Switch to: Citations

References in:

Names Are Predicates

Philosophical Review 124 (1):59-117 (2015)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Semantic vs. Syntactic Categories.Edwin Williams - 1983 - Linguistics and Philosophy 6 (3):423 - 446.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Mathematical logic.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1951 - Cambridge,: Harvard University Press.
    INTRODUCTION MATHEMATICAL logic differs from the traditional formal logic so markedly in method, and so far surpasses it in power and subtlety, ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   160 citations  
  • Thought and Reference.[author unknown] - 1989 - Mind 98 (389):167-169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Speaker’s Reference and Semantic Reference.Saul Kripke - 1977 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 2 (1):255-276.
    am going to discuss some issues inspired by a well-known paper ofKeith Donnellan, "Reference and Definite Descriptions,”2 but the interest—to me—of the contrast mentioned in my title goes beyond Donnellan's paper: I think it is of considerable constructive as well as critical importance to the philosophy oflanguage. These applications, however, and even everything I might want to say relative to Donnellan’s paper, cannot be discussed in full here because of problems of length. Moreover, although I have a considerable interest in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   399 citations  
  • Descriptions.Bertrand Russell - 2010 - In Darragh Byrne & Max Kölbel (eds.), Arguing about language. New York: Routledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Methods of logic.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1950 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    Provides comprehensive coverage of logical structure as well as the techniques of formal reasoning.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   222 citations  
  • Word and Object.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1960 - Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press.
    In the course of the discussion, Professor Quine pinpoints the difficulties involved in translation, brings to light the anomalies and conflicts implicit in our ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2595 citations  
  • Situations and Individuals.Paul D. Elbourne - 2005 - MIT Press.
    In Situations and Individuals, Paul Elbourne argues that the natural language expressions that have been taken to refer to individuals — pronouns, proper names, and definite descriptions — have a common syntax and semantics, roughly that of definite descriptions as construed in the tradition of Frege. In the course of his argument, Elbourne shows that proper names have previously undetected donkey anaphoric readings.This is contrary to previous theorizing and, if true, would undermine what philosophers call the direct reference theory (which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   177 citations  
  • Proper names as variables.Takashi Yagisawa - 1984 - Erkenntnis 21 (2):195 - 208.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Word and Object. W. Van Orman Quine.R. L. Goodstein - 1961 - Philosophy of Science 28 (2):217-217.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • A reply to mr. Sellars.P. F. Strawson - 1954 - Philosophical Review 63 (2):216-231.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Quantifiers and context-dependence.Jason Stanley & Alonso Church - 1995 - Analysis 55 (4):291.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Quantifiers and Context Dependence.Jason Stanley & Timothy Williamson - 1995 - Analysis 55 (4):291--295.
    Let DDQ be the thesis that definite descriptions are quantifiers. Philosophers often deny DDQ because they believe that quantifiers do not depend on context in certain ways, ways in which definite descriptions do depend on context. In this paper, we examine one such argument, which, if sound, would entail the negation of DDQ.We show that this argument fails, and draw some consequences from its failure.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Quantifiers and Context Dependence.Jason Stanley & Timothy Williamson - 1995 - Analysis 55 (4):291-295.
    Let DDQ be the thesis that definite descriptions are quantifiers. Philosophers often deny DDQ because they believe that quantifiers do not depend on context in certain ways, ways in which definite descriptions do depend on context. In this paper, we examine one such argument, which, if sound, would entail the negation of DDQ.We show that this argument fails, and draw some consequences from its failure.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • On Quantifier Domain Restriction.Jason Stanley & Zoltán Gendler Szabó - 2000 - Mind and Language 15 (2-3):219--61.
    In this paper, we provide a comprehensive survey of the space of possible analyses of the phenomenon of quantifier domain restriction, together with a set of considerations which militate against all but our own proposal. Among the many accounts we consider and reject are the ‘explicit’ approach to quantifier domain restric‐tion discussed, for example, by Stephen Neale, and the pragmatic approach to quantifier domain restriction proposed by Kent Bach. Our hope is that the exhaustive discussion of this special case of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   385 citations  
  • Making it articulated.Jason Stanley - 2002 - Mind and Language 17 (1-2):149–168.
    I argue in favor of the view that all the constituents of the propositions hearers would intuitively believe to be expressed by utterances are the result of assigning values to the elements of the sentence uttered, and combining them in accord with its structure. The way I accomplish this is by questioning the existence of some of the processes that theorists have claimed underlie the provision of constituents to the propositions recovered by hearers in linguistic interpretation, processes that apparently bypass (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • A more general theory of definite descriptions.Richard Sharvy - 1980 - Philosophical Review 89 (4):607-624.
    A unified theory is offered to account for three types of definite descriptions: with singular, plural, & mass predicates, & to provide an account for the word the in descriptions. It is noted that B. Russell's analysis ("On Denoting," Mind, 1905, 14, 479-493) failed to account for plural & mass descriptions. The proposed theory differs from Russell's only by the substitution of the notation (less than or equal to) for Russell's =. It is suggested that for every predicate G there (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations  
  • Presupposing.Wilfrid Sellars - 1954 - Philosophical Review 63 (2):197-215.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Two theories of names.Gabriel Segal - 2001 - Mind and Language 16 (5):547–563.
    Two semantic theories of proper names are explained and assessed. The theories are Burge’s treatment of proper names as complex demonstratives and Larson and Segal’s quasi-descriptivist account of names. The two theories are evaluated for empirical plausibility. Data from deficits, processing models, developmental studies and syntax are all discussed. It is concluded that neither theory is fully confirmed or refuted by the data, but that Larson and Segal’s theory has more empirical plausibility.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Two Theories of Names.Gabriel M. A. Segal - 2002 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 51:75-93.
    The aim of this paper is to assess the relative merits of two accounts of the semantics of proper names. The enterprise is of particular interest because the theories are very similar in fundamental respects. In particular, they can agree on three major features of names: names are rigid designators; different co-extensive names can have different cognitive significance; empty proper names can be meaningful. Neither theory by itself offers complete explanations of all three features. But each theory is consistent with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Incomplete Definite Descriptions.Scott Soames - 1986 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 27 (3):349--375.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Assertion and Incomplete Definite Descriptions.Nathan U. Salmon - 1982 - Philosophical Studies 42 (1):37--45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The Principles of Mathematics.Bertrand Russell - 1903 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 11 (4):11-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   688 citations  
  • On Denoting.Bertrand Russell - 1905 - Mind 14 (56):479-493.
    By a `denoting phrase' I mean a phrase such as any one of the following: a man, some man, any man, every man, all men, the present King of England, the present King of France, the center of mass of the solar system at the first instant of the twentieth century, the revolution of the earth round the sun, the revolution of the sun round the earth. Thus a phrase is denoting solely in virtue of its form. We may distinguish (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1205 citations  
  • On Denoting.Bertrand Russell - 2005 - Mind 114 (456):873 - 887.
    By a `denoting phrase' I mean a phrase such as any one of the following: a man, some man, any man, every man, all men, the present King of England, the present King of France, the center of mass of the solar system at the first instant of the twentieth century, the revolution of the earth round the sun, the revolution of the sun round the earth. Thus a phrase is denoting solely in virtue of its form. We may distinguish (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   667 citations  
  • Presuppositions and scope.Daniel Rothschild - 2007 - Journal of Philosophy 104 (2):71-106.
    This paper discusses the apparent scope ambiguities between definite descriptions and modal operators. I argue that we need the theory of presupposition to explain why these ambiguities are not always present, and that once that theory is in hand, Kripke’s modal argument loses much of its force.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • On the unification argument for the predicate view on proper names.Dolf Rami - 2014 - Synthese 191 (5):1-22.
    The predicate view on proper names opts for a uniform semantic representation of proper nouns like ‘Alfred’ as predicates on the level of logical form. Early defences of this view can be found in Sloat (Language, vol. 45, pp. 26–30, 1969) and Burge (J. Philos. 70: 425–439, 1973), but there is an increasing more recent interest in this view on proper names. My paper aims to provide a reconstruction and critique of Burge’s main argument for the predicate view on proper (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Mathematical Logic. [REVIEW]E. N. & Willard Van Orman Quine - 1940 - Journal of Philosophy 37 (23):640.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   114 citations  
  • Descriptions.Stephen Neale - 1990 - MIT Press.
    When philosophers talk about descriptions, usually they have in mind singular definite descriptions such as ‘the finest Greek poet’ or ‘the positive square root of nine’, phrases formed with the definite article ‘the’. English also contains indefinite descriptions such as ‘a fine Greek poet’ or ‘a square root of nine’, phrases formed with the indefinite article ‘a’ (or ‘an’); and demonstrative descriptions (also known as complex demonstratives) such as ‘this Greek poet’ and ‘that tall woman’, formed with the demonstrative articles (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   202 citations  
  • On the linguistic complexity of proper names.Ora Matushansky - 2008 - Linguistics and Philosophy 31 (5):573-627.
    While proper names in argument positions have received a lot of attention, this cannot be said about proper names in the naming construction, as in “Call me Al”. I argue that in a number of more or less familiar languages the syntax of naming constructions is such that proper names there have to be analyzed as predicates, whose content mentions the name itself (cf. “quotation theories”). If proper names can enter syntax as predicates, then in argument positions they should have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Scorekeeping in a language game.David Lewis - 1979 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 8 (1):339--359.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   908 citations  
  • The double life of names.Gail Leckie - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 165 (3):1139-1160.
    This paper is a counter to the view that names are always predicates with the same extension as a metalinguistic predicate with the form “is a thing called “N”” (the Predicate View). The Predicate View is in opposition to the Referential View of names. In this paper, I undermine one argument for the Predicate View. The Predicate View’s adherents take examples of uses of names that have the surface appearance of a predicate and generalise from these to treat uses of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • The semantics of mass-predicates.Kathrin Koslicki - 1999 - Noûs 33 (1):46-91.
    Along with many other languages, English has a relatively straightforward grammatical distinction between mass-occurrences of nouns and their countoccurrences. As the mass-count distinction, in my view, is best drawn between occurrences of expressions, rather than expressions themselves, it becomes important that there be some rule-governed way of classifying a given noun-occurrence into mass or count. The project of classifying noun-occurrences is the topic of Section II of this paper. Section III, the remainder of the paper, concerns the semantic differences between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Thought and Reference.Bernard W. Kobes - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (3):469.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   159 citations  
  • Singular terms, reference and methodology in semantics.Jeffrey C. King - 2006 - Philosophical Issues 16 (1):141–161.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • The end of millianism: Multiple bearers, improper names, and compositional meaning.Jerrold J. Katz - 2001 - Journal of Philosophy 98 (3):137-166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Words.David Kaplan - 1990 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 64 (1):93-119.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   235 citations  
  • Proper names: A defence of Burge.Jennifer Hornsby - 1976 - Philosophical Studies 30 (4):227 - 234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Methods of Logic.P. L. Heath & Willard Van Orman Quine - 1955 - Philosophical Quarterly 5 (21):376.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   128 citations  
  • Name-bearing, reference, and circularity.Aidan Gray - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 171 (2):207-231.
    Proponents of the predicate view of names explain the reference of an occurrence of a name N by invoking the property of bearing N. They avoid the charge that this view involves a vicious circularity by claiming that bearing N is not itself to be understood in terms of the reference of actual or possible occurrences of N. I argue that this approach is fundamentally mistaken. The phenomenon of ‘reference transfer’ shows that an individual can come to bear a name (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Symposium: On What there is.P. T. Geach, A. J. Ayer & W. V. Quine - 1948 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 25 (1):125-160.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   303 citations  
  • Domain of discourse.Christopher Gauker - 1997 - Mind 106 (421):1-32.
    The proposition expressed by an utterance of a quantified sentence depends on a domain of discourse somehow determined by the context. How does the context of utterance determine the content of the domain of discourse? Many philosophers would approach this question from the point of view of an expressive theory of linguistic communication, according to which the primary function of language is to enable speakers to convey the propositional contents of their thoughts to hearers. This paper argues that from this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Ueber Sinn und Bedeutunq (on sense and reference).Gottlob Frege - 2000 - In Robert J. Stainton (ed.), Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language: A Concise Anthology. Broadview Press. pp. 45-64.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • Sense and reference.Gottlob Frege - 1948 - Philosophical Review 57 (3):209-230.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   190 citations  
  • You can call me 'stupid', ... just don't call me stupid.Delia Graff Fara - 2011 - Analysis 71 (3):492-501.
    In this paper I argue that names are predicates when they occur in the appellation position of 'called'-predications. This includes not only proper names, but all names -- including quote-names of proper names and quote-names of other words or phrases. Thus in "You can call me Al", the proper name 'Al' is a predicate. And in "You can call me 'Al'," the quote-name of 'Al' -- namely ' 'Al' ' -- is also a predicate.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Reference and definite descriptions.Keith S. Donnellan - 1966 - Philosophical Review 75 (3):281-304.
    Definite descriptions, I shall argue, have two possible functions. 1] They are used to refer to what a speaker wishes to talk about, but they are also used quite differently. Moreover, a definite description occurring in one and the same sentence may, on different occasions of its use, function in either way. The failure to deal with this duality of function obscures the genuine referring use of definite descriptions. The best known theories of definite descriptions, those of Russell and Strawson, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   740 citations  
  • Variabilism.Samuel Cumming - 2008 - Philosophical Review 117 (4):525-554.
    Variabilism is the view that proper names (like pronouns) are semantically represented as variables. Referential names, like referential pronouns, are assigned their referents by a contextual variable assignment (Kaplan 1989). The reference parameter (like the world of evaluation) may also be shifted by operators in the representation language. Indeed verbs that create hyperintensional contexts, like ‘think’, are treated as operators that simultaneously shift the world and assignment parameters. By contrast, metaphysical modal operators shift the world of assessment only. Names, being (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Reference and proper names.Tyler Burge - 1973 - Journal of Philosophy 70 (14):425-439.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   192 citations  
  • Proper names as predicates.Steven E. Boër - 1975 - Philosophical Studies 27 (6):389 - 400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Good news about the description theory of names.Bart Geurts - 1997 - Journal of Semantics 14 (4):319-348.
    This is an attempt at reviving Kneale's version of the description theory of names, which says that a proper name is synonymous with a definite description of the form ‘the individual named so-and-so’. To begin with, I adduce a wide range of observations to show that names and overt definites are alike in all relevant respects. I then turn to Kripke's main objection against Kneale's proposal, and endeavour to refute it. In the remainder of the paper I elaborate on Kneale's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations