Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Refugees, Fairness and Taking up the Slack: On Justice and the International Refugee Regime.Owen David - 2016 - Moral Philosophy and Politics 3 (2).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Ideal vs. Non‐ideal Theory: A Conceptual Map. [REVIEW]Laura Valentini - 2012 - Philosophy Compass 7 (9):654-664.
    This article provides a conceptual map of the debate on ideal and non‐ideal theory. It argues that this debate encompasses a number of different questions, which have not been kept sufficiently separate in the literature. In particular, the article distinguishes between the following three interpretations of the ‘ideal vs. non‐ideal theory’ contrast: (i) full compliance vs. partial compliance theory; (ii) utopian vs. realistic theory; (iii) end‐state vs. transitional theory. The article advances critical reflections on each of these sub‐debates, and highlights (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   329 citations  
  • Political legitimacy and democracy.Allen Buchanan - 2002 - Ethics 112 (4):689-719.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • Democratic inclusion: Rainer Bauböck in dialogue.Rainer Bauböck (ed.) - 2017 - Manchester University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • What is the point of equality.Elizabeth Anderson - 1999 - Ethics 109 (2):287-337.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   981 citations  
  • Democratic Theory and Border Coercion.Arash Abizadeh - 2008 - Political Theory 36 (1):37-65.
    The question of whether or not a closed border entry policy under the unilateral control of a democratic state is legitimate cannot be settled until we first know to whom the justification of a regime of control is owed. According to the state sovereignty view, the control of entry policy, including of movement, immigration, and naturalization, ought to be under the unilateral discretion of the state itself: justification for entry policy is owed solely to members. This position, however, is inconsistent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   205 citations  
  • Strangers in Our Midst: The Political Philosophy of Immigration.David Miller - 2016 - Harvard University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   189 citations  
  • Survey Article: Internal Doubts about Cohen's Rescue of Justice.Patrick Tomlin - 2010 - Journal of Political Philosophy 18 (2):228-247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Neurolaw and Neuroprediction: Potential Promises and Perils.Walter Sinnott‐Armstrong Thomas Nadelhoffer - 2012 - Philosophy Compass 7 (9):631-642.
    Neuroscience has been proposed for use in the legal system for purposes of mind reading, assessment of responsibility, and prediction of misconduct. Each of these uses has both promises and perils, and each raises issues regarding the admissibility of neuroscientific evidence.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Justice in migration.Christine Straehle - 2018 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 48 (2):245-265.
    The movement of people across borders is one of the most pressing issues of our time. Yet it is still unclear how migration should be regulated to be fair to the sending societies, the host societies and the individual migrant. What is at issue? Are we discussing migration from an ethical or from a political philosophical perspective, or both? Are we discussing migration from a global justice perspective or social justice perspective? Do we consider political legitimacy and democratic self-determination as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Immigration, Rights and Democracy.Ben Saunders - 2011 - Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory 58 (129):58-77.
    Arash Abizadeh has recently argued that political communities have no right to close their borders unilaterally, since by doing so they subject outsiders to coercion which lacks democratic justification. His conclusion is that any legitimate regime of border controls must be justified to outsiders. David Miller has sought to defend closed borders by distinguishing between coercion and prevention and arguing that the latter does not require democratic justification. This paper explores a different route, arguing firstly that the requirements of democracy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Causation: Empirical Trends and Future Directions.David Rose & David Danks - 2012 - Philosophy Compass 7 (9):643-653.
    Empirical research has recently emerged as a key method for understanding the nature of causation, and our concept of causation. One thread of research aims to test intuitions about the nature of causation in a variety of classic cases. These experiments have principally been used to try to resolve certain debates within analytic philosophy, most notably that between proponents of transference and dependence views of causation. The other major thread of empirical research on our concept of causation has investigated the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Transnational citizenship and the democratic state: modes of membership and voting rights.David Owen - 2011 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 14 (5):641-663.
    This article addresses two central topics in normative debates on transnational citizenship: the inclusion of resident non-citizens and of non-resident citizens within the demos. Through a critical review of the social membership (Carens, Rubio-Marin) and stakeholder (Baubock) principles, it identifies two problems within these debates. The first is the antinomy of incorporation, namely, the point that there are compelling arguments both for the mandatory naturalization of permanent residents and for making naturalization a voluntary process. The second is the arbitrary demos (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Refugees and responsibilities of justice.David Owen - 2018 - Global Justice : Theory Practice Rhetoric 11 (1).
    This essay develops, within the terms of the recent New York Declaration, an account of the shared responsibility of states to refugees and of how the character of that responsibility effects the ways in which it can be fairly shared. However, it also moves beyond the question of the general obligations that states owe to refugees to consider ways in which refugee choices and refugee voice can be given appropriate standing with the global governance of refuge. It offers an argument (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Why Immigration Controls Are Not Coercive: A Reply to Arash Abizadeh.David Miller - 2010 - Political Theory 38 (1):111-120.
    Abizadeh has argued that because border controls coerce would-be immigrants and invade their autonomy, they are entitled to participate in the democratic institutions that impose those controls. In reply, the author distinguishes between coercion and prevention, shows that prevention need not undermine autonomy, and concludes that although border controls may restrict freedom, they do not give rise to democratic entitlements.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Democratic Inclusion and the Governance of Immigration.Joseph Lampert - 2015 - Social Theory and Practice 41 (1):51-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Rule Over None II: Social Equality and the Justification of Democracy.Niko Kolodny - 2014 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 42 (4):287-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  • Putting Fairness in Its Place: Why There Is a Duty to Take Up the Slack.Anja Karnein - 2014 - Journal of Philosophy 111 (11):593-607.
    The view that agents are not obliged to do more than their initial fair shares when their fellow duty bearers fail to comply has prominent defenders, including Liam Murphy and David Miller. While Murphy thinks that asking agents to take up other agents’ slack would be unfair, Miller claims that slack-taking cannot be required because primary responsibility does not migrate from noncompliers to compliers. This paper argues, by contrast, that there are a number of circumstances in which there is a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Legitimacy is Not Authority.Jon Garthoff - 2010 - Law and Philosophy 29 (6):669-694.
    The two leading traditions of theorizing about democratic legitimacy are liberalism and deliberative democracy. Liberals typically claim that legitimacy consists in the consent of the governed, while deliberative democrats typically claim that legitimacy consists in the soundness of political procedures. Despite this difference, both traditions see the need for legitimacy as arising from the coercive enforcement of law and regard legitimacy as necessary for law to have normative authority. While I endorse the broad aims of these two traditions, I believe (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Democracy, citizenship and the bits in between.Sarah Fine - 2011 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 14 (5):623-640.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Democracy, citizenship and the bits in between.Sarah Fine - 2014 - In Richard Bellamy & Madeleine Kennedy-Macfoy (eds.), Citizenship. Routledge. pp. 623-640.
    This paper lays the foundations for a democratic defence of the argument that at least some non-citizens are entitled to claim rights of political participation with regard to states in which they are not resident. First I outline a distinctively democratic case for granting participatory rights to certain non-resident non-citizens, based upon the central claim that in a democracy those who are governed ought to have the opportunity to participate in the exercise of government. I offer support for extending rights (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The British Academy Brian Barry Prize Essay: Mandatory Citizenship for Immigrants.Helder De Schutter & Lea Ypi - 2015 - British Journal of Political Science 45 (2):235 - 251.
    © © Cambridge University Press 2015. Long-term immigrants often have the option but not the obligation to acquire citizenship in their state of residence. Contrary to the received wisdom, this article defends the idea of mandatory citizenship for immigrants. It suggests that the current asymmetry in the distribution of political obligations between native-born citizens and immigrants is unfair. It also argues that mandatory citizenship is required by the principle that those who persistently affect others should share a democratic setting. Finally, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Stakeholder Citizenship and Transnational Political Participation: A Normative Evaluation of External Voting.Rainer Bauböck - 2007 - Fordham Law Review 75 (5):2393-2447.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy.Henry Shue & Theodore M. Benditt - 1980 - Law and Philosophy 4 (1):125-140.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   156 citations  
  • Political Liberalism.J. Rawls - 1995 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 57 (3):596-598.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2175 citations