Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The principles of art.R. G. Collingwood - 1938 - New York,: Oxford University Press.
    This treatise on aesthetics criticizes various psychological theories of art, offers new theories and interpretations, and draws important inferences concerning ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  • The Principles of Art.R. G. Collingwood - 1938 - New York,: Oxford University Press USA.
    This treatise on aesthetics begins by showing that the word "art" is used as a name not only for "art proper" but also for certain things which are "art falsely so called." These are craft or skill, magic, and amusement, each of which, by confusion with art proper, generates a false aesthetic theory. In the course of attacking these theories the author criticizes various psychological theories of art, offers a new theory of magic, and reinterprets Plato's so-called "attack on art," (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • What the Body Told.Theodore Gracyk - 1996 - I.B. Tauris.
    What the Body Told is the second book of poetry from Rafael Campo, a practicing physician, a gay Cuban American, and winner of the National Poetry Series 1993 Open Competition. Exploring the themes began in his first book, The Other Man Was Me, Campo extends the search for identity into new realms of fantasy and physicality. He travels inwardly to the most intimate spaces of the imagination where sexuality and gender collide and where life crosses into death. Whether facing a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Art and its objects.Richard Wollheim - 1968 - New York,: Harper & Row.
    What defines a work of art and determines the way in which we respond to it?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Art and its Objects.Richard Wollheim - 1968 - Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Richard Thomas Eldridge.
    Richard Wollheim's classic reflection on art considers central questions regarding expression, representation, style, the significance of the artist's intention and the essentially historical nature of art. Presented in a fresh series livery for the twenty-first century, with a specially commissioned preface written by Richard Eldridge, illuminating its continuing importance and relevance to philosophical enquiry, Art and its Objects continues to be a perceptive and engaging introduction to the questions and philosophical issues raised by works of art and the part they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • The metaphysics of jazz.James O. Young & Carl Matheson - 2000 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 58 (2):125-133.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Art and Its Objects.Jeffrey Wieand - 1981 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 40 (1):91-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • The complete work.Kelly Trogdon & Paisley Nathan Livingston - 2014 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 72 (3):225-233.
    Defense of a psychological account of what it is for an artwork to be complete.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Artwork completion: a response to Gover.Kelly Trogdon & Paisley Nathan Livingston - 2015 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 73 (4):460-462.
    Response to Gover (2015) on Trogdon and Livingston (2015) on artwork completion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Musical Materialism.Chris Tillman - 2011 - British Journal of Aesthetics 51 (1):13-29.
    The consensus is that musical works and other ‘multiple’ artworks are abstract objects of some sort. According to the standard objections to musical materialism, multiple artworks cannot be identified with any concrete manifestation since concrete manifestations are many, and one thing cannot be identical to many. Multiple artworks are particularly good, while particular concrete manifestations are particularly bad, at surviving the destruction of particular concrete manifestations. Finally, multiple artworks cannot be identified with a particular sum of concrete manifestations since sums (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Musical materialism and the inheritance problem.Chris Tillman & J. Spencer - 2012 - Analysis 72 (2):252-259.
    Some hold that musical works are fusions of, or coincide with, their performances. But if performances contain wrong notes, won't works inherit that property? We say ‘no’.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Psychologism and Completeness in the Arts.Guy Rohrbaugh - 2017 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 75 (2):131-141.
    When is an artwork complete? Most hold that the correct answer to this question is psychological in nature. A work is said to be complete just in case the artist regards it as complete or is appropriately disposed to act as if he or she did. Even though this view seems strongly supported by metaphysical, epistemological, and normative considerations, this article argues that such psychologism about completeness is mistaken, fundamentally, because it cannot make sense of the artist's own perspective on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Artworld Metaphysics by kraut, robert.Guy Rohrbaugh - 2009 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 67 (3):339-341.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Artworks as historical individuals.Guy Rohrbaugh - 2003 - European Journal of Philosophy 11 (2):177–205.
    In 1907, Alfred Stieglitz took what was to become one of his signature photographs, The Steerage. Stieglitz stood at the rear of the ocean liner Kaiser Wilhelm II and photographed the decks, first-class passengers above and steerage passengers below, carefully exposing the film to their reflected light. Later, in the darkroom, Stieglitz developed this film and made a number of prints from the resulting negative. The photograph is a familiar one, an enduring piece of social commentary, but what exactly is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Not ideal: Collingwood's expression theory.Aaron Ridley - 1997 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 55 (3):263-272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Musical Ontology, Musical Reasons.Aaron Ridley - 2012 - The Monist 95 (4):663-683.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • What Is Music? Is There a Definitive Answer?Jonathan Mckeown-Green - 2014 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 72 (4):393-403.
    Philosophers frequently defend definitions by appealing to intuitions and contemporary folk classificatory norms. I raise methodological concerns that undermine some of these defenses. Focusing on Andrew Kania's recent definition of music, I argue that the way in which it has been developed leads to problems, and I show that a number of other definitions of interest to philosophers of art run into similar problems.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Judging Covers.Cristyn Magnus, P. D. Magnus & Christy Mag Uidhir - 2013 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 71 (4):361-370.
    Cover versions form a loose but identifiable category of tracks and performances. We distinguish four kinds of covers and argue that they mark important differences in the modes of evaluation that are possible or appropriate for each: mimic covers, which aim merely to echo the canonical track; rendition covers, which change the sound of the canonical track; transformative covers, which diverge so much as to instantiate a distinct, albeit derivative song; and referential covers, which not only instantiate a distinct song, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Counting fragments, and Frenhofer’s paradox.Paisley Nathan Livingston - 1999 - British Journal of Aesthetics 39 (1):14-23.
    It is quite common to draw a distinction between complete and unfinished works of art. For example, it is uncontroversial to think that Vermeer had actually completed View of Delft before inept restorers added layers of coloured varnish to give the picture an antique quality, and there is very good evidence to support the related claim that the artist had not finished the work before he effected several pentimenti, including the painting over of a figure in the foreground on the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Counting fragments, and Frenhofer’s paradox.Paisley Nathan Livingston - unknown
    It is quite common to draw a distinction between complete and unfinished works of art. For example, it is uncontroversial to think that Vermeer had actually completed View of Delft before inept restorers added layers of coloured varnish to give the picture an antique quality, and there is very good evidence to support the related claim that the artist had not finished the work before he effected several pentimenti, including the painting over of a figure in the foreground on the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • What a musical work is.Jerrold Levinson - 1980 - Journal of Philosophy 77 (1):5-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   136 citations  
  • Platonism in Music.Peter Kivy - 1983 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 19 (1):109-129.
    Various criticisms have been brought against a Platonistic construal of the musical work: that is, against the view that the musical work is a universal or kind or type, of which the performances are instances or tokens. Some of these criticisms are: (1) that musical works possess perceptual properties and universals do not; (2) that musical works are created and universals cannot be; (3) that universals cannot be destroyed and musical works can; (4) that parts of tokens of the same (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Platonism in Music.Peter Kivy - 1983 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 19 (1):109-129.
    Various criticisms have been brought against a Platonistic construal of the musical work: that is, against the view that the musical work is a universal or kind or type, of which the performances are instances or tokens. Some of these criticisms are: (1) that musical works possess perceptual properties and universals do not; (2) that musical works are created and universals cannot be; (3) that universals cannot be destroyed and musical works can; (4) that parts of tokens of the same (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Silent Music.Andrew Kania - 2010 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 68 (4):343-353.
    In this essay, I investigate musical silence. I first discuss how to integrate the concept of silence into a general theory or definition of music. I then consider the possibility of an entirely silent musical piece. I begin with John Cage’s 4′33″, since it is the most notorious candidate for a silent piece of music, even though it is not, in fact, silent. I conclude that it is not music either, but I argue that it is a piece of non-musical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Making tracks: The ontology of rock music.Andrew Kania - 2006 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 64 (4):401–414.
    I argue that the work of art in rock music is a track constructed in the studio, that tracks usually manifest songs, which can be performed live, and that a cover version is a track (successfully) intended to manifest the same song as some other track. This ontology reflects the way informed audiences talk about rock. It recognizes not only the centrality of recorded tracks to the tradition, as discussed by Theodore Gracyk, but also the value accorded to live performance (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • In Defence of Higher-Order Musical Ontology: A Reply to Lee B. Brown.A. Kania - 2012 - British Journal of Aesthetics 52 (1):97-102.
    In a recent article in this journal, Lee B. Brown criticizes one central kind of project in higher-order musical ontology—the project of offering an ontological theory of a particular musical tradition. I defend this kind of project by replying to Brown’s critique, arguing that musical practices are not untheorizably messy, and that a suitably subtle descriptivist ontology of a given practice can be valuable both theoretically and practically.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • All Play and No Work: An Ontology of Jazz.Andrew Kania - 2011 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 69 (4):391-403.
    I argue for an ontology of jazz according to which it is a tradition of musical performances but no works of art. I proceed by rejecting three alternative proposals: (i) that jazz is a work performance tradition, (ii) that jazz performances are works of art in themselves, and (iii) that jazz recordings are works of art. I also note that the concept of a work of art involved (1) is nonevaluative, so to deny jazz works of art is not to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • When is a work of art finished?Darren Hudson Hick - 2008 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 66 (1):67–76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • When Is a Work of Art Finished&quest.Darrenhudson Hick - 2008 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 66 (1):67-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • When Is a Work of Art Finished?Darren Hudson Hick - 2008 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 66 (1):67-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Imaginary Museum of Musical Works.Garry L. Hagberg - 1994 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 28 (4):99.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Rhythm and Noise: An Aesthetics of Rock.John Fisher - 1999 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 57 (4):467-469.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Ambivalent Agency: A Response to Trogdon and Livingston on Artwork Completion.K. E. Gover - 2015 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 73 (4):457-460.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The imaginary museum of musical works: an essay in the philosophy of music.Lydia Goehr - 1992 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    What is the difference between a performance of Beethoven's Fifth Symphony and the symphony itself? What does it mean for musicians to be faithful to the works they perform? To answer this question, Goehr combines philosophical and historical methods of enquiry. She describes how the concept of a musical work emerged as late as 1800, and how it subsequently defined the norms, expectations, and behavior characteristic of classical musical practice. Out of the historical thesis, Goehr draws philosophical conclusions about the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Compounds and aggregates.Kit Fine - 1994 - Noûs 28 (2):137-158.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Constitution and qua objects in the ontology of music.Simon J. Evnine - 2009 - British Journal of Aesthetics 49 (3):203-217.
    Musical Platonists identify musical works with abstract sound structures but this implies that they are not created but only discovered. Jerrold Levinson adapts Platonism to allow for creation by identifying musical works with indicated sound structures. In this paper I explore the similarities between Levinson's view and Kit Fine's theory of qua objects. Fine offers the theory of qua objects as an account of constitution, as it obtains, for example, between a statue and the clay the statue is made out (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Upholding Standards: A Realist Ontology of Standard Form Jazz.Julian Dodd - 2014 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 72 (3):277-290.
    In “All Play and No Work,” Andrew Kania claims that standard form jazz involves no works, only performances. This article responds to Kania by defending one of the alternative ontological proposals that he rejects, namely, that jazz works are ontologically continuous with works of classical music. I call this alternative “the standard view,” and I argue that it is the default position in the ontology of standard form jazz. Kania has three objections to the standard view. The bulk of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • On Defining Music.Stephen Davies - 2012 - The Monist 95 (4):535-555.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Musical Works and Performances: A Philosophical Exploration.Andrew Kania - 2003 - Mind 112 (447):513-518.
    A review of Stephen Davies's book, Musical Works and Performances.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Musical Works and Performances: A Philosophical Exploration.Stephen Davies - 2001 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    What are musical works? Are they discovered or created? Can recordings substitute faithfully for live performances? This book considers these and other intriguing questions. It first outlines the nature of musical works, their relation to performances, and their notational specification; it then considers authenticity in performance, musical traditions, and recordings. Comprehensive and original, the volume discusses many kinds of music, applying its conclusions to issues as diverse as the authentic performance movement, the cultural integrity of ethnic music, and the implications (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Dodd on the 'audibility' of musical works.David Davies - 2009 - British Journal of Aesthetics 49 (2):99-108.
    Julian Dodd has argued that the type–token theory in musical ontology has a ‘default’ status because it can explain the repeatability and audibility of musical works without the need for philosophical reinterpretation. I present two challenges to Dodd's claims about audibility. First, I argue (a) that a type–token theorist who, like Dodd, adheres to Wolterstorff's doctrine of analogical predication must grant that musical works themselves are hearable only in an ‘analogical’ sense; and (b) that alternative musical ontologies are able to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Collingwood's ‘performance’ theory of art.David Davies - 2008 - British Journal of Aesthetics 48 (2):162-174.
    Even if we reject the Wollheimian reading of Collingwood as an Idealist in the ontology of art, it remains puzzling how his non-Idealist ontology fits with his idea of art as expression. In trying to clarifying these matters, I argue that (i) the work of art, for Collingwood, is an activity, not the product of an activity; (ii) puzzling features of the Principles arise from attempts to reconcile this claim with the idea of art as expression while preserving the art/craft (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Art as Performance. [REVIEW]A. Kania - 2005 - Mind 114 (453):137-141.
    A review of David Davies, _Art as Performance_ (Blackwell, 2004).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Art as Performance.Robert Stecker - 2005 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 63 (1):77-80.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • An ontology of art.Gregory Currie - 1989 - New York: St. Martin's Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • An Ontology of Art, by Gregory Currie. [REVIEW]Jerrold Levinson - 1992 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1):215-222.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Unperformable Works and the Ontology of Music.Wesley D. Cray - 2016 - British Journal of Aesthetics 56 (1):67-81.
    Some artworks—works of music, theatre, dance, and the like—are works for performance. Some works for performance are, I contend, unperformable. Some such works are unperformable by beings like us; others are unperformable given our laws of nature; still others are unperformable given considerations of basic logic. I offer examples of works for performance—focusing, in particular, on works of music—that would fit into each of these categories, and go on to defend the claim that such ‘works’ really are genuine works, musical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • An Ontology of Ideas.Wesley D. Cray & Timothy Schroeder - 2015 - Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1 (4):757-775.
    Philosophers often talk about and engage with ideas. Scientists, artists, and historians do, too. But what is an idea? In this paper, we first motivate the desire for an ontology of ideas before discussing what conditions a candidate ontology would have to satisfy to be minimally adequate. We then offer our own account of the ontology of ideas, and consider various strategies for specifying the underlying metaphysics of the account. We conclude with a discussion of potential future work to be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A defence of musical idealism.Renée Cox - 1986 - British Journal of Aesthetics 26 (2):133-142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Defending musical perdurantism.Ben Caplan & Carl Matheson - 2006 - British Journal of Aesthetics 46 (1):59-69.
    If musical works are abstract objects, which cannot enter into causal relations, then how can we refer to musical works or know anything about them? Worse, how can any of our musical experiences be experiences of musical works? It would be nice to be able to sidestep these questions altogether. One way to do that would be to take musical works to be concrete objects. In this paper, we defend a theory according to which musical works are concrete objects. In (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations