Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The importance of what we care about.Harry Frankfurt - 1982 - Synthese 53 (2):257-272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   573 citations  
  • Agents and their actions.Maria Alvarez & John Hyman - 1998 - Philosophy 73 (2):219-245.
    In the past thirty years or so, the doctrine that actions are events has become an essential, and sometimes unargued, part of the received view in the philosophy of action, despite the efforts of a few philosophers to undermine the consensus. For example, the entry for Agency in a recently published reference guide to the philosophy of mind begins with the following sentence: A central task in the philosophy of action is that of spelling out the differences between events in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • At one with our actions, but at two with our bodies: Hornsby's Account of Action.Adrian Haddock - 2005 - Philosophical Explorations 8 (2):157 – 172.
    Jennifer Hornsby's account of human action frees us from the temptation to think of the person who acts as 'doing' the events that are her actions, and thereby removes much of the allure of 'agent causation'. But her account is spoiled by the claim that physical actions are 'tryings' that cause bodily movements. It would be better to think of physical actions and bodily movements as identical; but Hornsby refuses to do this, seemingly because she thinks that to do so (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Actions are not events.Kent Bach - 1980 - Mind 89 (353):114-120.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • (1 other version)9 Agency and Alienation.Jennifer Hornsby - 2004 - In Mario De Caro & David Macarthur (eds.), Naturalism in Question. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. pp. 173-187.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Plato: Complete Works.J. Cooper & D. S. Hutchinson - 1998 - Phronesis 43 (2):197-206.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  • Actions.J. Hornsby - 1982 - Mind 91 (361):147-149.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  • Simple Mindedness: In Defense of Naive Naturalism in the Philosophy of Mind.</article-title>< cont. [REVIEW]Katalin Balog & Jennifer Hornsby - 1999 - Philosophical Review 108 (4):562-565.
    Hornsby is a defender of a position in the philosophy of mind she calls “naïve naturalism”. She argues that current discussions of the mind-body problem have been informed by an overly scientistic view of nature and a futile attempt by scientific naturalists to see mental processes as part of the physical universe. In her view, if naïve naturalism were adopted, the mind-body problem would disappear. I argue that her brand of anti-physicalist naturalism runs into difficulties with the problem of mental (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • (1 other version)Agency and Actions.Jennifer Hornsby - 2004 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 55:1-23.
    Among philosophical questions about human agency, one can distinguish in a rough and ready way between those that arise in philosophy of mind and those that arise in ethics. In philosophy of mind, one central aim has been to account for the place of agents in a world whose operations are supposedly ‘physical’. In ethics, one central aim has been to account for the connexion between ethical species of normativity and the distinctive deliberative and practical capacities of human beings. Ethics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • VIII*—An Ancient Principle about Causation.Stephen Makin - 1991 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91 (1):135-152.
    Stephen Makin; VIII*—An Ancient Principle about Causation, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 91, Issue 1, 1 June 1991, Pages 135–152, https://doi.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Aristotle's Definition of Change.James Kostman - 1987 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 4 (1):3 - 16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Aristotle's definition of motion.L. A. Kosman - 1969 - Phronesis 14 (1):40-62.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Platonic Causes.David Sedley - 1998 - Phronesis 43 (2):114-132.
    This paper examines Plato's ideas on cause-effect relations in the "Phaedo." It maintains that he sees causes as things (not events, states of affairs or the like), with any information as to how that thing brings about the effect relegated to a strictly secondary status. This is argued to make good sense, so long as we recognise that aition means the "thing responsible" and exploit legal analogies in order to understand what this amounts to. Furthermore, provided that we do not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Action, Emotion and Will.Anthony Kenny - 1963 - Philosophy 39 (149):277-278.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   256 citations  
  • Aristotle's Physics Books III and IV.Edward Hussey - 1984 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 35 (4):404-408.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Aristotle on Housebuilding.Robert Heinaman - 1985 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 2 (2):145 - 162.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Is Aristotle's Definition of Change Circular?Robert Heinaman - 1994 - Apeiron 27 (1):25 - 37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations