Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Freedom and Fulfillment: Philosophical Essays.Joel Feinberg - 1992 - Princeton University Press.
    This collection concludes with two essays dealing with concepts used in appraising the whole of a person's life: absurdity and self-fulfillment, and their interplay.Dealing with a diverse set of problems in practical and theoretical ethics, ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • Furthering the Case for Anti-natalism: Seana Shiffrin and the Limits of Permissible Harm.Asheel Singh - 2012 - South African Journal of Philosophy 31 (1):104-116.
    Anti-natalism is the view that it is (almost) always wrong to bring people (and perhaps all sentient beings) into existence. This view is most famously defended by David Benatar (1997, 2006). There are, however, other routes to an anti-natal conclusion. In this respect, Seana Shiffrin’s paper, “Wrongful Life, Procreative Responsibility, and the Significance of Harm” (1999), has been rather neglected in the natal debate. Though she appears unwilling to conclude that procreation is always wrong, I believe that she in fact (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Immorality of Procreation.Jimmy Alfonso Licon - 2012 - Think 11 (32):85-91.
    In this paper, I argue the practice of procreation is immoral regardless of the consequences of human presence such as climate change and overpopulation; the lack of consent, interests and moral desert on the part of nonexistent individuals means someone could potentially suffer in the absence of moral justification. Procreation is only morally justified if there is some method for acquiring informed consent from a non-existent person; but that is impossible; therefore, procreation is immoral.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Paternalism and Subsequent Consent.Donald Van De Veer - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9 (4):631 - 642.
    Some philosophers believe that appeals to promoting or maximizing good consequences are a suspect way of attempting to justify coercive interference with another person's actions. Suppose that is true. If there is a presumption that individuals have a right not to be coercively interfered with, then, foregoing utilitarian type appeals, it would seem that the only way to justify coercive interference of a paternalistic sort would be to show that under certain conditions the presumption fails.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Procreative Beneficence: Why We Should Select the Best Children.Julian Savulescu - 2001 - Bioethics 15 (5-6):413-426.
    We have a reason to use information which is available about such genes in our reproductive decision-making; (3) couples should selec.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   274 citations  
  • Human reproduction: irrational but in most cases morally defensible.R. Bennett - 2004 - Journal of Medical Ethics 30 (4):379-380.
    While I am inclined to agree that in most cases a choice to become pregnant and bring to birth a child is an irrational choice, unlike Professor Häyry,1 I believe that choosing to do so is far from being necessarily immoral. In fact I will argue that it is often these irrational choices which make human life the valuable commodity many of us believe it is.Häyry argues that not only is the choice to have children always an irrational choice, but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Constraints on freedom.David Miller - 1983 - Ethics 94 (1):66-86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • What’s up with anti-natalists? An observational study on the relationship between dark triad personality traits and anti-natalist views.Philipp Schönegger - 2022 - Philosophical Psychology 35 (1):66-94.
    In the past decade, research on the dark triad of personality (Machiavellianism, narcissism, and psychopathy) has demonstrated a strong relationship to a number of socially aversive moral judgments such as sacrificial utilitarian decisions in moral dilemmas. This study widens the scope of this research program and investigates the association between dark triad personality traits and anti-natalist views, i.e., views holding that procreation is morally wrong. The results of this study indicate that the dark triad personality traits of Machiavellianism and psychopathy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Antinatalism and Moral Particularism.Gerald K. Harrison - 2019 - Essays in Philosophy 20 (1):66-88.
    I believe most acts of human procreation are immoral, and I believe this despite also believing in the truth of moral particularism. In this paper I explain why. I argue that procreative acts possess numerous features that, in other contexts, seem typically to operate with negative moral valences. Other things being equal this gives us reason to believe they will operate negatively in the context of procreative acts as well. However, most people’s intuitions represent procreative acts to be morally permissible (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Hypothetical Consent Objection to Anti-Natalism.Asheel Singh - 2018 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 21 (5):1135-1150.
    A very common but untested assumption is that potential children would consent to be exposed to the harms of existence in order to experience its benefits. And so, would-be parents might appeal to the following view: Procreation is all-things-considered permissible, as it is morally acceptable for one to knowingly harm an unconsenting patient if one has good reasons for assuming her hypothetical consent—and procreators can indeed reasonably rely on some notion of hypothetical consent. I argue that this view is in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Why We Should Reject S.Derek Parfit - 1984 - In Reasons and Persons. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    An argument against the bias towards the near; how a defence of temporal neutrality is not a defence of S; an appeal to inconsistency; why we should reject S and accept CP.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1179 citations  
  • Quality of life in cancer patients--an hypothesis.K. C. Calman - 1984 - Journal of Medical Ethics 10 (3):124-127.
    Quality of life is a difficult concept to define and to measure. An hypothesis is proposed which suggests that the quality of life measures the difference, or the gap, at a particular period of time between the hopes and expectations of the individual and that individual's present experiences. Quality of life can only be described by the individual, and must take into account many aspects of life. The approach is goal-orientated, and one of task analysis. The hypothesis is developed in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • I. Professor Narveson's utilitarianism.Timothy L. S. Sprigge - 1968 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 11 (1-4):332-346.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Utilitarianism and new generations.Jan Narveson - 1967 - Mind 76 (301):62-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   111 citations  
  • On Risk-Based Arguments for Anti-natalism.Erik Magnusson - 2022 - Journal of Value Inquiry 56 (1):101-117.
    In this paper, I explore the prospects for risk-based arguments in favour of anti-natalism, which explain the wrongness of procreation in terms of wrongful risk-imposition on the resultant child. After considering and rejecting two risk-based arguments from the existing literature - David Benatar's and Matti Häyry's - I propose a more promising version that focuses on the lack of appropriate justification for imposing the risks of existence, namely, one that refers to the essential interests of the child on whom those (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Just Better Utilitarianism.Matti Häyry - 2021 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 30 (2):343-367.
    Utilitarianism could still be a viable moral and political theory, although an emphasis on justice as distributing burdens and benefits has hidden this from current conversations. The traditional counterexamples prove that we have good grounds for rejecting classical, aggregative forms of consequentialism. A nonaggregative, liberal form of utilitarianism is immune to this rejection. The cost is that it cannot adjudicate when the basic needs of individuals or groups are in conflict. Cases like this must be solved by other methods. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Negative utilitarianism.R. N. Smart - 1958 - Mind 67 (268):542-543.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • (1 other version)Wrongful Life, Procreative Responsibility, and the Significance of Harm.Seana Shiffrin - 1999 - Legal Theory 5 (2):117-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   222 citations  
  • Social Philosophy.Stephen Pink & Joel Feinberg - 1975 - Philosophical Review 84 (2):306.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • A rational cure for prereproductive stress syndrome.M. Hayry - 2004 - Journal of Medical Ethics 30 (4):377-378.
    Since human reproduction is arguably both irrational and immoral, those who seek help before conceiving could be advised it is all right not to have children.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Procreative beneficence and the prospective parent.P. Herissone-Kelly - 2006 - Journal of Medical Ethics 32 (3):166-169.
    Julian Savulescu has given clear expression to a principle—that of “procreative beneficence”—which underlies the thought of many contemporary writers on bioethics. The principle of procreative beneficence holds that parents or single reproducers are at least prima facie obliged to select the child, out of a range of possible children they might have, who will be likely to lead the best life. My aim in this paper is to argue that prospective parents, just by dint of their being prospective parents, are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Causation, Responsibility, and Harm: How the Discursive Shift from Law and Ethics to Social Justice Sealed the Plight of Nonhuman Animals.Matti Häyry - 2020 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 29 (2):246-267.
    Moral and political philosophers no longer condemn harm inflicted on nonhuman animals as self-evidently as they did when animal welfare and animal rights advocacy was at the forefront in the 1980s, and sentience, suffering, species-typical behavior, and personhood were the basic concepts of the discussion. The article shows this by comparing the determination with which societies seek responsibility for human harm to the relative indifference with which law and morality react to nonhuman harm. When harm is inflicted on humans, policies (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Procreative justice: A contractualist account.Rivka M. Weinberg - 2002 - Public Affairs Quarterly 16 (4):405-425.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Hard and soft offers as constraints.Matti Häyry & Timo Airaksinen - 1988 - Philosophia 18 (4):385-398.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Elements of Constraint.Matti Häyry & Timo Airaksinen - 1988 - Analyse & Kritik 10 (1):32-47.
    This paper analyses the various effects of threats and offers on freedom. Both threats and offers are related to social power. Threats are part of coercion and they are constraints. We try to say why this is so. Offers are more problematic. We identify soft and hard offers, or offers that can be refused and those that cannot. Hard offers have several interesting features, especially in relation to individual preference orders and sets of action alternatives. This paper studies problems which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wonderwoman and Superman: The Ethics of Human Biotechnology.John Harris - 1993 - Philosophy 68 (264):248-250.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • The Morality of Naturalness.Tuija Takala - 2004 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 13 (1):15-19.
    In discussions among nonphilosophers, the ethical argument from naturalness frequently comes up. “Of course, cloning should be banned—it is unnatural.” “Surely you cannot deny that homosexuality is unnatural.” “The immorality of gene technology is apparent because things like that do not happen in nature. Genes do not jump between species and crossbreeding produces infertile offspring.” Even those who come from a philosophical background can catch themselves thinking, “That is unnatural!” and finding grounds for suspicion from the thought. But what do (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Ulysses and the Sirens: Studies in Rationality and Irrationality.Jon Elster - 1979 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 48 (4):650-651.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   205 citations  
  • Threats, Offers, Law, Opinion and Liberty.J. P. Day - 1977 - American Philosophical Quarterly 14 (4):257 - 272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations