Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The spatial presence of spirits among the cartesians.Jasper William Reid - 2008 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 46 (1):91-117.
    : The Cartesians have often been read as if they denied spatial presence to incorporeal substances, reserving it for extended things alone. This article explores whether this common interpretation is accurate, examining the cases of both created minds and the divine substance of God Himself. Through scrutiny of the relevant texts of both Descartes himself and his followers, it demonstrates that, in the divine case, this common interpretation is incorrect, and that the Cartesians did believe that God’s own substance really (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Gravity and Newton’s Substance Counting Problem.Hylarie Kochiras - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 40 (3):267-280.
    A striking feature of Newton’s thought is the very broad reach of his empiricism, potentially extending even to immaterial substances, including God, minds, and should one exist, a non-perceiving immaterial medium. Yet Newton is also drawn to certain metaphysical principles—most notably the principle that matter cannot act where it is not—and this second, rationalist feature of his thought is most pronounced in his struggle to discover ‘gravity’s cause’. The causal problem remains vexing, for he neither invokes primary causation, nor accepts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • (1 other version)Newton as Philosopher. [REVIEW]Lisa Downing - 2011 - Philosophical Review 120 (1):124-129.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Locke’s Newtonianism and Lockean Newtonianism.Lisa J. Downing - 1997 - Perspectives on Science 5 (3):285-310.
    I explore Locke’s complex attitude toward the natural philosophy of his day by focusing on Locke’s own treatment of Newton’s theory of gravity and the presence of Lockean themes in defenses of Newtonian attraction/gravity by Maupertuis and other early Newtonians. In doing so, I highlight the inadequacy of an unqualified labeling of Locke as “mechanist” or “Newtonian.”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Newton on action at a distance and the cause of gravity.Steffen Ducheyne - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (1):154-159.
    In this discussion paper, I seek to challenge Hylarie Kochiras’ recent claims on Newton’s attitude towards action at a distance, which will be presented in Section 1. In doing so, I shall include the positions of Andrew Janiak and John Henry in my discussion and present my own tackle on the matter . Additionally, I seek to strengthen Kochiras’ argument that Newton sought to explain the cause of gravity in terms of secondary causation . I also provide some specification on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Principia: Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy.Isaac Newton - 1999 - University of California Press.
    Presents Newton's unifying idea of gravitation and explains how he converted physics from a science of explanation into a general mathematical system.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   197 citations  
  • Qualities, Properties, and Laws in Newton’s Induction.David Marshall Miller - 2009 - Philosophy of Science 76 (5):1052-1063.
    Newton’s argument for universal gravitation in the Principia eventually rested on the third “Rule of Philosophizing,” which warrants the generalization of “qualities of bodies.” An analysis of the rule and the history of its development indicate that the term ‘quality’ should be taken to include both inherent properties of bodies and relations among systems of bodies, generalized into `laws'. By incorporating law‐induction into the rule, Newton could legitimately rebuff objections to his theory by claiming that universal gravitation was justified by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica.Isaac Newton - 1726 - Filozofia 56 (5):341-354.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   198 citations  
  • Substance and Action in Descartes and Newton.Andrew Janiak - 2010 - The Monist 93 (4):657-677.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Works of John Locke, in Nine Volumes.John Locke - 2019 - Hardpress Publishing.
    This is a reproduction of the original artefact. Generally these books are created from careful scans of the original. This allows us to preserve the book accurately and present it in the way the author intended. Since the original versions are generally quite old, there may occasionally be certain imperfections within these reproductions. We're happy to make these classics available again for future generations to enjoy!
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Newton and Kant: Quantity of matter in the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science.Michael Friedman - 2012 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 50 (3):482-503.
    Immanuel Kant's Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science (1786) provides metaphysical foundations for the application of mathematics to empirically given nature. The application that Kant primarily has in mind is that achieved in Isaac Newton's Principia (1687). Thus, Kant's first chapter, the Phoronomy, concerns the mathematization of speed or velocity, and his fourth chapter, the Phenomenology, concerns the empirical application of the Newtonian notions of true or absolute space, time, and motion. This paper concentrates on Kant's second and third chapters—the Dynamics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Newton’s substance monism, distant action, and the nature of Newton’s empiricism: discussion of H. Kochiras “Gravity and Newton’s substance counting problem”.Eric Schliesser - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (1):160-166.
    This paper is a critical response to Hylarie Kochiras’ “Gravity and Newton’s substance counting problem,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 40 267–280. First, the paper argues that Kochiras conflates substances and beings; it proceeds to show that Newton is a substance monist. The paper argues that on methodological grounds Newton has adequate resources to respond to the metaphysical problems diagnosed by Kochiras. Second, the paper argues against the claim that Newton is committed to two speculative doctrines attributed to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Gravity and De gravitatione: the development of Newton’s ideas on action at a distance.John Henry - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (1):11-27.
    This paper is in three sections. The first establishes that Newton, in spite of a well-known passage in a letter to Richard Bentley of 1692, did believe in action at a distance. Many readers may see this merely as an act of supererogation, since it is so patently obvious that he did. However, there has been a long history among Newton scholars of allowing the letter to Bentley to over-ride all of Newton’s other pronouncements in favour of action at a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Newton: The Classical Scholia.Paolo Casini - 1984 - History of Science 22 (1):1-46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Kant's Gesammelte Schriften.Immanuel Kant - 1928
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  • Kant’s dynamical theory of matter in 1755, and its debt to speculative Newtonian experimentalism.Michela Massimi - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (4):525-543.
    This paper explores the scientific sources behind Kant’s early dynamic theory of matter in 1755, with a focus on two main Kant’s writings: Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens and On Fire. The year 1755 has often been portrayed by Kantian scholars as a turning point in the intellectual career of the young Kant, with his much debated conversion to Newton. Via a careful analysis of some salient themes in the two aforementioned works, and a reconstruction of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • (1 other version)Reviews Newton as philosopher by Andrew Janiak cambridge university press, 2008, £45 / $90 isbn 978-0-521-86286-.Michela Massimi - 2010 - Philosophy 85 (1):157-163.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Isaac Newton's Papers and Letters on Natural Philosophy", ed. by I. Bernard Cohen. [REVIEW]Dirk Struik - 1959 - Science and Society 23 (3):279-282.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Newton's metaphysics.Howard Stein - 2002 - In The Cambridge Companion to Newton. Cambridge University Press. pp. 256--307.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • (1 other version)Newton as Philosopher. [REVIEW]Lisa Downing - 2010 - Philosophical Review 119 (3):124-129.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Descartes and the Problem of Action at a Distance.Patrick Suppes - 1954 - Journal of the History of Ideas 15 (1/4):146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Reviews: Newton as Philosopher By Andrew Janiak. [REVIEW]Michela Massimi - 2010 - Philosophy 85 (1):157-163.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Enduring Question of Action at a Distance in Saint Albert the Great.Francis J. Kovach - 1979 - Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 10 (3):161-235.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations