Switch to: Citations

References in:

Suspended judgment

Philosophical Studies 162 (2):165-181 (2013)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)Confidence and Coarse-Grained Attitudes.Scott Sturgeon - 2010 - Oxford Studies in Epistemology 3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • The Language of Not Doing.Myles Brand - 1971 - American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (1):45 - 53.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Being of Two Minds: Belief with Doubt.Nathan Salmon - 1995 - Noûs 29 (1):1-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • A solution for Russellians to a puzzle about belief.Sean Crawford - 2004 - Analysis 64 (3):223-29.
    According to Russellianism (or Millianism), the two sentences ‘Ralph believes George Eliot is a novelist’ and ‘Ralph believes Mary Ann Evans is a novelist’ cannot diverge in truth-value, since they express the same proposition. The problem for the Russellian (or Millian) is that a puzzle of Kaplan’s seems to show that they can diverge in truth-value and that therefore, since the Russellian holds that they express the same proposition, the Russellian view is contradictory. I argue that the standard Russellian appeal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • The aim of belief.Ralph Wedgwood - 2002 - Philosophical Perspectives 16:267-97.
    It is often said, metaphorically, that belief "aims" at the truth. This paper proposes a normative interpretation of this metaphor. First, the notion of "epistemic norms" is clarified, and reasons are given for the view that epistemic norms articulate essential features of the beliefs that are subject to them. Then it is argued that all epistemic norms--including those that specify when beliefs count as rational, and when they count as knowledge--are explained by a fundamental norm of correct belief, which requires (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   371 citations  
  • Understanding belief reports.David Braun - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (4):555-595.
    In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection. The theory is Russellianism, sometimes also called `neo-Russellianism', `Millianism', `the direct reference theory', `the "Fido"-Fido theory', or `the naive theory'. The objection concernssubstitution of co-referring names in belief sentences. Russellianism implies that any two belief sentences, that differ only in containing distinct co-referring names, express the same proposition (in any given context). Since `Hesperus' and `Phosphorus' both refer to the planet Venus, this view implies that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  • Evidentialism: essays in epistemology.Earl Conee & Richard Feldman - 2004 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by Richard Feldman.
    Evidentialism is a view about the conditions under which a person is epistemically justified in having a particular doxastic attitude toward a proposition. Evidentialism holds that the justified attitudes are determined entirely by the person's evidence. This is the traditional view of justification. It is now widely opposed. The essays included in this volume develop and defend the tradition. Evidentialism has many assets. In addition to providing an intuitively plausible account of epistemic justification, it helps to resolve the problem of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • Defeaters and higher-level requirements.Michael Bergmann - 2005 - Philosophical Quarterly 55 (220):419–436.
    Internalists tend to impose on justification higher-level requirements, according to which a belief is justified only if the subject has a higher-level belief (i.e., a belief about the epistemic credentials of a belief). I offer an error theory that explains the appeal of this requirement: analytically, a belief is not justified if we have a defeater for it, but contingently, it is often the case that to avoid having defeaters, our beliefs must satisfy a higher-level requirement. I respond to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   124 citations  
  • Illogical Belief.Nathan Salmon - 1989 - Philosophical Perspectives 3:243-285.
    A sequel to the author’s book /Frege’s Puzzle/ (1986).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations  
  • Evidentialism: Essays in Epistemology.Earl Conee & Richard Feldman - 2006 - Philosophical Quarterly 56 (222):147-149.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   215 citations  
  • Refraining, Omitting, and Negative Acts.Kent Bach - 2010 - In Timothy O'Connor & Constantine Sandis (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Action. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 50–57.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Ways of Failing to Do Something Refraining Omitting Negative Acts: Inaction as Action? References.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Person and Object.Roderick Chisholm - 1976 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 39 (2):281-283.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   244 citations  
  • Outlines of Pyrrhonism.Sextus Empiricus - 1990 - Harvard University Press. Edited by R. G. Bury.
    Throughout history philosophers have sought to define, understand, and delineate concepts important to human well-being. One such concept is "knowledge." Many philosophers believed that absolute, certain knowledge, is possible--that the physical world and ideas formulated about it could be given solid foundation unaffected by the varieties of mere opinion. Sextus Empiricus stands as an example of the "skeptic" school of thought whose members believed that knowledge was either unattainable or, if a genuine possibility, the conditions necessary to achieve it were (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • (1 other version)The agnostic subtly probabilified.C. van Fraassen Bas - 1998 - Analysis 58 (3):212–220.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Beyond Singular Propositions?Scott Soames - 1995 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25 (4):515 - 549.
    Propositional attitudes, like believing and asserting, are relations between agents and propositions. Agents are individuals who do the believing and asserting; propositions are things that are believed and asserted. Propositional attitude ascriptions are sentences that ascribe propositional attitudes to agents. For example, a propositional attitude ascription α believes, or asserts, that S is true iff the referent of a bears the relation of believing, or asserting, to the proposition expressed by s. The questions I will address have to do with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Outlines of Pyrrhonism.Sextus Empiricus - 2020 - Sententiae 39 (2):125-137.
    The first Ukrainian translation of the classic work of ancient skepticism, Sextus Empiricus’ Outlines of Pyrrhonism, made by D. of Sc. Philology Lesia Zvonska under the scientific editorship of Dr. of Sc. in Philosophy. Oleg Khoma.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Agnostic Subtly Probabilified.Bas C. van Fraassen - 1998 - Analysis 58 (3):212-220.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Agnosticism meets bayesianism.Alan Hájek - 1998 - Analysis 58 (3):199–206.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • (1 other version)Confidence and coarse-grained attitudes.Scott Sturgeon - 2005 - In Tamar Szabó Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology. Oxford University Press. pp. 3--126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Bayesian agnosticism and constructive empiricism.Bradley Monton - 1998 - Analysis 58 (3):207–212.
    This paper addresses the question: how should the traditional doxastic attitude of agnosticism be represented in a Bayesian framework? Bas van Fraassen has one proposal: a Bayesian is agnostic about a proposition if her opinion about the proposition is represented by a probability interval with zero as the lower limit. I argue that van Fraassen's proposal is not adequate. Mark Kaplan claims that this leads to a problem with constructive empiricism; I show that Kaplan's claim is incorrect.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Sextus, Descartes, Hume, and Peirce: On securing settled doxastic states.Louis Loeb - 1998 - Noûs 32 (2):205-230.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Refraining.Robert E. Moore - 1979 - Philosophical Studies 36 (4):407 - 424.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Agnosticism meets Bayesianism.Alan H.Ájek - 1998 - Analysis 58 (3):199-206.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations