Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Was Feyerabend a Popperian? Methodological issues in the History of the Philosophy of Science.Matteo Collodel - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 57:27-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science | Vol 73, No 3.Karl R. Popper - 1959 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 10 (38):171-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • The philosophy of Karl Popper.W. W. Bartley Iii - 1978 - Philosophia 7 (3-4):675-716.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Sir Karl Popper and his philosophy of physics.Max Jammer - 1991 - Foundations of Physics 21 (12):1357-1368.
    The eminent mathematical physicist Sir Hermann Bondi once said: “There is no more to science than its method, and there is no more to its method than Popper has said.” Indeed, many regard Sir Karl Raimund Popper the greatest philosopher of science in our generation. Much of what Popper “has said” refers to physics, but physicists, generally speaking, have little knowledge of what he has said. True, Popper's philosophy of science and, in particular, his realistic interpretation of quantum mechanics deviates (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A Suggested Interpretation of the Quantum Theory in Terms of ‘Hidden’ Variables, I and II.David Bohm - 1952 - Physical Review (85):166-193.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   313 citations  
  • “The Most Philosophically Important of All the Sciences”: Karl Popper and Physical Cosmology.Helge Kragh - 2013 - Perspectives on Science 21 (3):325-357.
    While Karl Popper’s philosophy of science has only few followers among modern philosophers, it is easily the view of science with the biggest impact on practicing scientists. According to Peter Medawar, Nobel laureate and eminent physiologist, Popper was the greatest authority ever on the scientific method. He praised the “great strength of Karl Popper’s conception of the scientific process,” a main reason for the praise being “that it is realistic—it gives a pretty fair picture of what goes on in real (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Birkhoff and von Neumann's Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics.Karl Popper - 1968 - Nature 219:682-685.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Indeterminism in quantum physics and in classical physics.Karl R. Popper - 1950 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 1 (2):117-133.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Propensities in a non-deterministic physics.N. Gisin - 1991 - Synthese 89 (2):287 - 297.
    Propensities are presented as a generalization of classical determinism. They describe a physical reality intermediary between Laplacian determinism and pure randomness, such as in quantum mechanics. They are characterized by the fact that their values are determined by the collection of all actual properties. It is argued that they do not satisfy Kolmogorov axioms; other axioms are proposed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The propensity interpretation of probability.Karl R. Popper - 1959 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 10 (37):25-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   236 citations  
  • Indeterminism in quantum physics and in classical physics. Part I.Karl R. Popper - 1950 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 1 (2):117-133.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Indeterminism in quantum physics and in classical physics: Part II.Karl R. Popper - 1950 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 1 (3):173-195.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Who invented the “copenhagen interpretation”? A study in mythology.Don Howard - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (5):669-682.
    What is commonly known as the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, regarded as representing a unitary Copenhagen point of view, differs significantly from Bohr's complementarity interpretation, which does not employ wave packet collapse in its account of measurement and does not accord the subjective observer any privileged role in measurement. It is argued that the Copenhagen interpretation is an invention of the mid‐1950s, for which Heisenberg is chiefly responsible, various other physicists and philosophers, including Bohm, Feyerabend, Hanson, and Popper, having (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • On a recent critique of complementarity: Part I.Paul K. Feyerabend - 1968 - Philosophy of Science 35 (4):309-331.
    Discussions of the interpretation of quantum theory are at present obstructed by (1) the increasing axiomania in physics and philosophy which replaces fundamental problems by problems of formulation within a certain preconceived calculus, and (2) the decreasing (since 1927) philosophical interest and sophistication both of professional physicists and of professional philosophers which results in the replacement of subtle positions by crude ones and of dialectical arguments by dogmatic ones. More especially, such discussions are obstructed by the ignorance of both opponents, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • On a recent critique of complementarity: Part II.Paul K. Feyerabend - 1969 - Philosophy of Science 36 (1):82-105.
    “Bohr was primarily a philosopher, not a physicist, but he understood that natural philosophy... carries weight only if its every detail can be subjected to the... test of experiment”. As a result his approach differed from that of the school-philosophers whom he regarded with a somewhat “sceptical attitude, to say the least” and whose lack of interest in “the important viewpoint which had emerged during the development of atomic physics” he noticed with regret. But it also differed, and to a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Strife about complementarity (II).Mario Bunge - 1955 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 6 (22):141-154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The philosophy of Karl Popper.W. W. Bartley - 1978 - Philosophia 7 (3-4):675-716.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Von Neumann’s impossibility proof: Mathematics in the service of rhetorics.Dennis Dieks - 2017 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 60:136-148.
    According to what has become a standard history of quantum mechanics, von Neumann in 1932 succeeded in convincing the physics community that he had proved that hidden variables were impossible as a matter of principle. Subsequently, leading proponents of the Copenhagen interpretation emphatically confirmed that von Neumann's proof showed the completeness of quantum mechanics. Then, the story continues, Bell in 1966 finally exposed the proof as seriously and obviously wrong; this rehabilitated hidden variables and made serious foundational research possible. It (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Genesis of Karl Popper's EPR-like experiment and its resonance amongst the physics community in the 1980s.Flavio Del Santo - 2018 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 62:56-70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The origins of the research on the foundations of quantum mechanics in Italy during the 1970s.Angelo Baracca, Silvio Bergia & Flavio Del Santo - 2017 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 57:66-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations