Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Falsificationism and the structure of theories: the Popper–Kuhn controversy about the rationality of normal science.Jose Díez - 2007 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 38 (3):543-554.
    Many controversies within philosophy of science have been attempted to be explained in terms of the metaphilosophical prescription/description distinction over the goal of philosophy of science. The aim of this paper is to show that the controversy between Popper and Kuhn about the ir/rationality of Normal Science cannot be fully explained in these terms, not even if we also take the truth/problem-solving distinction over the goal of science into account. It is argued that, to gain full understanding of this controversy, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Constructive criticism.Philip Catton - 2004 - In Philip Catton & Graham Macdonald (eds.), Karl Popper: Critical Appraisals. New York: Routledge. pp. 50-77.
    Aristarchus, Harvey, Wegener, Newton and Einstein all made significant scientific progress in which they overturned the thinking of their predecessors. But Popper’s model of conjectures and refutations is a poor guide to fathoming the accomplishment of these scientists. By now we have a better model, which I articulate. From its vantage point, I criticise Popper.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The open society revisited.Anthony O'Hear - 2004 - In Philip Catton & Graham Macdonald (eds.), Karl Popper: Critical Appraisals. New York: Routledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Physicists: The History of a Scientific Community in Modern America.Gerald Holton & Daniel J. Kevles - 1978 - Hastings Center Report 8 (3):42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • The open society and its enemies.Karl Raimund Popper - 1945 - London,: G. Routledge & sons. Edited by Alan Ryan & E. H. Gombrich.
    Written in political exile during the Second World War and first published in 1945, Karl Popper's The Open Society and Its Enemiesis one of the most influential books of the twentieth century. Hailed by Bertrand Russell as a 'vigorous and profound defence of democracy', its now legendary attack on the philosophies of Plato, Hegel and Marx exposed the dangers inherent in centrally planned political systems. Popper's highly accessible style, his erudite and lucid explanations of the thought of great philosophers and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   182 citations  
  • The Superconducting Super Collider's Frontier Outpost, 1983–1988.Lillian Hoddeson & Adrienne W. Kolb - 2000 - Minerva 38 (3):271-310.
    In 1993, after an optimistic beginning followed by a half-decadeof conflict, the Superconducting Super Collider (SSC) project wasabandoned. In an era of `Big Science', a major scientificenterprise collapsed. Why? We employ the metaphor of the`frontier outpost' to analyse a critical moment in the history ofthis vastly expensive project, when the physicists who designedthe machine were forced to recognize that traditional post-warscientific values were no longer in harmony with governmentpriorities.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Reconsidering Feyerabend’s “Anarchism‘.Jonathan Y. Tsou - 2003 - Perspectives on Science 11 (2):208-235.
    This paper explores Paul Feyerabend's (1924-1994) skeptical arguments for "anarchism" in his early writings between 1960 to 1975. Feyerabend's position is encapsulated by his well-known suggestion that the only principle for scientific method that can be defended under all circumstances is: "anything goes." I present Feyerabend's anarchism as a recommendation for pluralism that assumes a realist view of scientific theories. The aims of this paper are threefold: (1) to present a defensible view of Feyerabend's anarchism and its motivations, (2) to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Structure of scientific revolutions, the (ch. 9 only).Thomas Kuhn - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations  
  • Normal science: From logic to case-based and model-based reasoning.Tom Nickles - 2002 - In Thomas Nickles (ed.), Thomas Kuhn. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 142-77.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Why did Kuhn’s S tructure of Scientific Revolutions Cause a Fuss?Brendan Larvor - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (2):369-390.
    After the publication of The structure of scientific revolutions, Kuhn attempted to fend off accusations of extremism by explaining that his allegedly “relativist” theory is little more than the mundane analytical apparatus common to most historians. The appearance of radicalism is due to the novelty of applying this machinery to the history of science. This defence fails, but it provides an important clue. The claim of this paper is that Kuhn inadvertently allowed features of his procedure and experience as an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • From Conant's Education Strategy to Kuhn's Research Strategy.Steve Fuller - 2000 - Science & Education 9 (1-2):21-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Knowledge and Human Interests.Richard W. Miller - 1975 - Philosophical Review 84 (2):261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   225 citations  
  • Statistical language, statistical truth and statistical reason: the self-authenticictation of a style of scientific reasoning.A. Pickering - 1992 - In Andrew Pickering (ed.), Science as practice and culture. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Learning from the past: Reflections on the role of history in the philosophy of science.Daniel Garber - 1986 - Synthese 67 (1):91 - 114.
    In recent years philosophers of science have turned away from positivist programs for explicating scientific rationality through detailed accounts of scientific procedure and turned toward large-scale accounts of scientific change. One important motivation for this was better fit with the history of science. Paying particular attention to the large-scale theories of Lakatos and Laudan I argue that the history of science is no better accommodated by the new large-scale theories than it was by the earlier positivist philosophies of science; both (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations