Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Kant on the Ethics of Belief.Alix Cohen - 2014 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 114 (3pt3):317-334.
    In this paper, I explore the possibility of developing a Kantian account of the ethics of belief by deploying the tools provided by Kant's ethics. To do so, I reconstruct epistemic concepts and arguments on the model of their ethical counterparts, focusing on the notions of epistemic principle, epistemic maxim and epistemic universalizability test. On this basis, I suggest that there is an analogy between our position as moral agents and as cognizers: our actions and our thoughts are subject to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The Logical Conscience.Jonathan Dancy - 1977 - Analysis 37 (2):81 - 84.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The Search for Logically Alien Thought.James Conant - 1992 - Philosophical Topics 20 (1):115-180.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Kant's concepts of justification.Andrew Chignell - 2007 - Noûs 41 (1):33–63.
    An essay on Kant's theory of justification, where by “justification” is meant the evaluative concept that specifies conditions under which a propositional attitude is rationally acceptable with a moderate-to-high degree of confidence. Kant employs both epistemic and non-epistemic concepts of justification: an epistemic concept of justification sets out conditions under which a propositional attitude is rationally acceptable with a moderate-to-high degree of confidence and a candidate (if true and Gettier-immune) for knowledge. A non-epistemic concept of justification, by contrast, sets out (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Merit, Meaning, and Human Bondage: An Essay on Free Will.Nomy Arpaly - 2006 - Princeton University Press.
    Perhaps everything we think, feel, and do is determined, and humans--like stones or clouds--are slaves to the laws of nature. Would that be a terrible state? Philosophers who take the incompatibilist position think so, arguing that a deterministic world would be one without moral responsibility and perhaps without true love, meaningful art, and real rationality. But compatibilists and semicompatibilists argue that determinism need not worry us. As long as our actions stem, in an appropriate way, from us, or respond in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • Kant. [REVIEW]Karl Ameriks - 1980 - Teaching Philosophy 3 (3):359-363.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • On Naturalizing Kant's Transcendental Psychology.Henry E. Allison - 1995 - Dialectica 49 (2‐4):335-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Hegel's Critique of Kant: From Dichotomy to Identity.Sally S. Sedgwick - 2012 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Sally Sedgwick presents a fresh account of Hegel's critique of Kant's theoretical philosophy. She argues that Hegel offers a compelling critique of and alternative to the conception of cognition that Kant defended in his 'Critical' period, and explores Hegel's claim to derive from Kantian doctrines clues to a superior form of idealism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Kant and the Normativity of Logic.Clinton Tolley - 2008 - In Valerio Rohden, Ricardo R. Terra, Guido Antonio de Almeida & Margit Ruffing (eds.), Recht und Frieden in der Philosophie Kants Akten des X. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. De Gruyter. pp. vol. 5, 215-227.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Kant and the Normativity of Logic.Margit Ruffing, Guido A. De Almeida, Ricardo R. Terra & Valerio Rohden - 2008 - In Margit Ruffing, Guido A. De Almeida, Ricardo R. Terra & Valerio Rohden (eds.), Law and Peace in Kant's Philosophy/Recht und Frieden in der Philosophie Kants: Proceedings of the 10th International Kant Congress/Akten des X. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Walter de Gruyter.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kant and the Spontaneity of the Understanding.Stefanie Grüne - 2013 - In Dina Emundts (ed.), Self, World, and Art: Metaphysical Topics in Kant and Hegel. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 145-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Unsociable Sociability.Allen W. Wood - 1991 - Philosophical Topics 19 (1):325-351.
    Kant holds that the moral principle is a priori, not empirical. But consistently with this, important parts of Kantian ethics, including his formulations of the moral principle, depend on a rich and interesting empirical theory of human nature.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Kant on the Nature of Logical Laws.Clinton Tolley - 2006 - Philosophical Topics 34 (1-2):371-407.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Kant’s Puzzling Ethics of Maxims.Jens Timmermann - 2000 - The Harvard Review of Philosophy 8 (1):39-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Kant's Commitment to Metaphysics of Morals.L. Nandi Theunissen - 2013 - European Journal of Philosophy 24 (1):103-128.
    A definitive feature of Kant's moral philosophy is its rationalism. Kant insists that moral theory, at least at its foundation, cannot take account of empirical facts about human beings and their circumstances in the world. This is the core of Kant's commitment to ‘metaphysics of morals’, and it is what he sees as his greatest contribution to moral philosophy. The paper clarifies what it means to be committed to metaphysics of morals, why Kant is committed to it, and where he (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Kant on the Spontaneity of Mind.Robert B. Pippin - 1987 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (2):449 - 475.
    In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant refers often and with no apparent hesitation or sense of ambiguity to the mind. He does so not only in his justly famous destruction of rationalist proofs of immaterialism, but throughout his own, positive, ‘transcendental’ account in the Transcendental Aesthetic and Transcendental Analytic. In the first edition of the Critique, he even proposed what he adventurously called a ‘transcendental psychology’ and, although this strange discipline seemed to disappear in the second edition, he left (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant’s Pure General Logic.Tyke Nunez - 2018 - Mind 128 (512):1149-1180.
    There are two ways interpreters have tended to understand the nature of the laws of Kant’s pure general logic. On the first, these laws are unconditional norms for how we ought to think, and will govern anything that counts as thinking. On the second, these laws are formal criteria for being a thought, and violating them makes a putative thought not a thought. These traditions are in tension, in so far as the first depends on the possibility of thoughts that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Priority of Practical Reason in Kant.Sasha Mudd - 2013 - European Journal of Philosophy 24 (1):78-102.
    Throughout the critical period Kant enigmatically insists that reason is a ‘unity’, thereby suggesting that both our theoretical and practical endeavors are grounded in one and the same rational capacity. How Kant's unity thesis ought to be interpreted and whether it can be substantiated remain sources of controversy in the literature. According to the strong reading of this claim, reason is a ‘unity’ because all our reasoning, including our theoretical reasoning, functions practically. Although several prominent commentators endorse this view, it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On the Transcendental Freedom of the Intellect.Colin McLear - 2020 - Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 7:35-104.
    Kant holds that the applicability of the moral ‘ought’ depends on a kind of agent-causal freedom that is incompatible with the deterministic structure of phenomenal nature. I argue that Kant understands this determinism to threaten not just morality but the very possibility of our status as rational beings. Rational beings exemplify “cognitive control” in all of their actions, including not just rational willing and the formation of doxastic attitudes, but also more basic cognitive acts such as judging, conceptualizing, and synthesizing.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Are Moral Requirements Hypothetical Imperatives?John McDowell & I. G. McFetridge - 1978 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 52 (1):13-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   224 citations  
  • Are Moral Requirements Hypothetical Imperatives?John McDowell & I. G. McFetridge - 1978 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 52 (1):13-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   210 citations  
  • Maxims in Kant's practical philosophy.Richard R. McCarty - 2006 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 44 (1):65-83.
    : A standard interpretation of Kantian "maxims" sees them as expressing reasons for action, implying that we cannot act without a maxim. But recent challenges to this interpretation claim that Kant viewed acting on maxims as optional. Kant's understanding of maxims derives from Christian Wolff, who regarded maxims as major premises of the practical syllogism. This supports the standard interpretation. Yet Kant also viewed commitments to maxims as essential for virtue and character development, which supports challenges to the standard interpretation, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Kant and the Normativity of Logic.Huaping Lu‐Adler - 2017 - European Journal of Philosophy 25 (2):207-230.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Kant on Freedom of Empirical Thought.Markus Kohl - 2015 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 53 (2):301-26.
    It is standardly assumed that, in Kant, “free agency” is identical to moral agency and requires the will or practical reason. Likewise, it is often held that the concept of “spontaneity” that Kant uses in his theoretical philosophy is very different from, and much thinner than, his idea of practical spontaneity. In this paper I argue for the contrary view: Kant has a rich theory of doxastic free agency, and the spontaneity in empirical thought (which culminates in judgments of experience) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Is the Categorical Imperative the Highest Principle of Both Pure Practical and Theoretical Reason?Heiner F. Klemme - 2014 - Kantian Review 19 (1):119-126.
    In her new book, Patricia Kitcher supports Onora O'Neill's view that the categorical imperative is the highest principle of both practical and theoretical reason. I claim that neither O'Neill's original interpretation nor Kitcher's additional evidence in favour of it are convincing. At its core, this misconception of Kant's position consists in the identification of self-referential critique of reason with the concept of autonomy. It will be shown that the (Kant) of both practical and theoretical reason is not the categorical imperative, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What Is a Maxim?Patricia Kitcher - 2003 - Philosophical Topics 31 (1-2):215-243.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Practice of Moral Judgment.Barbara Herman - 1985 - Journal of Philosophy 82 (8):414.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   263 citations  
  • The Unity of Reason.Paul Guyer - 1989 - The Monist 72 (2):139-167.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Unity of Reason.Paul Guyer - 1989 - The Monist 72 (2):139-167.
    Understanding provides one form of unity in our experience—let us say, at least for the sake of illustration, that form of unity constituted by the capacity to assign any given experiences a uniquely determined place relative to any other given experiences in the ideal chronology of our experience as a whole. But the unity of experience does not, as Kant sees things, exhaust the forms of unity among our representations which we must seek. In addition to the unity of experience (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reason and reflective judgment: Kant on the significance of systematicity.Paul Guyer - 1990 - Noûs 24 (1):17-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Recent work on Kantian maxims II.Rob Gressis - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (3):228-239.
    Maxims play a crucial role in Kant's ethical philosophy, but there is significant disagreement about what maxims are. In this two-part essay, I survey eight different views of Kantian maxims, presenting their strengths and their weaknesses. In Part II: New Approaches, I look at three more recent views in somewhat greater detail than I do the five treatments canvassed in 'Recent Works on Kantian Maxims I: Established Approaches'. First, there is Richard McCarty's Interpretation, which holds that Kant's understanding of maxims (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Recent work on Kantian maxims I: Established approaches.Rob Gressis - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (3):216-227.
    Maxims play a crucial role in Kant's ethical philosophy, but there is significant disagreement about what maxims are. In this two-part essay, I survey eight different views of Kantian maxims, presenting their strengths, and their weaknesses. Part I: Established Approaches, begins with Rüdiger Bubner's view that Kant took maxims to be what ordinary people of today take them to be, namely pithily expressed precepts of morality or prudence. Next comes the position, most associated with Rüdiger Bittner and Otfried Höffe, that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Morality as a system of hypothetical imperatives.Philippa Foot - 1972 - Philosophical Review 81 (3):305-316.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   323 citations  
  • Understanding and sensibility.Stephen Engstrom - 2006 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 49 (1):2 – 25.
    Kant holds that the human cognitive power is divided into two "stems", understanding and sensibility. This doctrine has seemed objectionably dualistic to many critics, who see these stems as distinct parts, each able on its own to produce representations, which must somehow interact, determining or constraining one another, in order to secure the fit, requisite for cognition, between concept and intuition. This reading cannot be squared, however, with what Kant actually says about theoretical cognition and the way understanding and sensibility (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • The form of practical knowledge: a study of the categorical imperative.Stephen P. Engstrom - 2009 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    Introduction -- Part I: Willing as practical knowing -- The will and practical judgment -- Fundamental practical judgments : the wish for happiness -- Part II: From presuppositions of judgment to the idea of a categorical imperative -- The formal presuppositions of practical judgment -- Constraints on willing -- Part III: Interpretation -- The categorical imperative -- Applications -- Conclusion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations  
  • Sensibility and Understanding.S. Engstrorn - 2006 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 49 (1):2-25.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Kant on the Unity of Theoretical and Practical Reason.Pauline Kleingeld - 1998 - Review of Metaphysics 52 (2):500-528.
    In his critical works of the 1780's, Kant claims, seemingly inconsistently, that (1) theoretical and practical reason are one and the same reason, applied differently, (2) that he still needs to show that they are, and (3) that theoretical and practical reason are united. I first argue that current interpretations of Kant's doctrine of the unity of reason are insufficient. But rather than concluding that Kant’s doctrine becomes coherent only in the Critique of Judgment, I show that the three statements (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The Bounds of Sense: An Essay on Kant's "Critique of Pure Reason.".P. R. Strawson, Jonathan Bennett, D. P. Dryer & Arnulf Zweig - 1967 - Ethics 78 (1):89-90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • Review: Hoffe, Immanuel Kant.Karl Ameriks - 1985 - Review of Metaphysics 38 (3):636-637.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations