Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Kant's moral religion.Allen W. Wood - 1970 - Ithaca,: Cornell University Press.
    Kant's Moral Religion argues that Kant's doctrine of religious belief if consistent with his best critical thinking and, in fact, that the "moral arguments"--along with the faith they justify--are an integral part of Kant's critical thinking.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Zur diskussion.[author unknown] - 1997 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 79 (3):310-323.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Constructivism VS. Contractualism.Onora O'Neill - 2003 - Ratio 16 (4):319-331.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Contractarian Constructivism.Ronald Milo - 1995 - Journal of Philosophy 92 (4):181-204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Christine M. Korsgaard: Creating the Kingdom of Ends.James Lenman - 1998 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 1 (4):487-488.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   165 citations  
  • Back to Kant? No Way.Charles Larmore - 2003 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 46 (2):260-271.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kant and the Philosophy of History. [REVIEW]William A. Galston - 1983 - Philosophical Review 92 (2):288-291.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • O'Neill and Korsgaard on the Construction of Normativity.Eric Watkins & William Fitzpatrick - 2002 - Journal of Value Inquiry 36 (2-3):349-367.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Review: Ameriks, Karl, Autonomy and Idealism in and after Kant[REVIEW]Eric Watkins - 2004 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69 (3):728–741.
    Regardless of one’s particular philosophical interests and convictions, it is evident that the notion of autonomy is an important one. However, agreement about the nature of autonomy and about what it requires has proven elusive in contemporary discussions. In Kant and the Fate of Autonomy Karl Ameriks addresses this impasse by going back to the historical roots of this notion in Kant and arguing that many contemporary conceptions of autonomy are based on misunderstandings of Kant’s position, misunderstandings that first arose (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Fact of Reason. Kant’s Passage to Ordinary Moral Knowledge.Paweł Łuków - 1993 - Kant Studien 84 (2):204-221.
    The paper gives an interpretation of Kant's doctrine of the fact of reason against the background of a constructivist reading of his philosophy, which does not allow us to appeal to any indubitable facts. The fact of reason is the object of a philosophical account of the moral law forms the quid juris part of deduction or legitimization of the law. A more intuitive grasp of the fact is the phenomenon of reverence for duty which ordinary people grasp in form (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Opinion, belief or faith, and knowledge.Leslie Stevenson - 2003 - Kantian Review 7:72-101.
    Kant famously said he 'had to deny knowledge in order to make room for faith ’ . But what exactly was his conception of Glaube, and how does it fit into his epistemology? In the first Critique it is not until the concluding Method section that he explicitly addresses these issues. In the Canon of Pure Reason he lists three questions that sum up ‘all interest of my reason’: What can I know? What should I do? What may I hope? (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Moral realism: a defence.Russ Shafer-Landau - 2003 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Moral Realism is a systematic defence of the idea that there are objective moral standards. Russ Shafer-Landau argues that there are moral principles that are true independently of what anyone, anywhere, happens to think of them. His central thesis, as well as the many novel supporting arguments used to defend it, will spark much controversy among those concerned with the foundations of ethics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   584 citations  
  • Natural Law, Skepticism, and Methods of Ethics.J. B. Schneewind - 1991 - Journal of the History of Ideas 52 (2):289-308.
    In the Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals Kant presented a method for discovering what morality requires us to do in any situation and claimed that it is a method everyone can use. The method consists in testing one's maxim against the requirement stated in the formulations of the categorical imperative. There has been endless discussion of the adequacy of Kant's method in giving moral guidance, but there has been little effort to situate Kant's view of ethical method in its (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Two conceptions of the highest good in Kant.Andrews Reath - 1988 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 26 (4):593-619.
    This paper develops an interpretation of what is essential to kant's doctrine of the highest good, Which defends it while also explaining why it is often rejected. While it is commonly viewed as a theological ideal in which happiness is proportioned to virtue, The paper gives an account in which neither feature appears. The highest good is best understood as a state of affairs to be achieved through human agency, Containing the moral perfection of all individuals and the satisfaction of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Legislating the moral law.Andrews Reath - 1994 - Noûs 28 (4):435-464.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Lectures on the history of moral philosophy.John Rawls - 2000 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Edited by Barbara Herman.
    This book brings together the lectures that inspired a generation of students--and a regeneration of moral philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  • Kant's moral anti-realism.Frederick Rauscher - 2002 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 40 (4):477-499.
    I defend the claim that Kant is a moral antirealist, or (as he would state it) moral idealist. I first define moral realism and moral idealism, concluding that moral idealism requires that every moral property depend upon the minds of moral agents. Kant's metaethical theory is idealist regarding the nature of value, since it depends upon the voluntary choices of moral agents in pursuing particular ends, the nature of right, since the categorical imperative stems from moral agents' own reason, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Kant's two priorities of practical reason.Frederick Rauscher - 1998 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 6 (3):397 – 419.
    I find in Kant two distinct conceptions of the priority of practical over theoretical reason, focused on belief and on action. The former actually involves a higher priority of theoretical reason. The latter, in contrast, gives genuine priority to practical reason by noting that theoretical considerations are irrelevant in moral decision-making. I argue that the former conception requires one to abandon genuine priority of the practical, while the latter conception requires one to abandon the necessary unity of reason. I also (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kant's Legal Metaphor and the Nature of a Deduction.Ian Proops - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (2):209-229.
    This essay partly builds on and partly criticizes a striking idea of Dieter Henrich. Henrich argues that Kant's distinction in the first Critique between the question of fact (quid facti) and the question of law (quid juris) provides clues to the argumentative structure of a philosophical "Deduction". Henrich suggests that the unity of apperception plays a role analogous to a legal factum. By contrast, I argue, first, that the question of fact in the first Critique is settled by the Metaphysical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • 5. Kritik der praktischen Vernunft (§§ 7–8, 30–41).Onora O'Neill - 2002 - In Otfried Höffe (ed.), Immanuel Kant: Kritik der Praktischen Vernunft. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. pp. 81-97.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Constructivism VS. contractualism.Onora O'Neill - 2003 - Ratio 16 (4):319–331.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Constructions of reason: explorations of Kant's practical philosophy.Onora O'Neill - 1989 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Two centuries after they were published, Kant's ethical writings are as much admired and imitated as they have ever been, yet serious and long-standing accusations of internal incoherence remain unresolved. Onora O'Neill traces the alleged incoherences to attempts to assimilate Kant's ethical writings to modern conceptions of rationality, action and rights. When the temptation to assimilate is resisted, a strikingly different and more cohesive account of reason and morality emerges. Kant offers a "constructivist" vindication of reason and a moral vision (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   244 citations  
  • Making Sense of Kant’s Highest Good.Jacqueline Mariña & West Lafayette - 2000 - Kant Studien 91 (3):329-355.
    This paper explores Kant's concept of the highest good and the postulate of the existence of God arising from it. Kant has two concepts of the highest good standing in tension with one another, an immanent and a transcendent one. I provide a systematic exposition of the constituents of both variants and show how Kant’s arguments are prone to confusion through a conflation of both concepts. I argue that once these confusions are sorted out Kant’s claim regarding the need to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Back to Kant? No way.Charles Larmore - 2003 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 46 (2):260 – 271.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Kantian humility: our ignorance of things in themselves.Rae Langton - 1998 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Rae Langton offers a new interpretation and defense of Kant's doctrine of things in themselves. Kant distinguishes things in themselves from phenomena, and in so doing he makes a metaphysical distinction between intrinsic and relational properties of substances. Langton argues that his claim that we have no knowledge of things in themselves is not idealism, but epistemic humility: we have no knowledge of the intrinsic properties of substances. This interpretation vindicates Kant's scientific realism, and shows his primary/secondary quality distinction to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   130 citations  
  • Kant's Transcendental Deduction of God's Existence as a Postulate of Pure Practical Reason.Manfred Kuehn - 1985 - Kant Studien 76 (1-4):152-169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • How Kantian is Constructivism?Larry Krasnoff - 1999 - Kant Studien 90 (4):385-409.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Self-legislation in Kant's moral philosophy.Patrick Kain - 2004 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 86 (3):257-306.
    Kant famously insisted that “the idea of the will of every rational being as a universally legislative will” is the supreme principle of morality. Recent interpreters have taken this emphasis on the self-legislation of the moral law as evidence that Kant endorsed a distinctively constructivist conception of morality according to which the moral law is a positive law, created by us. But a closer historical examination suggests otherwise. Kant developed his conception of legislation in the context of his opposition to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Interpreting Kant's theory of divine commands.Patrick Kain - 2005 - Kantian Review 9:128-149.
    Several interpretive disagreements about Kant's theory of divine commands (esp. in the work of Allen Wood and John E. Hare) can be resolved with further attention to Kant's works. It is argued that Kant's moral theism included (at least until 1797) the claim that practical reason, reflecting upon the absolute authority of the moral law, should lead finite rational beings like us to believe that there exists an omnipotent, omniscient and holy being who commands our obedience to the moral law (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Immanuel Kant: Kritik der Praktischen Vernunft.Otfried Höffe (ed.) - 2002 - Berlin: Akademie Verlag.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Immanuel Kant: Kritik der Praktischen Vernunft.Otfried Höffe (ed.) - 2002 - Berlin: Akademie Verlag.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kant and the Claims of Knowledge.Ralf Meerbote - 1987 - Noûs 26 (3):391-396.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Kant's Doctrine of Transcendental Illusion.B. Longuenesse - 2003 - Mind 112 (448):718-724.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • The Practical Turn in Ethical Theory: Korsgaard’s Constructivism, Realism, and the Nature of Normativity.William J. FitzPatrick - 2005 - Ethics 115 (4):651-691.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • The concept of the highest good in Kant's moral theory.Stephen Engstrom - 1992 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (4):747-780.
    Kant claims that the concept of the highest good, the idea of happiness in proportion to virtue, is grounded in the moral law. But this claim has often been challenged. How can Kant justify including happiness in the highest good? Why should only the virtuous be worthy of happiness? This paper argues that when the moral law is interpreted as the criterion for valid application of the concept of the good, the concept of the highest good does indeed follow from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Kant's Transcendental Idealism: An Interpretation and Defense by Henry F. Allison. [REVIEW]Eckart Förster - 1985 - Journal of Philosophy 82 (12):734-738.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Kants Theory of Freedom. [REVIEW]Roger J. Sullivan - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (4):865-867.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kant's criticism of atheism.Lara Denis - 2003 - Kant Studien 94 (2):198-219.
    Although Kant argues that morality is prior to and independent of religion, Kant nevertheless claims that religion of a certain sort (“moral theism”) follows from morality, and that atheism poses threats to morality. Kant criticizes atheism as morally problematic in four ways: atheism robs the atheist of springs for moral action, leads the atheist to moral despair, corrupts the atheist’s moral character, and has a pernicious influence on the atheist’s community. I argue that Kant is right to say that moral (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Enlightenment, Revolution, and Romanticism: The Genesis of Modern German Political Thought, 1790-1800.Frederick Beiser - 1992 - Philosophical Review 103 (1):192-194.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Enlightenment, Revolution, and Romanticism: The Genesis of Modern German Political Thought, 1790–1800.Frederick C. Beiser - 1992 - Harvard University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Kant's Theory of Mind.Karl Ameriks - 1984 - Philosophical Quarterly 34 (137):514-515.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Kant and the Fate of Autonomy: Problems in the Appropriation of the Critical Philosophy.Paul Guyer - 2003 - Mind 112 (445):87-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Kant's Transcendental Idealism. [REVIEW]Arthur Melnick - 1985 - Philosophical Review 94 (1):134-136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   161 citations  
  • Kant's Transcendental Idealism.Henry E. Allison - 1988 - Yale University Press.
    This landmark book is now reissued in a new edition that has been vastly rewritten and updated to respond to recent Kantian literature.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   248 citations  
  • Things in themselves.Robert Merrihew Adams - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (4):801-825.
    The paper is an interpretation and defense of Kant's conception of things in themselves as noumena, along the following lines. Noumena are transempirical realities. As such they have several important roles in Kant's critical philosophy (Section 1). Our theoretical faculties cannot obtain enough content for a conception of noumena that would assure their real possibility as objects, but can establish their merely formal logical possibility (Sections 2-3). Our practical reason, however, grounds belief in the real possibility of some noumena, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Philosophical Ethics: An Historical And Contemporary Introduction.Stephen L. Darwall - 1997 - Westview Press.
    Why is ethics part of philosophy? Stephen Darwall's Philosophical Ethics introduces students to ethics from a distinctively philosophical perspective, one that weaves together central ethical questions such as "What has value?" and "What are our moral obligations?" with fundamental philosophical issues such as "What is value?" and "What can a moral obligation consist in?"With one eye on contemporary discussions and another on classical texts,Philosophical Ethics shows how Hobbes, Mill, Kant, Aristotle, and Nietzsche all did ethical philosophy how, for example, they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Kant's final synthesis: an essay on the Opus postumum.Eckart Förster - 2000 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    This is the first book in English devoted entirely to Kant's Opus postumum and its place in the Kantian oeuvre.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Vindicating reason.Onora O'Neill - 1992 - In Paul Guyer (ed.), The Cambridge companion to Kant. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 280--308.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • 13 Rational theology, moral faith, and religion.Allen W. Wood - 1992 - In Paul Guyer (ed.), The Cambridge companion to Kant. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 3--394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • 9 Constructivism in Rawls and Kant1.Onora O'neill - 2002 - In Samuel Freeman (ed.), The Cambridge companion to Rawls. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 347.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations