reviewed. These groups do not have finite-dimensional faithful representations. An explicit construction and the classification of all\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document} $$\overline {SL} $$ \end{document}(n, R), n=3,4 unitary irreducible representations is presented. Infinite-component spinorial and tensorial\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document} $$\overline {SL} $$ \end{document} fields, “manifields”, are introduced. Particle content of the ladder manifields, as given by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On empirically equivalent systems of the world.Willard van Orman Quine - 1975 - Erkenntnis 9 (3):313-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   278 citations  
  • The meaning of general covariance.John Stachel - 1993 - In John Earman (ed.), Philosophical Problems of the Internal and External World. University of Pittsburgh Press. pp. 129--60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Causal theories of time and the conventionality of simultaneity.David Malament - 1977 - Noûs 11 (3):293-300.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  • Relativistic quantum mechanics and the conventionality of simultaneity.David Gunn & Indrakumar Vetharaniam - 1995 - Philosophy of Science 62 (4):599-608.
    1. Introduction Dirac's theory of the electron was the first widely accepted relativistic quantum theory, and it later provided the basis for constructing the modern electromagnetic theory of quantum electrodynamics. Whereas Dirac's theory in its simplest form describes relativistic freely-propagating massive non-chiral particles of spin-½, QED describes how such particles interact with one another electromagnetically, via a dynamical quantum field.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Is General Relativity Generally Relativistic?Roger Jones - 1980 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1980:363 - 381.
    Among the principles that are generally taken to underlie the general theory of relativity is a general principle of relativity. Such a principle is supposed to extend the special principle of relativity, which holds observers in uniform motion to be indistinguishable by appeal to the laws of physics, to a requirement on observers in arbitrary states of motion. Starting with physical intuitions described graphically by Galileo, proceeding through a series of formal requirements on reference frames defined on models of space-time (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (1 other version)History of science and its rational reconstructions.Imre Lakatos - 1971 - In R. C. Buck & R. S. Cohen (eds.), Psa 1970. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science Viii. D. Reidel. pp. 91-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   212 citations  
  • Some remarks on the notions of general covariance and background independence.Domenico Giulini - 2007 - Lecture Notes in Physics 721:105--20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • (1 other version)General covariance, gauge theories and the kretschmann objection.John D. Norton - 2002 - In Katherine Brading & Elena Castellani (eds.), Symmetries in Physics: Philosophical Reflections. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 110--123.
    How can we reconcile two claims that are now both widely accepted: Kretschmann's claim that a requirement of general covariance is physically vacuous and the standard view that the general covariance of general relativity expresses the physically important diffeomorphism gauge freedom of general relativity? I urge that both claims can be held without contradiction if we attend to the context in which each is made.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Absolute objects and counterexamples: Jones--Geroch dust, Torretti constant curvature, tetrad-spinor, and scalar density.J. Brian Pitts - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 37:347-71.
    James L. Anderson analyzed the novelty of Einstein's theory of gravity as its lack of "absolute objects." Michael Friedman's related work has been criticized by Roger Jones and Robert Geroch for implausibly admitting as absolute the timelike 4-velocity field of dust in cosmological models in Einstein's theory. Using the Rosen-Sorkin Lagrange multiplier trick, I complete Anna Maidens's argument that the problem is not solved by prohibiting variation of absolute objects in an action principle. Recalling Anderson's proscription of "irrelevant" variables, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • (1 other version)Jeffrey C. Alexander; Rodney Benson; Bruce G. Carruthers; Jeffrey K. Hass; John Levi Martin; Philip Smith; Arthur L. Stinchcombe. [REVIEW][author unknown] - 2004 - Theory and Society 28 (3):499-500.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation