Switch to: Citations

References in:

Robin George Collingwood

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2010)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. R.G. Collingwood: a research companion.James Connelly - 2015 - New York: Bloomsbury Academic. Edited by Peter Johnson & Stephen D. Leach.
    R G Collingwood is an important twentieth century historian, archaeologist and philosopher whose works are the subject of continued interest, analysis and study. There is an unquestionable need to support this research activity with the provision of a reference guide which is fully up-to-date, informed and authoritative. The Companion will therefore list all primary and secondary material relevant to the study of Collingwood in all his fields of expertise - historical theory, philosophy and archaeology. It will also provide a guide (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Truth, Time and History: A Philosophical Inquiry.Sophie Botros - 2017 - London, UK: Bloomsbury Academic.
    This book investigates the reality of the past by connecting arguments across areas which are conventionally discussed in isolation from each other. Breaking the impasse within the narrower analytic debate between Dummett’s semantic anti-realists and the truth value link realists as to whether the past exists independently of our methods of verification, it is argued, through an examination of the puzzles concerning identity over time, that only the present exists. Drawing on Lewis’s analogy between times and possible worlds, and work (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The touch of King Midas: Collingwood on why actions are not events.Giuseppina D’Oro - 2018 - Philosophical Explorations 21 (1):160-169.
    It is the ambition of natural science to provide complete explanations of reality. Collingwood argues that science can only explain events, not actions. The latter is the distinctive subject matter of history and can be described as actions only if they are explained historically. This paper explains Collingwood’s claim that the distinctive subject matter of history is actions and why the attempt to capture this subject matter through the method of science inevitably ends in failure because science explains events, not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • History and Idealism: Collingwood and Oakeshott.Giuseppina D'Oro - 2015 - In Malpass Jeff & Malpas Jeff (eds.), The Routledge Companion to hermenutics. Routledge. pp. 191-204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • L. S. Klejn and R. G. Collingwood on History, Archaeology, and Detection.Stephen Leach - 2017 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 11 (3):391-407.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Collingwood’s “Lost” Manuscript of.Jan van der Dussen - 1997 - History and Theory 36 (1):32-62.
    In his edition of The Idea of History Knox made use of parts of Collingwood's unfinished manuscript of The Principles of History, written during a voyage through the Dutch East Indies in 1938–1939. This manuscript, however, is not among Collingwood's manuscripts, available at the Bodleian Library at Oxford since 1978. It was therefore considered lost, but it has recently been discovered in the Electronics of Oxford University Press. Originally, it consisted of ninety pages containing finished chapters on "Evidence," "Action," and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Language, Truth, and Logic.A. J. Ayer - 1936 - Philosophy 23 (85):173-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   775 citations  
  • (1 other version)Systematically misleading expressions.G. Ryle - 1932 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 32:139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Bradley, Collingwood and the ‘other metaphysics’.James Connelly - 1997 - Bradley Studies 3 (2):89-112.
    In so far as Collingwood is branded an ‘idealist’, the corresponding assumption is that he subscribed to the broad themes associated with the ‘English idealists or Hegelians’; in so far as he is thought to have broken free from their pernicious influence he is regarded as a proto-Kuhn or Wittgenstein who saw the error of his early ways. This paper suggests that neither picture is fully accurate, and that while the figure of F.H. Bradley perhaps played a more significant part (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Philosophical Context of Collingwood’s Re-Enactment Theory.Jan van der Dussen - 1995 - International Studies in Philosophy 27 (2):81-99.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Collingwood on Reasons, Causes, and the Explanation of Action.Rex Martin - 1991 - International Studies in Philosophy 23 (3):47-62.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The Philosophy of Logical Atomism.Bertrand Russell - 1918 - In ¸ Iterussell1986. Open Court. pp. 193-210..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   346 citations  
  • (1 other version)Actions, Reasons, and Causes.Donald Davidson - 1963 - Journal of Philosophy 60 (23):685.
    What is the relation between a reason and an action when the reason explains the action by giving the agent's reason for doing what he did? We may call such explanations rationalizations, and say that the reason rationalizes the action. In this paper I want to defend the ancient - and common-sense - position that rationalization is a species of ordinary causal explanation. The defense no doubt requires some redeployment, but not more or less complete abandonment of the position, as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1294 citations  
  • IX.—Essentially Contested Concepts.W. B. Gallie - 1956 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 56 (1):167-198.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   341 citations  
  • Rediscovering Empathy: Agency, Folk Psychology, and the Human Sciences.Karsten R. Stueber - 2006 - Bradford.
    In this timely and wide-ranging study, Karsten Stueber argues that empathy is epistemically central for our folk-psychological understanding of other agents--that it is something we cannot do without in order to gain understanding of other minds. Setting his argument in the context of contemporary philosophy of mind and the interdisciplinary debate about the nature of our mindreading abilities, Stueber counters objections raised by some in the philosophy of social science and argues that it is time to rehabilitate the empathy thesis.Empathy, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  • The Many-Faced Argument. Recent Studies on the Ontological Argument for the Existence of God.John Hick & Arthur C. Mcgill - 1969 - Religious Studies 5 (1):123-125.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Collingwood: Action, Re-enactment and Evidence.L. B. Cebik - 1970 - Philosophical Forum 2 (1):68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Hesitant Hegelian: Collingwood, Hegel And Inter-War Oxford.James Connelly - 2005 - Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain 51:57-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Wahrheit und Methode, Grundzüge einer philosophischen Hermeneutik.Hans-Georg Gadamer - 1962 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 17 (2):258-259.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Collingwood: The Great Philosophers.Aaron Ridley - 1997 - New York: Routledge.
    First published in 1999. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor & Francis, an informa company.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The historical explanation of actions reconsidered.William Dray - 1963 - In Sidney Hook (ed.), Philosophy and history. [New York]: New York University Press. pp. 105--35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • R.G. Collingwood, Analytical Philosophy And Logical Positivism.James Connelly - 2008 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 4:2.
    R.G. Collingwood is not normally associated with analytic philosophy, neither negatively nor positively. He neither regarded himself, nor was regarded by his contemporaries and their successors, as an analytical philosopher. However, the story is more interestingly complex than this, both because Collingwood is one of the few pre-analytics in the UK who continues to be of interest to current analytical philosophers, especially in relation to the philosophy of art and history and his conception of metaphysics, and because he mounted a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Collingwood and anthropology as a historical science.D. Boucher - 2002 - History of Political Thought 23 (2):303-332.
    This paper explores R.G. Collingwood's argument that a new type of archaeology, taking fairy tales as its subject matter, is capable of expanding our historical knowledge of cultural practices. I suggest that it is interesting from the point of view of current discussions about cosmopolitanism and communitarianism and also for understanding past practices, such as magic, without having to attribute failure of reasoning or a breakdown in mentality to the participants, as Le Roy Ladurie does. Collingwood maintains that the natural (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Gadamer and Collingwood on temporal distance and understanding.Chinatsu Kobayashi & Mathieu Marion - 2011 - History and Theory 50 (4):81-103.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Narrative Logic: A Semantic Analysis of the Historian’s Language.Frank Ankersmit - 1983 - M. Nijhoff.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Collingwood's Historical Individualism.William H. Dray - 1980 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 10 (1):1 - 20.
    Central to R. G. Collingwood's philosophy of history, and among the most controvrsial of his doctrines, is the contention that historical understanding requires a re-anactment of past experience or a re-thinking of past thought. Some critics have found this contention in it-self incoherent or otherwise unsatisfactory, even as applied to what Collingwood apparently regarded as paradigm cases of historical thinking: for example, accounting for Caesar's crossing of the Rubicon in terms of his political ambitions. Others, while accepting the applicability of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Myth of Collingwood's Historicism.Giuseppina D'oro - 2010 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 53 (6):627-641.
    This paper seeks to clarify the precise sense in which Collingwood's “metaphysics without ontology” is a descriptive metaphysics. It locates Collingwood's metaphysics against the background of Strawson's distinction between descriptive and revisionary metaphysics and then defends it against the claim that Collingwood reduced metaphysics to a form of cultural anthropology. Collingwood's metaphysics is descriptive not because it is some sort of historicised psychology that describes temporally parochial and historically shifting assumptions, but because it is a high level form of conceptual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Collingwood and the Radical Conversion Hypothesis.Lionel Rubinoff - 1966 - Dialogue 5 (1):71-83.
    In 1938, four years before his death, Collingwood characterized his life as “in the main an attempt to bring about a rapprochement between philosophy and history”. Collingwood's success in this matter has been a subject of much debate. The majority of his critics have argued, following the leadership of T. A. Knox, that the alleged rapprochement was a failure. In the early writings, such as Religion and Philosophy and Speculum Mentis, it is simply obscure. In An Essay on Philosophical Method (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Human Conduct, History, and Social Science in the Works of R. G. Collingwood and Michael Oakeshott.David Boucher - 1993 - New Literary History 24:697-717.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The 'object' of historical knowledge.Patrick Gardiner - 1952 - Philosophy 27 (102):211-220.
    A critique of Collingwood's re-enactment concept.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • R. G. Collingwood on the identity of thoughts.Heikki Saari - 1989 - Dialogue 28 (1):77-89.
    R. G. Collingwood's re-enactment doctrine has been widely discussed in recent years by his commentators. However, most philosophers who discuss the re-enactment doctrine touch only briefly on his view of the identity of thoughts. This is surprising because Collingwood claims that the historian's successful re-enactment of the thought behind the historical agent's action involves re-thinking the same thought as the agent and not merely a copy of his thought.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Philosophy of history.William H. Dray - 1964 - Englewood Cliffs, N.J.,: Prentice-Hall.
    This update of the original version focuses on six central problems in the critical philosophy of history and explores the connections among them. Starting with the fundamentals of each philosophical topic in history and then delving into the specifics of each to better understand the surrounding issues, the reference first offers a comprehensive introduction into these topics then covers explanation and understanding ... objectivity and value judgment .. causes in history ... the nature and role of narrative ... and historical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Making sense of history: the philosophies of Popper and Collingwood.Peter Skagestad - 1975 - Oslo: Universitetsforlaget.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Explanation and understanding.Georg Henrik von Wright - 1971 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
    I Two Traditions. Scientific inquiry, seen in a very broad perspective, may be said to present two main aspects. One is the ascertaining and discovery of ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   171 citations  
  • R.G. Collingwood: a philosophy of art.Aaron Ridley (ed.) - 1998 - London: Phoenix.
    Many philosophers have been interested in aesthetics, but Collingwood was passionate about art. His theories were never merely theoretical: aesthetics for him was a vivid, vibrant thing, to be experienced immediately in worked paint and in sculptured stones, in poetry and music. Art and life were no dichotomy for Collingwood - for how could you have one without the other? Works of art were created in and for the real world, to be enjoyed by real people, to enchant to enhance. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The vicissitude of completeness: Gadamer's criticism of Collingwood.Dimitrios Vardoulakis - 2004 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 12 (1):3 – 19.
    The purpose of this article is to examine Gadamer's criticism of Collingwood's re-enactment. A parallel concern is the evaluation of Collingwood's hermeneutics of history. Given that Collingwood can be read as a hermeneutic thinker, what is the impact of Gadamer's critique of re-enactment? My response to this question focuses on the dual significance of completeness for hermeneutics. The fore-conception of completeness, on the one hand, presupposes meaningfulness. The incompleteness of meaning, on the other hand, shows that the finite human can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The function of general laws in history.Carl Gustav Hempel - 1942 - Journal of Philosophy 39 (2):35-48.
    The classic logical positivist account of historical explanation, putting forward what is variously called the "regularity interpretation" (#Gardiner, The Nature of Historical Explanation), the "covering law model" (#Dray, Laws and Explanation in History), or the "deductive model" (Michael #Scriven, "Truisms as Grounds for Historical Explanations"). See also #Danto, Narration and Knowledge, for further criticisms of the model. Hempel formalizes historical explanation as involving (a) statements of determining (initial and boundary) conditions for the event to be explained, and (b) statements of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   229 citations  
  • Re-enactment and radical interpretation.Giuseppina D'Oro - 2004 - History and Theory 43 (2):198–208.
    This article discusses R. G. Collingwood’s account of re-enactment and Donald Davidson’s account of radical translation. Both Collingwood and Davidson are concerned with the question “how is understanding possible?” and both seek to answer the question transcendentally by asking after the heuristic principles that guide the historian and the radical translator. Further, they both agree that the possibility of understanding rests on the presumption of rationality. But whereas Davidson’s principle of charity entails that truth is a presupposition or heuristic principle (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The later Collingwood's alleged historicism and relativism.Tariq Modood - 1989 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 27 (1):101-125.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • R.G. Collingwood: an introduction.Peter Johnson - 1998 - Dulles, Va.: Thoemmes.
    Why should modern philosophers read the works of R. G. Collingwood? His ideas are often thought difficult to locate in the main lines of development taken by twentieth-century philosophy. Some have read Collingwood as anticipating the later Wittgenstein, others have concentrated exclusively on the internal coherence of his thought. This work aims to introduce Collingwood to contemporary students of philosophy through direct engagement with his arguments. It is a conversation with Collingwood that takes as its subject matter the topics that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Re-thinking history.Keith Jenkins - 1991 - New York: Routledge.
    This introductory text is written for students faced with the question "what is history?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Inference and Intuition in Collingwood’s Philosophy of History.Robert G. Shoemaker - 1969 - The Monist 53 (1):100-115.
    My concern here is with the possibility of defending some of R. G. Collingwood’s views regarding the roles of inference and ‘re-enactment’ in ‘doing history’. The difficulties encountered result from the fact that Collingwood never presented his views in an altogether clear and complete form, and the fact that several metaphysical and epistemological problems are involved. The specific problems dealt with are, for the most part, those which seem most easily disposed of by an adequate interpretation of Collingwood.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Significance of R. G. Collingwood's "Principles of History".David Boucher - 1997 - Journal of the History of Ideas 58 (2):309.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Significance of R. G. Collingwood’s Principles of HistoryDavid BoucherThe Principles of History is the work that Collingwood saw as his principal philosophical enterprise, the book for which his whole intellectual life had been a preparation. It was to have been a work divided into three books. 1 In the first there was to be a discussion of the characteristics that make the special science of history distinctive. In (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • History and the Primacy of Knowing.Leon J. Goldstein - 1977 - History and Theory 16 (4):29-52.
    Knowledge, including historical knowledge, is dependent upon the procedure by which it is acquired. Nowell-Smith attempts to drive a logical wedge between the assertion of historical statements and the objects to which they refer. This distinction between assertion and referent, however, does not exist in the practice of history. In historical study there is no way to acquire knowledge except through the construction of theory. The brute sensory data which form an essential part of an understanding of the present are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Constructionist Theory of History.P. H. Nowell-Smith - 1977 - History and Theory 16 (4):1-28.
    The constructionist thesis of history states, in general, that the historian must construct a theory to explain the past. Some, including Leon Goldstein, attempt to push this formulation beyond a description of historical methodology. They argue that since the real past is inaccessible to present observation, the real past can have no relevance for historiography. The distinctions made between the present, the real past, and the historical past generate problems with the concepts of past and present knowledge, theoretical infrastructure and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (2 other versions)A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive.John Stuart Mill - 1843 - New York and London,: University of Toronto Press. Edited by J. Robson.
    Ethics and jurisprudence are liable to the remark in common with logic. Almost every writer having taken a different view of some of the particulars which ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   349 citations  
  • (1 other version)Philosophical analysis and history.William H. Dray - 1966 - [New York,: Harper & Row.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Re-enactment and Reconstruction in Collingwood's Philosophy of History.Margit Hurup Nielsen - 1981 - History and Theory 20 (1):1-31.
    Collingwood's re-enactment doctrine, the notion that the historian must re-enact the past in his own mind, forms the methodological pillar of Collingwood's constructivism. The first tenet of this interpretation states that for the past to be knowable it must have left traces analyzable in the present. Second, the historical process must be rational, which necessitates that the object of knowledge be "re-enactable" and that the subject of knowledge be "re-enact-capable." Third, both subject and object must come in contact in an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth-century Europe.Hayden V. White - 1973 - Baltimore: Johns Hopkins.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  • Congratulations, it's a tragedy: Collingwood's remarks on genre.Aaron Ridley - 2002 - British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (1):52-63.
    This essay argues that R.G. Collingwood's remarks about genre are implausible, and that they stem, despite their apparent origin in his wider account of art, from his failure to take some of his own most important insights seriously enough. Some possible reasons for that failure are suggested; and it is shown that, once the relevant insights are given their proper weight, Collingwood's account commands the resources from which a plausible story about genre might have been constructed. To this extent, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations