Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Language, Truth and Logic.[author unknown] - 1937 - Erkenntnis 7 (1):123-125.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   323 citations  
  • Reductive theories of modality.Theodore Sider - 2003 - In Michael J. Loux & Dean W. Zimmerman (eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 180-208.
    Logic begins but does not end with the study of truth and falsity. Within truth there are the modes of truth, ways of being true: necessary truth and contingent truth. When a proposition is true, we may ask whether it could have been false. If so, then it is contingently true. If not, then it is necessarily true; it must be true; it could not have been false. Falsity has modes as well: a false proposition that could not have been (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • Statements partly about observation.David Lewis - 1988 - Philosophical Papers 17 (1):1-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  • Some remarks on "protocol sentences".Richard Creath - 1987 - Noûs 21 (4):471-475.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On Kaplan on Carnap on significance.Richard Creath - 1976 - Philosophical Studies 30 (6):393 - 400.
    In 'the methodological character of theoretical concepts' carnap offered a sophisticated criterion of empirical significance. Unfortunately, Shortly thereafter david kaplan devised a pair of devastating counter-Examples which appeared to show that carnap's criterion was simultaneously too wide and too narrow. In this note I show that kaplan's first counter-Example misses its mark and that his second counter-Example can be avoided by a natural generalization of carnap's method.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Every dogma has its day.Richard Creath - 1991 - Erkenntnis 35 (1-3):347-389.
    This paper is a reexamination of Two Dogmas in the light of Quine's ongoing debate with Carnap over analyticity. It shows, first, that analytic is a technical term within Carnap's epistemology. As such it is intelligible, and Carnap's position can meet Quine's objections. Second, it shows that the core of Quine's objection is that he has an alternative epistemology to advance, one which appears to make no room for analyticity. Finally, the paper shows that Quine's alternative epistemology is itself open (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Revisability and Conceptual Change in "Two Dogmas of Empiricism".David J. Chalmers - 2011 - Journal of Philosophy 108 (8):387-415.
    W.V. Quine’s article “Two Dogmas of Empiricism” is one of the most influential works in 20thcentury philosophy. The article is cast most explicitly as an argument against logical empiricists such as Carnap, arguing against the analytic/synthetic distinction that they appeal to along with their verificationism. But the article has been read much more broadly as an attack on the notion..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The methodological character of theoretical concepts.R. Carnap - 1956 - Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 1 (1):38--76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   233 citations  
  • Testability and Meaning.Rudolf Carnap - 1951 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 16 (2):137-137.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  • Testability and meaning (part 2).Rudolf Carnap - 1937 - Philosophy of Science 4 (4):1-40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   182 citations  
  • Testability and meaning.Rudolf Carnap - 1936 - Philosophy of Science 3 (4):419-471.
    Two chief problems of the theory of knowledge are the question of meaning and the question of verification. The first question asks under what conditions a sentence has meaning, in the sense of cognitive, factual meaning. The second one asks how we get to know something, how we can find out whether a given sentence is true or false. The second question presupposes the first one. Obviously we must understand a sentence, i.e. we must know its meaning, before we can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   341 citations  
  • Testability and meaning (part 1).Rudolf Carnap - 1936 - Philosophy of Science 3 (4):420-71.
    Two chief problems of the theory of knowledge are the question of meaning and the question of verification. The first question asks under what conditions a sentence has meaning, in the sense of cognitive, factual meaning. The second one asks how we get to know something, how we can find out whether a given sentence is true or false. The second question presupposes the first one. Obviously we must understand a sentence, i.e. we must know its meaning, before we can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   228 citations  
  • Rudolf Carnap, Logical Empiricist.Brian Carr & Jaakko Hintikka - 1977 - Philosophical Quarterly 27 (109):364.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Intellectual autobiography.Aaron Ben-Ze’ev - 2008 - Philosophia 36 (3):255-276.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Language, truth and logic.Alfred Jules Ayer - 1936 - London,: V. Gollancz.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   570 citations  
  • The Duhem thesis.Roger Ariew - 1984 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 35 (4):313-325.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • The philosophy of David Kaplan.Joseph Almog & Paolo Leonardi (eds.) - 2010 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This volume collects new, previously unpublished articles on Kaplan, analyzing a broad spectrum of topics ranging from cutting edge linguistics and the ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Legacy of Logical Positivism: Studies in the Philosophy of Science.Peter Achinstein & Stephen Francis Barker (eds.) - 1969 - Baltimore,: Johns Hopkins University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Legacy of Logical Positivism.Boruch A. Brody - 1972 - Philosophy of Science 39 (1):102-104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Legacy of Logical Positivism. [REVIEW]Robert Ackermann - 1970 - Journal of Philosophy 67 (11):388-391.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Metaphysics after Carnap : the ghost who walks?Huw Price - 2007 - In David Chalmers, David Manley & Ryan Wasserman (eds.), Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Oxford University Press. pp. 320--46.
    To appear in David Chalmers, Ryan Wasserman and David Manley, eds., Metametaphysics (OUP, 2009).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • Testability and Meaning.Rudolf Carnap - 2011 - Literary Licensing, LLC.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   158 citations  
  • Positivism and the Pragmatic Theory of Observation.Thomas Oberdan - 1990 - In Oberdan Thomas (ed.), Contributed Papers. Psa: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. pp. 25--37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Two Dogmas of Empiricism.W. Quine - 1951 - [Longmans, Green].
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1206 citations  
  • Testability.Elliott Sober - 1999 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 73 (2):47-76.
    That some propositions are testable, while others are not, was a fundamental idea in the philosophical program known as logical empiricism. That program is now widely thought to be defunct. Quine’s (1953) “Two Dogmas of Empiricism” and Hempel’s (1950) “Problems and Changes in the Empiricist Criterion of Meaning” are among its most notable epitaphs. Yet, as we know from Mark Twain’s comment on an obituary that he once had the pleasure of reading about himself, the report of a death can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Quine.Elliott Sober & Peter Hylton - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74:237-299.
    [Elliott Sober] In 'Two Dogmas of Empiricism', Quine attacks the analytic/synthetic distinction and defends a doctrine that I call epistemological holism. Now, almost fifty years after the article's appearance, what are we to make of these ideas? I suggest that the philosophical naturalism that Quine did so much to promote should lead us to reject Quine's brief against the analytic/synthetic distinction; I also argue that Quine misunderstood Carnap's views on analyticity. As for epistemological holism, I claim that this thesis does (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Quine.Elliott Sober & Peter Hylton - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74:237-299.
    In 'Two Dogmas of Empiricism', Quine attacks the analytic/synthetic distinction and defends a doctrine that I call epistemological holism. Now, almost fifty years after the article's appearance, what are we to make of these ideas? I suggest that the philosophical naturalism that Quine did so much to promote should lead us to reject Quine's brief against the analytic/synthetic distinction; I also argue that Quine misunderstood Carnap's views on analyticity. As for epistemological holism, I claim that this thesis does not follow (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Quine, I.Elliott Sober - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74 (1):237–280.
    In 'Two Dogmas of Empiricism', Quine attacks the analytic/synthetic distinction and defends a doctrine that I call epistemological holism. Now, almost fifty years after the article's appearance, what are we to make of these ideas? I suggest that the philosophical naturalism that Quine did so much to promote should lead us to reject Quine's brief against the analytic/synthetic distinction; I also argue that Quine misunderstood Carnap's views on analyticity. As for epistemological holism, I claim that this thesis does not follow (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • I_– _Elliott Sober.Elliott Sober - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74 (1):237-280.
    In ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’, Quine attacks the analytic/synthetic distinction and defends a doctrine that I call epistemological holism. Now, almost fifty years after the article’s appearance, what are we to make of these ideas? I suggest that the philosophical naturalism that Quine did so much to promote should lead us to reject Quine’s brief against the analytic/synthetic distinction; I also argue that Quine misunderstood Carnap's views on analyticity. As for epistemological holism, I claim that this thesis does not follow (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • I_– _Elliott Sober.Elliott Sober - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74 (1):237-280.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The unreliability of naive introspection.Eric Schwitzgebel - 2006 - Philosophical Review 117 (2):245-273.
    We are prone to gross error, even in favorable circumstances of extended reflection, about our own ongoing conscious experience, our current phenomenology. Even in this apparently privileged domain, our self-knowledge is faulty and untrustworthy. We are not simply fallible at the margins but broadly inept. Examples highlighted in this essay include: emotional experience (for example, is it entirely bodily; does joy have a common, distinctive phenomenological core?), peripheral vision (how broad and stable is the region of visual clarity?), and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   267 citations  
  • A note on Carnap's meaning criterion.William W. Rozeboom - 1960 - Philosophical Studies 11 (3):33 - 38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Two Dogmas of Empiricism.W. V. Quine - 1951 - Philosophical Review 60 (1):20-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   602 citations  
  • Two Dogmas of Empiricism.Willard V. O. Quine - 1951 - Philosophical Review 60 (1):20–43.
    Modern empiricism has been conditioned in large part by two dogmas. One is a belief in some fundamental cleavage between truths which are analytic, or grounded in meanings independently of matters of fact, and truth which are synthetic, or grounded in fact. The other dogma is reductionism: the belief that each meaningful statement is equivalent to some logical construct upon terms which refer to immediate experience. Both dogmas, I shall argue, are ill founded. One effect of abandoning them is, as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1335 citations  
  • On Carnap’s Views on Ontology.Willard van Orman Quine - 1951 - Philosophical Studies 2 (5):65--72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • Should we trust our intuitions? Deflationary accounts of the analytic data.Eric Margolis & Stephen Laurence - 2003 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 103 (3):299-323.
    At least since W. V. O. Quine's famous critique of the analytic/synthetic distinction, philosophers have been deeply divided over whether there are any analytic truths. One line of thought suggests that the simple fact that people have ' intuitions of analyticity' might provide an independent argument for analyticities. If defenders of analyticity can explain these intuitions and opponents cannot, then perhaps there are analyticities after all. We argue that opponents of analyticity have some unexpected resources for explaining these intuitions and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Eleanor Bisbee. Confusion about exclusive and exceptive propositions. The philosophical review, vol. 46 (1937), pp. 85–88. [REVIEW]Henry S. Leonard & Rudolf Carnap - 1937 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 2 (1):49-49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • The Emperor’s New Intuitions.Jaakko Hintikka - 1999 - Journal of Philosophy 96 (3):127-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • Theory and Evidence.Clark N. Glymour - 1980 - Princeton University Press.
    The Description for this book, Theory and Evidence, will be forthcoming.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   373 citations  
  • The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of Psychology and Psychoanalysis. [REVIEW]C. A. Mace - 1958 - Philosophical Review 67 (3):397-401.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Does mathematics need new axioms.Solomon Feferman, Harvey M. Friedman, Penelope Maddy & John R. Steel - 1999 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 6 (4):401-446.
    Part of the ambiguity lies in the various points of view from which this question might be considered. The crudest di erence lies between the point of view of the working mathematician and that of the logician concerned with the foundations of mathematics. Now some of my fellow mathematical logicians might protest this distinction, since they consider themselves to be just more of those \working mathematicians". Certainly, modern logic has established itself as a very respectable branch of mathematics, and there (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • Evidence and Evolution: The Logic Behind the Science.Elliott Sober - 2008 - Cambridge University Press.
    How should the concept of evidence be understood? And how does the concept of evidence apply to the controversy about creationism as well as to work in evolutionary biology about natural selection and common ancestry? In this rich and wide-ranging book, Elliott Sober investigates general questions about probability and evidence and shows how the answers he develops to those questions apply to the specifics of evolutionary biology. Drawing on a set of fascinating examples, he analyzes whether claims about intelligent design (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   181 citations  
  • Rudolf Carnap, logical empiricist: materials and perspectives.Jaakko Hintikka (ed.) - 1975 - Boston: D. Reidel Pub. Co..
    "Homage to Rudolph Carnap."--Hempel, C. G. Rudolf Carnap, logical empiricist.--Wedberg, A. How Carnap built the world in 1928.--Eberle, R. A construction of quality classes improved upon the Aufbau.--Carnap, R. Observation language and theoretical language.--Kaplan, D. Significance and analyticity: a comment of some recent proposals of Carnap.--Wójcicki, R. The factual content of empirical theories.--Williams, P. M. On the conservative extensions of semantical systems: a contribution to the problem of analyticity.--Winnie, J. A. Theoretical analyticity.--Wedberg, A. Decision and belief in science.--Bohnert, H. G. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science.Mary S. Morgan & Margaret Morrison (eds.) - 1999 - Cambridge University Press.
    Models as Mediators discusses the ways in which models function in modern science, particularly in the fields of physics and economics. Models play a variety of roles in the sciences: they are used in the development, exploration and application of theories and in measurement methods. They also provide instruments for using scientific concepts and principles to intervene in the world. The editors provide a framework which covers the construction and function of scientific models, and explore the ways in which they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   351 citations  
  • Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology.Ryan Wasserman, David Manley & David Chalmers (eds.) - 2009 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    This volume concerns the status and ambitions of metaphysics as a discipline.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   169 citations  
  • Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science.Herbert Feigl & Michael Scriven (eds.) - 1956 - , Vol.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   109 citations  
  • Empiricism and the philosophy of mind.Wilfrid Sellars - 1956 - Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 1:253-329.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1196 citations  
  • Language, Truth, and Logic.A. J. Ayer - 1936 - Philosophy 23 (85):173-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   758 citations  
  • Carnap and ontological pluralism.Matti Eklund - 2009 - In David Chalmers, David Manley & Ryan Wasserman (eds.), Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Oxford University Press. pp. 130--56.
    My focus here will be Rudolf Carnap’s views on ontology, as these are presented in the seminal “Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology” (1950). I will first describe how I think Carnap’s distinction between external and internal questions is best understood. Then I will turn to broader issues regarding Carnap’s views on ontology. With certain reservations, I will ascribe to Carnap an ontological pluralist position roughly similar to the positions of Eli Hirsch and the later Hilary Putnam. Then I turn to some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • The Logical Syntax of Language. [REVIEW]N. E. - 1937 - Journal of Philosophy 34 (11):303-304.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations