Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A note on negation.CharlesB Daniels - 1990 - Erkenntnis 32 (3):423 - 429.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • On a three-valued logical calculus and its application to the analysis of the paradoxes of the classical extended functional calculus.D. A. Bochvar & Merrie Bergmann - 1981 - History and Philosophy of Logic 2 (1-2):87-112.
    A three-valued propositional logic is presented, within which the three values are read as ?true?, ?false? and ?nonsense?. A three-valued extended functional calculus, unrestricted by the theory of types, is then developed. Within the latter system, Bochvar analyzes the Russell paradox and the Grelling-Weyl paradox, formally demonstrating the meaninglessness of both.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • A story semantics for implication.Charles Daniels - 1986 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 27 (2):221-246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Formal inconsistency and evolutionary databases.Walter A. Carnielli, João Marcos & Sandra De Amo - 2000 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 8 (2):115-152.
    This paper introduces new logical systems which axiomatize a formal representation of inconsistency (here taken to be equivalent to contradictoriness) in classical logic. We start from an intuitive semantical account of inconsistent data, fixing some basic requirements, and provide two distinct sound and complete axiomatics for such semantics, LFI1 and LFI2, as well as their first-order extensions, LFI1* and LFI2*, depending on which additional requirements are considered. These formal systems are examples of what we dub Logics of Formal Inconsistency (LFI) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Don't care was made to care.Ross Brady & Richard Routley - 1973 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 51 (3):211 – 225.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Proof Systems for Reasoning about Computation Errors.Arnon Avron & Beata Konikowska - 2009 - Studia Logica 91 (2):273-293.
    In the paper we examine the use of non-classical truth values for dealing with computation errors in program specification and validation. In that context, 3-valued McCarthy logic is suitable for handling lazy sequential computation, while 3-valued Kleene logic can be used for reasoning about parallel computation. If we want to be able to deal with both strategies without distinguishing between them, we combine Kleene and McCarthy logics into a logic based on a non-deterministic, 3-valued matrix, incorporating both options as a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Reflections on the Logic of Nonsense.Lennart Åqvist - 1962 - Theoria 28 (1):138--57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Tautological entailments.Alan Ross Anderson & Nuel D. Belnap - 1962 - Philosophical Studies 13 (1-2):9 - 24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Tautological Entailments.Alan Ross Anderson & Nuel D. Belnap - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (4):608-608.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Lectures on the Curry-Howard isomorphism.Morten Heine Sørensen - 2007 - Boston: Elsevier. Edited by Paweł Urzyczyn.
    The Curry-Howard isomorphism states an amazing correspondence between systems of formal logic as encountered in proof theory and computational calculi as found in type theory. For instance, minimal propositional logic corresponds to simply typed lambda-calculus, first-order logic corresponds to dependent types, second-order logic corresponds to polymorphic types, sequent calculus is related to explicit substitution, etc. The isomorphism has many aspects, even at the syntactic level: formulas correspond to types, proofs correspond to terms, provability corresponds to inhabitation, proof normalization corresponds to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Possibility.[author unknown] - 1937 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 124 (11):274-275.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Possibility. [REVIEW][author unknown] - 1930 - The Monist 40 (2):324-324.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Knowledge and Belief: An Introduction to the Logic of the Two Notions.Jaakko Hintikka - 1962 - Studia Logica 16:119-122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   664 citations  
  • How a computer should think.Nuel Belnap - 1977 - In Gilbert Ryle (ed.), Contemporary aspects of philosophy. Boston: Oriel Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   155 citations  
  • Symbolic logic.Clarence Irving Lewis - 1932 - [New York]: Dover Publications. Edited by Cooper Harold Langford.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  • Knowledge and belief.Jaakko Hintikka - 1962 - Ithaca, N.Y.,: Cornell University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   710 citations  
  • The logic of significance and context.Leonard Goddard - 1973 - New York,: Wiley. Edited by Richard Sylvan.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Dynamic Logic.Lenore D. Zuck & David Harel - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (4):1480.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   159 citations  
  • Free Choice Disjunction and Epistemic Possibility.Thomas Ede Zimmermann - 2000 - Natural Language Semantics 8 (4):255-290.
    This paper offers an explanation of the fact that sentences of the form (1) ‘X may A or B’ may be construed as implying (2) ‘X may A and X may B’, especially if they are used to grant permission. It is suggested that the effect arises because disjunctions are conjunctive lists of epistemic possibilities. Consequently, if the modal may is itself epistemic, (1) comes out as equivalent to (2), due to general laws of epistemic logic. On the other hand, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  • Knowledge and Belief: An Introduction to the Logic of the Two Notions.Alan R. White - 1965 - Philosophical Quarterly 15 (60):268.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   222 citations  
  • A semantical theory of analytic implication.Alasdair Urquhart - 1973 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 2 (2):212 - 219.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Sense without Denotation.Timothy Smiley - 1959 - Analysis 20 (6):125 - 135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Reflections on the Logic of Nonsense.Krister Segerberg - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (1):134-136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A contribution to nonsense-logics.Krister Segerberg - 1965 - Theoria 31 (3):199-217.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Reflections on the Logic of Nonsense.Lennart Åqvist - 1962 - Theoria 28 (2):138-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The logic of paradox.Graham Priest - 1979 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 8 (1):219 - 241.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   442 citations  
  • Paraconsistency and Analyticity.Carlos A. OLLER - 1999 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 7 (1):91-99.
    William Parry conceived in the early thirties a theory of entail-
    ment, the theory of analytic implication, intended to give a formal expression to the idea that the content of the conclusion of a valid argument must be included in the content of its premises. This paper introduces a system of analytic, paraconsistent and quasi-classical propositional logic that does not validate the paradoxes of Parry’s analytic implication. The interpretation of the expressions of this logic will be given in terms of a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Semantical Analysis of Intuitionistic Logic I.Saul A. Kripke - 1963 - In Michael Dummett & J. N. Crossley (eds.), Formal Systems and Recursive Functions: Proceedings of the Eighth Logic Colloquium, Oxford July 1963. North Holland. pp. 92-130.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   108 citations  
  • Semantical Analysis of Intuitionistic Logic I.Saul A. Kripke, J. N. Crossley & M. A. E. Dummett - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (2):330-332.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Analytic implication.Kit Fine - 1986 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 27 (2):169-179.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • A modification of Parry's analytic implication.J. Michael Dunn - 1972 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 13 (2):195-205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Dynamic Logic.David Harel, Dexter Kozen & Jerzy Tiuryn - 2000 - MIT Press.
    This book provides the first comprehensive introduction to Dynamic Logic. Among the many approaches to formal reasoning about programs, Dynamic Logic enjoys the singular advantage of being strongly related to classical logic. Its variants constitute natural generalizations and extensions of classical formalisms. For example, Propositional Dynamic Logic (PDL) can be described as a blend of three complementary classical ingredients: propositional calculus, modal logic, and the algebra of regular events. In First-Order Dynamic Logic (DL), the propositional calculus is replaced by classical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  • The Logic of Nonsense.Sören Halldén - 1949 - Uppsala, Sweden: Upsala Universitets Arsskrift.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • A question concerning a logical calculus related to Lewis' System of strict implication, which is of special interest for the study of entailment.Sören Halldén - 1948 - Theoria 14 (3):265-269.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Philosophically Plausible Formal Interpretation of Intuitionistic Logic.Andrzej Grzegorczyk - 1971 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 36 (2):329-329.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Logic of Significance and Context.Nino B. Cocchiarella - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (4):1413-1415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The collected papers of Gerhard Gentzen.Gerhard Gentzen - 1969 - Amsterdam,: North-Holland Pub. Co.. Edited by M. E. Szabo.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • Investigations into Logical Deduction.Gerhard Gentzen, M. E. Szabo & Paul Bernays - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (1):144-145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Is semantic information meaningful data?Luciano Floridi - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (2):351-370.
    There is no consensus yet on the definition of semantic information. This paper contributes to the current debate by criticising and revising the Standard Definition of semantic Information (SDI) as meaningful data, in favour of the Dretske‐Grice approach: meaningful and well‐formed data constitute semantic information only if they also qualify as contingently truthful. After a brief introduction, SDI is criticised for providing necessary but insufficient conditions for the definition of semantic information. SDI is incorrect because truth‐values do not supervene on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • Intuitive semantics for first-degree entailments and 'coupled trees'.J. Michael Dunn - 1976 - Philosophical Studies 29 (3):149-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   229 citations  
  • The completeness of S.Harry Deutsch - 1979 - Studia Logica 38 (2):137 - 147.
    The subsystem S of Parry's AI [10] (obtained by omitting modus ponens for the material conditional) is axiomatized and shown to be strongly complete for a class of three valued Kripke style models. It is proved that S is weakly complete for the class of consistent models, and therefore that Ackermann's rule is admissible in S. It also happens that S is decidable and contains the Lewis system S4 on translation — though these results are not presented here. S is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Paraconsistent analytic implication.Harry Deutsch - 1984 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 13 (1):1 - 11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Relevant Logics and Their Rivals.Richard Routley, Val Plumwood, Robert K. Meyer & Ross T. Brady - 1982 - Ridgeview. Edited by Richard Sylvan & Ross Brady.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   204 citations  
  • An Introduction to Substructural Logics.Greg Restall - 1999 - New York: Routledge.
    This book introduces an important group of logics that have come to be known under the umbrella term 'susbstructural'. Substructural logics have independently led to significant developments in philosophy, computing and linguistics. _An Introduction to Substrucural Logics_ is the first book to systematically survey the new results and the significant impact that this class of logics has had on a wide range of fields.The following topics are covered: * Proof Theory * Propositional Structures * Frames * Decidability * Coda Both (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   202 citations  
  • Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Neccessity, Vol. I.Alan Ross Anderson & Nuel D. Belnap - 1975 - Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. Edited by Nuel D. Belnap & J. Michael Dunn.
    In spite of a powerful tradition, more than two thousand years old, that in a valid argument the premises must be relevant to the conclusion, twentieth-century logicians neglected the concept of relevance until the publication of Volume I of this monumental work. Since that time relevance logic has achieved an important place in the field of philosophy: Volume II of Entailment brings to a conclusion a powerful and authoritative presentation of the subject by most of the top people working in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   187 citations  
  • Investigations into Logical Deduction.Gerhard Gentzen - 1964 - American Philosophical Quarterly 1 (4):288 - 306.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   146 citations  
  • Symbolic Logic.C. I. Lewis & C. H. Langford - 1932 - Erkenntnis 4 (1):65-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   219 citations  
  • A useful four-valued logic.N. D. Belnap - 1977 - In J. M. Dunn & G. Epstein (eds.), Modern Uses of Multiple-Valued Logic. D. Reidel.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   259 citations  
  • Bilattices are nice things.Melvin Fitting - 2006 - In T. Bolander, V. Hendricks & S. A. Pedersen (eds.), Self-Reference. CSLI Publications.
    One approach to the paradoxes of self-referential languages is to allow some sentences to lack a truth value (or to have more than one). Then assigning truth values where possible becomes a fixpoint construction and, following Kripke, this is usually carried out over a partially ordered family of three-valued truth-value assignments. Some years ago Matt Ginsberg introduced the notion of bilattice, with applications to artificial intelligence in mind. Bilattices generalize the structure Kripke used in a very natural way, while making (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • The logic of the catuskoti.Graham Priest - 2010 - Comparative Philosophy 1 (2):24-54.
    In early Buddhist logic, it was standard to assume that for any state of a ff airs there were four possibilities: that it held, that it did not, both, or neither. This is the catuskoti (or tetralemma). Classical logicians have had a hard time mak­ing sense of this, but it makes perfectly good sense in the se­mantics of various paraconsistent logics, such as First Degree Entailment. Matters are more complicated for later Buddhist thinkers, such as Nagarjuna, who appear to suggest (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations