Switch to: Citations

References in:

Robin George Collingwood

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2010)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Philosophy of Logical Atomism.Bertrand Russell - 1918 - The Monist 28 (4):495-527.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   187 citations  
  • Human Nature and Historical Knowledge: Hume, Hegel and Vico.Leon Pompa - 1990 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This book presents a study of the nature and conditions of historical knowledge, conducted through a study of the relevant theories of Hume, Hegel and Vico. It is usually thought that in order to establish historical facts, we have to have a theory of human nature to support our arguments. Hume, Hegel and Vico all subscribed to this view, and are therefore discussed in detail. Professor Pompa goes on to argue that there is in fact no way of discovering anything (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Actions, Reasons, and Causes.Donald Davidson - 1963 - Journal of Philosophy 60 (23):685.
    What is the relation between a reason and an action when the reason explains the action by giving the agent's reason for doing what he did? We may call such explanations rationalizations, and say that the reason rationalizes the action. In this paper I want to defend the ancient - and common-sense - position that rationalization is a species of ordinary causal explanation. The defense no doubt requires some redeployment, but not more or less complete abandonment of the position, as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1275 citations  
  • IX.—Essentially Contested Concepts.W. B. Gallie - 1956 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 56 (1):167-198.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   330 citations  
  • The Autonomy of Historical Understanding.Louis O. Mink - 1966 - History and Theory 5 (1):24-47.
    On received philosophical doctrine, history is simply methodologically immature. History's autonomy can be established not by showing scientific explanations impossible for "history," but by coupling a demonstration that hypothetico-deductive explanation cannot exhaustively analyze historical knowledge with a critique of the proto-science view's assumption that legitimate modes of understanding must be analyzable by an explicit methodology. Certain views historians accept, e.g., that events are unique, while inadequate as a general theory of events, reveal historical understanding's distinctive feature: synoptic judgment, which, irreducible (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • The Constructionist Theory of History.P. H. Nowell-Smith - 1977 - History and Theory 16 (4):1-28.
    The constructionist thesis of history states, in general, that the historian must construct a theory to explain the past. Some, including Leon Goldstein, attempt to push this formulation beyond a description of historical methodology. They argue that since the real past is inaccessible to present observation, the real past can have no relevance for historiography. The distinctions made between the present, the real past, and the historical past generate problems with the concepts of past and present knowledge, theoretical infrastructure and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Understanding Others: Cultural Anthropology with Collingwood and Quine.Giuseppina D'Oro - 2013 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 7 (3):326-345.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • R.G. Collingwood, Analytical Philosophy And Logical Positivism.James Connelly - 2008 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 4:2.
    R.G. Collingwood is not normally associated with analytic philosophy, neither negatively nor positively. He neither regarded himself, nor was regarded by his contemporaries and their successors, as an analytical philosopher. However, the story is more interestingly complex than this, both because Collingwood is one of the few pre-analytics in the UK who continues to be of interest to current analytical philosophers, especially in relation to the philosophy of art and history and his conception of metaphysics, and because he mounted a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth-century Europe.Hayden V. White - 1973 - Baltimore: Johns Hopkins.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  • Human Conduct, History, and Social Science in the Works of R. G. Collingwood and Michael Oakeshott.David Boucher - 1993 - New Literary History 24:697-717.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • R. G. Collingwood on the identity of thoughts.Heikki Saari - 1989 - Dialogue 28 (1):77-89.
    R. G. Collingwood's re-enactment doctrine has been widely discussed in recent years by his commentators. However, most philosophers who discuss the re-enactment doctrine touch only briefly on his view of the identity of thoughts. This is surprising because Collingwood claims that the historian's successful re-enactment of the thought behind the historical agent's action involves re-thinking the same thought as the agent and not merely a copy of his thought.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Collected papers.Gilbert Ryle - 1971 - London,: Hutchinson.
    v. 1. Critical essays.--v. 2. Collected essays, 1929-1968.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Philosophical analysis and history.William H. Dray - 1966 - Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press. Edited by William H. Dray.
    The concept of scientific history / Isaiah Berlin -- The limits of scientific history / W.H. Walsh -- The objectivity of history / J.A. Passmore -- Explanation in science and in history / C.G. Hempel -- The Popper-Hempel theory reconsidered / Alan Donagan -- The autonomy of historical understanding / Louis O. Mink -- Historical continuity and causal analysis / Michael Oakeshott -- Causal judgment in history and in the law / H.L.A. Hart and A.M. Honoré -- Causes, connections and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Systematically misleading expressions.Gilbert Ryle - 1951 - In Gilbert Ryle & Antony Flew (eds.), Logic and language (first series): essays. Oxford: Blackwell. pp. 139 - 170.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Congratulations, it's a tragedy: Collingwood's remarks on genre.Aaron Ridley - 2002 - British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (1):52-63.
    This essay argues that R.G. Collingwood's remarks about genre are implausible, and that they stem, despite their apparent origin in his wider account of art, from his failure to take some of his own most important insights seriously enough. Some possible reasons for that failure are suggested; and it is shown that, once the relevant insights are given their proper weight, Collingwood's account commands the resources from which a plausible story about genre might have been constructed. To this extent, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The function of general laws in history.Carl Gustav Hempel - 1942 - Journal of Philosophy 39 (2):35-48.
    The classic logical positivist account of historical explanation, putting forward what is variously called the "regularity interpretation" (#Gardiner, The Nature of Historical Explanation), the "covering law model" (#Dray, Laws and Explanation in History), or the "deductive model" (Michael #Scriven, "Truisms as Grounds for Historical Explanations"). See also #Danto, Narration and Knowledge, for further criticisms of the model. Hempel formalizes historical explanation as involving (a) statements of determining (initial and boundary) conditions for the event to be explained, and (b) statements of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   225 citations  
  • The touch of King Midas: Collingwood on why actions are not events.Giuseppina D’Oro - 2018 - Philosophical Explorations 21 (1):160-169.
    It is the ambition of natural science to provide complete explanations of reality. Collingwood argues that science can only explain events, not actions. The latter is the distinctive subject matter of history and can be described as actions only if they are explained historically. This paper explains Collingwood’s claim that the distinctive subject matter of history is actions and why the attempt to capture this subject matter through the method of science inevitably ends in failure because science explains events, not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Philosophy, History and Civilization. Interdisciplinary Perspectives on R.G. Collingwood.David Boucher, James Connelly & Tariq Modood - 1996 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 58 (4):771-773.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Critical Essays on the Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood.Michael Krausz - 1973 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 163:222-223.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Philosophy of History.William H. Dray - 1966 - Philosophy 41 (156):183-185.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Bradley, Collingwood and the ‘other metaphysics’.James Connelly - 1997 - Bradley Studies 3 (2):89-112.
    In so far as Collingwood is branded an ‘idealist’, the corresponding assumption is that he subscribed to the broad themes associated with the ‘English idealists or Hegelians’; in so far as he is thought to have broken free from their pernicious influence he is regarded as a proto-Kuhn or Wittgenstein who saw the error of his early ways. This paper suggests that neither picture is fully accurate, and that while the figure of F.H. Bradley perhaps played a more significant part (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Rediscovering Empathy: Agency, Folk Psychology, and the Human Sciences.Karsten Stueber - 2006 - Bradford.
    In this timely and wide-ranging study, Karsten Stueber argues that empathy is epistemically central for our folk-psychological understanding of other agents--that it is something we cannot do without in order to gain understanding of other minds. Setting his argument in the context of contemporary philosophy of mind and the interdisciplinary debate about the nature of our mindreading abilities, Stueber counters objections raised by some in the philosophy of social science and argues that it is time to rehabilitate the empathy thesis.Empathy, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  • Wahrheit und Methode, Grundzüge einer philosophischen Hermeneutik.Hans-Georg Gadamer - 1962 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 17 (2):258-259.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Metaphysics, Method and Politics: The Political Philosophy of R.G. Collingwood.James Connelly - 2003 - Imprint Academic.
    This book argues that Collingwood developed a complete political philosophy of civilization. It also demonstrates that his philosophical work comprises a unity in which there is no fundamental discontinuity between his earlier and later writings.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Myth of Collingwood's Historicism.Giuseppina D'oro - 2010 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 53 (6):627-641.
    This paper seeks to clarify the precise sense in which Collingwood's “metaphysics without ontology” is a descriptive metaphysics. It locates Collingwood's metaphysics against the background of Strawson's distinction between descriptive and revisionary metaphysics and then defends it against the claim that Collingwood reduced metaphysics to a form of cultural anthropology. Collingwood's metaphysics is descriptive not because it is some sort of historicised psychology that describes temporally parochial and historically shifting assumptions, but because it is a high level form of conceptual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Laws and explanation in history.William H. Dray - 1957 - Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   134 citations  
  • R.G. Collingwood: an introduction.Peter Johnson - 1998 - Dulles, Va.: Thoemmes.
    Why should modern philosophers read the works of R. G. Collingwood? His ideas are often thought difficult to locate in the main lines of development taken by twentieth-century philosophy. Some have read Collingwood as anticipating the later Wittgenstein, others have concentrated exclusively on the internal coherence of his thought. This work aims to introduce Collingwood to contemporary students of philosophy through direct engagement with his arguments. It is a conversation with Collingwood that takes as its subject matter the topics that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Truth, Time and History: A Philosophical Inquiry.Sophie Botros - 2017 - London, UK: Bloomsbury Academic.
    This book investigates the reality of the past by connecting arguments across areas which are conventionally discussed in isolation from each other. Breaking the impasse within the narrower analytic debate between Dummett’s semantic anti-realists and the truth value link realists as to whether the past exists independently of our methods of verification, it is argued, through an examination of the puzzles concerning identity over time, that only the present exists. Drawing on Lewis’s analogy between times and possible worlds, and work (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Collingwood and the Metaphysics of Experience.Giuseppina D'oro - 2004 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 66 (2):365-368.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Language, Truth, and Logic.A. J. Ayer - 1936 - Philosophy 23 (85):173-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   777 citations  
  • The Philosophical Context of Collingwood’s Re-Enactment Theory.Jan van der Dussen - 1995 - International Studies in Philosophy 27 (2):81-99.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Many-Faced Argument. Recent Studies on the Ontological Argument for the Existence of God.John Hick & Arthur C. Mcgill - 1969 - Religious Studies 5 (1):123-125.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • History and the Primacy of Knowing.Leon J. Goldstein - 1977 - History and Theory 16 (4):29-52.
    Knowledge, including historical knowledge, is dependent upon the procedure by which it is acquired. Nowell-Smith attempts to drive a logical wedge between the assertion of historical statements and the objects to which they refer. This distinction between assertion and referent, however, does not exist in the practice of history. In historical study there is no way to acquire knowledge except through the construction of theory. The brute sensory data which form an essential part of an understanding of the present are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Collingwood's Theory of Historical Knowing.Leon J. Goldstein - 1970 - History and Theory 9 (1):3-36.
    Collingwood's well-known dicta about history and its practice are not expressions of a perverse idealism but are rooted in reflection on his own work as historian. The problem which informs his writings on history was to make sense of the discipline of history without opening the way to historical skepticism. The early view of his Speculum Mentis, rooted in an external philosophical stance and not in the actual practice of history, was actually skeptical. In his middle years he regarded history (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Re-enactment and Reconstruction in Collingwood's Philosophy of History.Margit Hurup Nielsen - 1981 - History and Theory 20 (1):1-31.
    Collingwood's re-enactment doctrine, the notion that the historian must re-enact the past in his own mind, forms the methodological pillar of Collingwood's constructivism. The first tenet of this interpretation states that for the past to be knowable it must have left traces analyzable in the present. Second, the historical process must be rational, which necessitates that the object of knowledge be "re-enactable" and that the subject of knowledge be "re-enact-capable." Third, both subject and object must come in contact in an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Collingwood: The Great Philosophers.Aaron Ridley - 1997 - New York: Routledge.
    First published in 1999. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor & Francis, an informa company.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Rethinking R.G. Collingwood: philosophy, politics, and the unity of theory and practice.Gary K. Browning - 2004 - New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Rethinking R.G. Collingwood reviews Collingwood's thought via his own rethinking of Hegel. It establishes the revisionary character of Collingwood's defence of liberal civilization in theory and practice. Collingwood is seen as avoiding the pitfalls of Hegel's teleological historicism by developing an open and contestable reading of the rationality of liberal civilization, which neither reduces practice to theory nor philosophy to history. The contemporary relevance of Collingwood's standpoint is demonstrated by comparing it with those of recent defenders and critics of liberalism (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Collingwood and the Radical Conversion Hypothesis.Lionel Rubinoff - 1966 - Dialogue 5 (1):71-83.
    In 1938, four years before his death, Collingwood characterized his life as “in the main an attempt to bring about a rapprochement between philosophy and history”. Collingwood's success in this matter has been a subject of much debate. The majority of his critics have argued, following the leadership of T. A. Knox, that the alleged rapprochement was a failure. In the early writings, such as Religion and Philosophy and Speculum Mentis, it is simply obscure. In An Essay on Philosophical Method (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Collingwood’s Claim That Metaphysics is a Historical Discipline.Rex Martin - 1989 - The Monist 72 (4):489-525.
    The procedure I will follow in this paper requires a brief initial note of explanation. Collingwood’s texts are opaque at two points. First, he does not make clear what precisely he meant by the claim that metaphysics is a historical discipline. The prevailing interpretation—which I dispute—has been that he had in mind a similarity or identity of certain methods of inquiry or explanation. Second, and more seriously, he does not make clear the relationship of his two main treatises on metaphysics. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • R.G. Collingwood: a philosophy of art.Aaron Ridley (ed.) - 1998 - London: Phoenix.
    Many philosophers have been interested in aesthetics, but Collingwood was passionate about art. His theories were never merely theoretical: aesthetics for him was a vivid, vibrant thing, to be experienced immediately in worked paint and in sculptured stones, in poetry and music. Art and life were no dichotomy for Collingwood - for how could you have one without the other? Works of art were created in and for the real world, to be enjoyed by real people, to enchant to enhance. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • History and Idealism: Collingwood and Oakeshott.Giuseppina D'Oro - 2015 - In Malpass Jeff & Malpas Jeff (eds.), The Routledge Companion to hermenutics. Routledge. pp. 191-204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Collingwood’s Metaphysics.Guido Vanheeswijck - 1998 - International Philosophical Quarterly 38 (2):153-174.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Collingwood on Reasons, Causes, and the Explanation of Action.Rex Martin - 1991 - International Studies in Philosophy 23 (3):47-62.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Presuppositions of Critical History.F. H. Bradley - 1935 - Chicago,: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Lionel Rubinoff.
    This work combines two early pamphlets by F. H. Bradley, the foremost philosopher of the British Idealist movement. The first essay, published in 1874, deals with the nature of professional history, and foreshadows some of Bradley's later ideas in metaphysics. He argues that history cannot be subjected to scientific scrutiny because it is not directly available to the senses, meaning that all history writing is inevitably subjective. Though not widely discussed at the time of publication, the pamphlet was influential on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The later philosophy of R. G. Colling wood.Alan Donagan - 1964 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 69 (3):356-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The historical explanation of actions reconsidered.William Dray - 1963 - In Sidney Hook (ed.), Philosophy and history. [New York]: New York University Press. pp. 105--35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The 'object' of historical knowledge.Patrick Gardiner - 1952 - Philosophy 27 (102):211-220.
    A critique of Collingwood's re-enactment concept.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Re-thinking history.Keith Jenkins - 1991 - New York: Routledge.
    This introductory text is written for students faced with the question "what is history?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Re-enactment and radical interpretation.Giuseppina D'Oro - 2004 - History and Theory 43 (2):198–208.
    This article discusses R. G. Collingwood’s account of re-enactment and Donald Davidson’s account of radical translation. Both Collingwood and Davidson are concerned with the question “how is understanding possible?” and both seek to answer the question transcendentally by asking after the heuristic principles that guide the historian and the radical translator. Further, they both agree that the possibility of understanding rests on the presumption of rationality. But whereas Davidson’s principle of charity entails that truth is a presupposition or heuristic principle (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Collingwood on re-enactment and the identity of thought.Giuseppina D'Oro - 2000 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 38 (1):87-101.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 38.1 (2000) 87-101 [Access article in PDF] Collingwood on Re-Enactment and The Identity of Thought Giuseppina D'oro University of Keele Collingwood's The Idea of History is often discussed in the context of the issue of the reducibility/non-reducibility of explanations in the social sciences to explanations in the natural sciences. In the 1950s and 60s, following the publication of Hempel's influential article, "The Function (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations