Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A formulation of the simple theory of types.Alonzo Church - 1940 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 5 (2):56-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   225 citations  
  • Principia Mathematica.A. N. Whitehead & B. Russell - 1927 - Annalen der Philosophie Und Philosophischen Kritik 2 (1):73-75.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   365 citations  
  • My Basic Conceptions of Probability and Induction, PA Schilpp ed.Rudolf Carnap - 1963 - In Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.), The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. La Salle, Ill.,: Open Court.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   139 citations  
  • Intellectual Autobiography.Rudolf Carnap - 1963 - In Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.), The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. La Salle, Ill.,: Open Court. pp. 3--84.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   219 citations  
  • Leon Chwistek, The Principles of the Pure Type Theory , translated by Adam Trybus with an Introductory Note by Bernard Linsky.Adam Trybus - 2012 - History and Philosophy of Logic 33 (4):329-352.
    ‘The Principles of the Pure Type Theory’ is a translation of Leon Chwistek's 1922 paper ‘Zasady czystej teorii typów’. It summarizes Chwistek's results from a series of studies of the logic of Whitehead and Russell's Principia Mathematica which were published between 1912 and 1924. Chwistek's main argument involves a criticism of the axiom of reducibility. Moreover, ‘The Principles of the Pure Type Theory’ is a source for Chwistek's views on an issue in Whitehead and Russell's ‘no-class theory of classes’ involving (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938.I. Grattan-Guinness - 1956 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (1):281-282.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Carnap’s early metatheory: scope and limits.Georg Schiemer, Richard Zach & Erich Reck - 2017 - Synthese 194 (1):33-65.
    In Untersuchungen zur allgemeinen Axiomatik and Abriss der Logistik, Carnap attempted to formulate the metatheory of axiomatic theories within a single, fully interpreted type-theoretic framework and to investigate a number of meta-logical notions in it, such as those of model, consequence, consistency, completeness, and decidability. These attempts were largely unsuccessful, also in his own considered judgment. A detailed assessment of Carnap’s attempt shows, nevertheless, that his approach is much less confused and hopeless than it has often been made out to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Foundations of Mathematics and other Logical Essays.Frank Plumpton Ramsey, R. B. Braithwaite & G. E. Moore - 1931 - Mind 40 (160):476-482.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   221 citations  
  • From a Logical Point of View.Richard M. Martin - 1955 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 15 (4):574-575.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   566 citations  
  • Carnap and logical truth.Willard van Orman Quine - 1954 - Synthese 12 (4):350--74.
    Kant's question 'How are synthetic judgments a priori possible?' pre- cipitated the Critique of Pure Reason. Question and answer notwith- standing, Mill and others persisted in doubting that such judgments were possible at all. At length some of Kant's own clearest purported.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   213 citations  
  • Ontology and the Vicious Circle Principle.Stanley C. Martens - 1976 - Philosophical Review 85 (2):256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Predicative fragments of Frege arithmetic.Øystein Linnebo - 2004 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 10 (2):153-174.
    Frege Arithmetic (FA) is the second-order theory whose sole non-logical axiom is Hume’s Principle, which says that the number of F s is identical to the number of Gs if and only if the F s and the Gs can be one-to-one correlated. According to Frege’s Theorem, FA and some natural definitions imply all of second-order Peano Arithmetic. This paper distinguishes two dimensions of impredicativity involved in FA—one having to do with Hume’s Principle, the other, with the underlying second-order logic—and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Russell's Metaphysical Logic.[author unknown] - 2001 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 63 (1):176-177.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Carnap’s dream: Gödel, Wittgenstein, and Logical, Syntax.S. Awodey & A. W. Carus - 2007 - Synthese 159 (1):23-45.
    In Carnap’s autobiography, he tells the story how one night in January 1931, “the whole theory of language structure” in all its ramifications “came to [him] like a vision”. The shorthand manuscript he produced immediately thereafter, he says, “was the first version” of Logical Syntax of Language. This document, which has never been examined since Carnap’s death, turns out not to resemble Logical Syntax at all, at least on the surface. Wherein, then, did the momentous insight of 21 January 1931 (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Hitting a Moving Target: Gödel, Carnap, and Mathematics as Logical Syntax.Gregory Lavers - 2019 - Philosophia Mathematica 27 (2):219-243.
    From 1953 to 1959 Gödel worked on a response to Carnap’s philosophy of mathematics. The drafts display Gödel’s familiarity with Carnap’s position from The Logical Syntax of Language, but they received a dismissive reaction on their eventual, posthumous, publication. Gödel’s two principal points, however, will here be defended. Gödel, though, had wished simply to append a few paragraphs to show that the same arguments apply to Carnap’s later views. Carnap’s position, however, had changed significantly in the intervening years, and to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Why Ramify?Harold T. Hodes - 2015 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 56 (2):379-415.
    This paper considers two reasons that might support Russell’s choice of a ramified-type theory over a simple-type theory. The first reason is the existence of purported paradoxes that can be formulated in any simple-type language, including an argument that Russell considered in 1903. These arguments depend on certain converse-compositional principles. When we take account of Russell’s doctrine that a propositional function is not a constituent of its values, these principles turn out to be too implausible to make these arguments troubling. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Semantics in Carnap.Warren Goldfarb - 1997 - Philosophical Topics 25 (2):51-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • On gödel's way in: The influence of Rudolf Carnap.Warren Goldfarb - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (2):185-193.
    The philosopher Rudolf Carnap, although not himself an originator of mathematical advances in logic, was much involved in the development of the subject. He was the most important and deepest philosopher of the Vienna Circle of logical positivists, or, to use the label Carnap later preferred, logical empiricists. It was Carnap who gave the most fully developed and sophisticated form to the linguistic doctrine of logical and mathematical truth: the view that the truths of mathematics and logic do not describe (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Diskussion zur grundlegung der mathematik.Kurt Gödel - 1931 - Erkenntnis 2 (1):135-151.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Carnap's Noncognitivism about Ontology.Vera Flocke - 2020 - Noûs 54 (3):527-548.
    Do numbers exist? Carnap (1956 [1950]) famously argues that this question can be understood in an “internal” and in an “external” sense, and calls “external” questions “non-cognitive”. Carnap also says that external questions are raised “only by philosophers” (p. 207), which means that, in his view, philosophers raise ”non-cognitive” questions. However, it is not clear how the internal/external distinction and Carnap’s related views about philosophy should be understood. This paper provides a new interpretation. I draw attention to Carnap’s distinction between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Combinatory Logic.Haskell B. Curry, J. Roger Hindley & Jonathan P. Seldin - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (1):109-110.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • The Logical Syntax of Language.Rudolph Carnap - 1936 - Philosophical Review 46 (5):549-553.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   219 citations  
  • Speaking of everything.Richard L. Cartwright - 1994 - Noûs 28 (1):1-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic.R. M. Martin - 1957 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 18 (4):558-559.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • Die logizistische grundlegung der mathematik.Rudolf Carnap - 1931 - Erkenntnis 2 (1):91-105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Bericht über untersuchungen zur allgemeinen axiomatik.Rudolf Carnap - 1930 - Erkenntnis 1 (1):303-307.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Carnap, completeness, and categoricity:The gabelbarkeitssatz OF 1928. [REVIEW]S. Awodey & A. W. Carus - 2001 - Erkenntnis 54 (2):145-172.
    In 1929 Carnap gave a paper in Prague on Investigations in General Axiomatics; a briefsummary was published soon after. Its subject lookssomething like early model theory, and the mainresult, called the Gabelbarkeitssatz, appears toclaim that a consistent set of axioms is complete justif it is categorical. This of course casts doubt onthe entire project. Though there is no furthermention of this theorem in Carnap''s publishedwritings, his Nachlass includes a largetypescript on the subject, Investigations inGeneral Axiomatics. We examine this work here,showing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • On the Concept of Following Logically.Alfred Tarski - 2002 - History and Philosophy of Logic 23 (3):155-196.
    We provide for the first time an exact translation into English of the Polish version of Alfred Tarski's classic 1936 paper, whose title we translate as ?On the Concept of Following Logically?. We also provide in footnotes an exact translation of all respects in which the German version, used as the basis of the previously published and rather inexact English translation, differs from the Polish. Although the two versions are basically identical, to an extent that is even uncanny, we note (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • 9 Carnap's logical syntax.Gary Ebbs - 2001 - In Richard Gaskin (ed.), Grammar in early twentieth-century philosophy. New York: Routledge. pp. 218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A refutation of an unjustified attack on the axiom of reducibility.John Myhill - 1979 - In Bertrand Russell & George Washington Roberts (eds.), Bertrand Russell memorial volume. New York: Humanities Press. pp. 81--90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Carnap's principle of tolerance, empiricism, and conventionalism.Thomas Ricketts - 1994 - In Peter Clark & Bob Hale (eds.), Reading Putnam. Blackwell. pp. 176--200.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations