Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Faraday to Einstein: constructing meaning in scientific theories.Nancy J. Nersessian - 1984 - Hingham, MA: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    PARTI The Philosophical Situation: A Critical Appraisal We must begin with the mistake and find out the truth in it. That is, we must uncover the source of ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • The concept of identity.Eli Hirsch - 1982 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this book, Eli Hirsch focuses on identity through time, first with respect to ordinary bodies, then underlying matter, and eventually persons.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   124 citations  
  • The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1962 - Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Edited by Ian Hacking.
    Thomas S. Kuhn's classic book is now available with a new index.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4761 citations  
  • Copernicus, the orbs, and the equant.Peter Barker - 1990 - Synthese 83 (2):317 - 323.
    I argue that Copernicus accepted the reality of celestial spheres on the grounds that the equant problem is unintelligible except as a problem about real spheres. The same considerations point to a number of generally unnoticed liabilities of Copernican astronomy, especially gaps between the spheres, and the failure of some spheres to obey the principle that their natural motion is to rotate. These difficulties may be additional reasons for Copernicus's reluctance to publish, and also stand in the way of strict (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Realism and instrumentalism in sixteenth century astronomy: A reappraisal.Peter Barker & Bernard R. Goldstein - 1998 - Perspectives on Science 6 (3):232-258.
    : We question the claim, common since Duhem, that sixteenth century astronomy, and especially the Wittenberg interpretation of Copernicus, was instrumentalistic rather than realistic. We identify a previously unrecognized Wittenberg astronomer, Edo Hildericus (Hilderich von Varel), who presents a detailed exposition of Copernicus's cosmology that is incompatible with instrumentalism. Quotations from other sixteenth century astronomers show that knowledge of the real configuration of the heavens was unattainable practically, rather than in principle. Astronomy was limited to quia demonstrations, although demonstration propter (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Conceptual Revolutions.Paul Thagard - 1992 - Princeton: Princeton University Press.
    In this path-breaking work, Paul Thagard draws on history and philosophy of science, cognitive psychology, and the field of artificial intelligence to develop a ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   278 citations  
  • Conceptual Change within and across Ontological Categories: Examples from Learning and Discovery in Science.Michelene Chi - 1992 - In R. Giere & H. Feigl (eds.), Cognitive Models of Science. University of Minnesota Press. pp. 129-186.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Object permanence in five-month-old infants.Elizabeth S. Spelke - 1985 - Cognition 20 (3):191-208.
    A new method was devised to test object permanence in young infants. Fivemonth-old infants were habituated to a screen that moved back and forth through a 180-degree arc, in the manner of a drawbridge. After infants reached habituation, a box was centered behind the screen. Infants were shown two test events: a possible event and an impossible event. In the possible event, the screen stopped when it reached the occluded box; in the impossible event, the screen moved through the space (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  • Kepler's move from.Bernard R. Goldstein & Giora Hon - 2005 - Perspectives on Science 13 (1):74-111.
    : This study of the concept of orbit is intended to throw light on the nature of revolutionary concepts in science. We observe that Kepler transformed theoretical astronomy that was understood in terms of orbs [Latin: orbes] (spherical shells to which the planets were attached) and models (called hypotheses at the time), by introducing a single term, orbit [Latin: orbita], that is, the path of a planet in space resulting from the action of physical causes expressed in laws of nature. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Road since Structure.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1990 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990:3-13.
    A highly condensed account of the author's present view of some philosophical problems unresolved in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. The concept of incommensurability, now considerably developed, remains at center stage, but the evolutionary metaphor, introduced in the final pages of the book, now also plays a principal role.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   195 citations  
  • The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.David Bohm - 1964 - Philosophical Quarterly 14 (57):377-379.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1157 citations  
  • Faraday to Einstein: Constructing Meaning in Scientific Theories. Nancy J. Nersessian. [REVIEW]Patrick Enfield - 1985 - Philosophy of Science 52 (4):641-642.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • How to build a baby: II. Conceptual primitives.Jean M. Mandler - 1992 - Psychological Review 99 (4):587-604.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   153 citations  
  • The Copernican Achievement. [REVIEW]R. S. Westman - 1978 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 29 (4):395-397.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • [Book Chapter].P. Thagard & C. P. Shelley - 1997
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   205 citations  
  • Science and Core Knowledge.Susan Carey & Elizabeth Spelke - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (4):515 - 533.
    While endorsing Gopnik's proposal that studies of the emergence and modification of scientific theories and studies of cognitive development in children are mutually illuminating, we offer a different picture of the beginning points of cognitive development from Gopnik's picture of "theories all the way down." Human infants are endowed with several distinct core systems of knowledge which are theory-like in some, but not all, important ways. The existence of these core systems of knowledge has implications for the joint research program (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Why did John Herschel fail to understand polarization? The differences between object and event concepts.Xiang Chen - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (3):491-513.
    This paper offers a solution to a problem in Herschel studies by drawing on the dynamic frame model for concept representation offered by cognitive psychology. Applying the frame model to represent the conceptual frameworks of the particle and wave theories, this paper shows that discontinuity between the particle and wave frameworks consists mainly in the transition from a particle notion ‘side’ to a wave notion ‘phase difference’. By illustrating intraconceptual relations within concepts, the frame representations reveal the ontological differences between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Events and objects in space and time.P. Hacker - 1982 - Mind 91 (361):1-19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • The Concept of Identity.Andrew Brennan - 1984 - Noûs 18 (3):541-548.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Commensurability, communicability, comparability.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1983 - In P. D. Asquith & T. Nickles (eds.), Psa 1982. Philosophy of Science Association. pp. 669-88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • The road since structure.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1991 - In A. Fine, M. Forbes & L. Wessels (eds.), Psa 1990. Philosophy of Science Association. pp. 3-13.
    A highly condensed account of the author's present view of some philosophical problems unresolved in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. The concept of incommensurability, now considerably developed, remains at center stage, but the evolutionary metaphor, introduced in the final pages of the book, now also plays a principal role.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   170 citations  
  • Constructing copernicus.Peter Barker - 2002 - Perspectives on Science 10 (2):208-227.
    : This paper offers my current view of a joint research project, with Bernard R. Goldstein, that examines Kepler's unification of physics and astronomy. As an organizing theme, I describe the extent to which the work of Kepler led to the appearance of the form of Copernicanism that we accept today. In the half century before Kepler's career began, the understanding of Copernicus and his work was significantly different from the modern one. In successive sections I consider the modern conception (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Process Metaphysics. An Introduction to Process Philosophy.Nicholas Rescher - 1996 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 32 (4):689-697.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   111 citations  
  • Transforming temporal knowledge: Conceptual change between event concepts.Xiang Chen - 2005 - Perspectives on Science 13 (1):49-73.
    : This paper offers a preliminary analysis of conceptual change between event concepts. It begins with a brief review of the major findings of cognitive studies on event knowledge. The script model proposed by Schank and Abelson was the first attempt to represent event knowledge. Subsequent cognitive studies indicated that event knowledge is organized in the form of dimensional organizations in which temporally successive actions are related causally. This paper proposes a frame representation to capture and outline the internal structure (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Science as a Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social and Conceptual Development of Science. [REVIEW]Jane Maienschein - 1989 - Journal of the History of Biology 22 (3):507-509.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Predicability.Fred Sommers - 1964 - In Max Black (ed.), Philosophy in America. Ithaca: Routledge. pp. 262--281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Kepler's Move from Orbs to Orbits: Documenting a Revolutionary Scientific Concept.Bernard R. Goldstein & Giora Hon - 2005 - Perspectives on Science 13 (1):74-111.
    This study of the concept of orbit is intended to throw light on the nature of revolutionary concepts in science. We observe that Kepler transformed theoretical astronomy that was understood in terms of orbs [Latin: orbes] and models , by introducing a single term, orbit [Latin: orbita], that is, the path of a planet in space resulting from the action of physical causes expressed in laws of nature. To demonstrate the claim that orbit is a revolutionary concept we pursue three (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Concept of Identity.Harold W. Noonan - 1984 - Philosophical Quarterly 34 (135):175.
    In this book, Eli Hirsch focuses on identity through time, first with respect to ordinary bodies, then underlying matter, and eventually persons. These are linked at various points with other aspects of identity, such as the spatial unity of things, the unity of kinds, and the unity of groups. He investigates how our identity concept ordinarily operates in these respects. He also asks why this concept is so cental to our thinking and whether we can justify seeing the world in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Faraday to Einstein: Constructing Meaning in Scientific Theories.Nancy J. Nersessian - 1987 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (4):575-577.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • Process Metaphysics: An Introduction to Process Philosophy.Nicholas Rescher - 1996 - State University of New York Press.
    Presents a synoptic, compact, and accessible exposition of this influential and interesting sector of twentieth-century American philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • The representation of number in natural language syntax and in language of thought: A case study of the evolution and development of representational resources.Susan Carey - 2001 - In João Branquinho (ed.), The Foundations of Cognitive Science. Oxford University Press UK. pp. 23--53.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The ordinary language tree.Fred Sommers - 1959 - Mind 68 (270):160-185.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations