Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme.Donald Davidson - 1973 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 47:5-20.
    Davidson attacks the intelligibility of conceptual relativism, i.e. of truth relative to a conceptual scheme. He defines the notion of a conceptual scheme as something ordering, organizing, and rendering intelligible empirical content, and calls the position that employs both notions scheme-content dualism. He argues that such dualism is untenable since: not only can we not parcel out empirical content sentence per sentence but also the notion of uninterpreted content to which several schemes are relative, and the related notion of a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   586 citations  
  • 8 Could There Be a Science of Rationality?Donald Davidson - 2004 - In Mario De Caro & David Macarthur (eds.), Naturalism in Question. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. pp. 152-170.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Could there be a science of rationality?Donald Davidson - 1995 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 3 (1):1-16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • On moral properties.Jonathan Dancy - 1981 - Mind 90 (359):367-385.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Impossible Worlds: A Modest Approach.Daniel Nolan - 1997 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38 (4):535-572.
    Reasoning about situations we take to be impossible is useful for a variety of theoretical purposes. Furthermore, using a device of impossible worlds when reasoning about the impossible is useful in the same sorts of ways that the device of possible worlds is useful when reasoning about the possible. This paper discusses some of the uses of impossible worlds and argues that commitment to them can and should be had without great metaphysical or logical cost. The paper then provides an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   297 citations  
  • Ethics without principles.Jonathan Dancy - 2004 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this much-anticipated book, Jonathan Dancy offers the only available full-scale treatment of particularism in ethics, a view with which he has been associated for twenty years. Dancy now presents particularism as the view that the possibility of moral thought and judgement does not in any way depend on an adequate supply of principles. He grounds this claim on a form of reasons-holism, holding that what is a reason in one case need not be any reason in another, and maintaining (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   672 citations  
  • The paradox of the knower without epistemic closure.Charles B. Cross - 2001 - Mind 110 (438):319-333.
    In this essay I present a new version of the Paradox of the Knower and show that this new paradox vitiates a certain argument against epistemic closure. I then prove a theorem that relates the new paradox to epistemological scepticism. I conclude by assessing the use of the Knower in arguments against syntactical treatments of knowledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Presentism and the grounding objection.Thomas M. Crisp - 2007 - Noûs 41 (1):90–109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   149 citations  
  • Mental Causation and Mental Reality.Tim Crane - 1992 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 92:185-202.
    The Problems of Mental Causation. Functionalism in the philosophy of mind identifies mental states with their dispositional connections with other mental states, perceptions and actions. Many theories of the mind have sailed under the Functionalist flag. But what I take to be essential to Functionalism is that mental states are individuated causally: the reality of mental states depends essentially on their causal efficacy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Kinds of context: A Wittgensteinian approach to proper names and indexicals.Eros Corazza - 2004 - Philosophical Investigations 27 (2):158–188.
    In focusing on indexicals and proper names and on the different ways in which their references are fixed, I illustrate how our linguistic practice rests on context, broadly construed. The following theses are discussed and defended: • There are two main kinds of information: (i) anchored information, i.e. the information one gathers in using and entertaining indexical expressions and (ii) unanchored information, i.e. the information one may gain in hearing a proper name. • Indexical expressions differ from proper names; this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Introduction.Carl H. Coleman - 2019 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 47 (2):189-193.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Response to Phillips.Brian R. Clack - 2003 - Religious Studies 39 (2):203-209.
    In this response to D. Z. Phillips's critique of my interpretation of Wittgenstein's view of magic and ritual, I counter Phillips's claim that I have misrepresented the Wittgensteinian view of ritual, consider the instrumentalist dimension of the Remarks on Frazer's Golden Bough, offer some objections to Phillips's expressivist view that a ritual ‘says itself’, and detect obscurantism in his approach to the study of religion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Engine of Reason, the Seat of Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain.Paul M. Churchland - 1998 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 58 (4):885-892.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Neurophilosophy: Toward A Unified Science of the Mind-Brain.Patricia Smith Churchland - 1986 - MIT Press.
    This is a unique book. It is excellently written, crammed with information, wise and a pleasure to read.' ---Daniel C. Dennett, Tufts University.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   758 citations  
  • A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science.Paul M. Churchland - 1989 - MIT Press.
    A Neurocomputationial Perspective illustrates the fertility of the concepts and data drawn from the study of the brain and of artificial networks that model the...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   446 citations  
  • The Simple Vs. Reformed Conditional Analysis of Dispositions.Sungho Choi - 2006 - Synthese 148 (2):369-379.
    Lewis claims that Martin’s cases indeed refute the simple conditional analysis of dispositions and proposes the reformed conditional analysis that is purported to overcome them. In this paper I will first argue that Lewis’s defense of the reformed analysis can be understood to invoke the concepts of disposition-specific stimulus and manifestation. I will go on to argue that advocates of the simple analysis, just like Lewis, can also defend their analysis from alleged counterexamples including Martin’s cases by invoking the concepts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Critical Notices.Nancy Cartwright - 2003 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66 (1):244-249.
    The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science. nancy cartwright. Plato's Reception of Parmenides. john a. palmer.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   315 citations  
  • Testability and meaning.Rudolf Carnap - 1936 - Philosophy of Science 3 (4):419-471.
    Two chief problems of the theory of knowledge are the question of meaning and the question of verification. The first question asks under what conditions a sentence has meaning, in the sense of cognitive, factual meaning. The second one asks how we get to know something, how we can find out whether a given sentence is true or false. The second question presupposes the first one. Obviously we must understand a sentence, i.e. we must know its meaning, before we can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   341 citations  
  • How the laws of physics lie.Nancy Cartwright - 1983 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this sequence of philosophical essays about natural science, the author argues that fundamental explanatory laws, the deepest and most admired successes of modern physics, do not in fact describe regularities that exist in nature. Cartwright draws from many real-life examples to propound a novel distinction: that theoretical entities, and the complex and localized laws that describe them, can be interpreted realistically, but the simple unifying laws of basic theory cannot.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1199 citations  
  • Über Extremalaxiome.Rudolf Carnap & Friedrich Bachmann - 1936 - Erkenntnis 6 (1):166-188.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Art, mind, and religion.William H. Capitan & Daniel Davy Merrill (eds.) - 1967 - [Pittsburgh]: University of Pittsburgh Press.
    This volume offers an unusual variety of topics presented during the sixth annual Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Art, Mind, and Religion. [REVIEW]David Lewis - 1969 - Journal of Philosophy 66 (1):22-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Abstract particulars.Keith Campbell - 1990 - Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   312 citations  
  • Taking Thermodynamics Too Seriously.Craig Callender - 2001 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 32 (4):539-553.
    This paper discusses the mistake of understanding the laws and concepts of thermodynamics too literally in the foundations of statistical mechanics. Arguing that this error is still made in subtle ways, the article explores its occurrence in three examples: the Second Law, the concept of equilibrium and the definition of phase transitions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • Appearance and Reality.J. E. C. - 1893 - Philosophical Review 2 (6):750.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Philosophy of Mind.Alex Byrne & Jaegwon Kim - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (1):113.
    In the preface, Kim writes hopefully that his introduction to the philosophy of mind is “intended to be accessible to those without a formal background in philosophy”. The blurb at the end is more realistic: Philosophy of Mind is “a textbook for upper-level undergraduates and graduate students”. It is an admirable addition to Westview’s excellent Dimensions of Philosophy series. Brisk, workmanlike chapters profile the usual suspects: behaviorism, the identity theory, mind as computer and as causal structure, mental causation, consciousness, mental (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • How hard are the sceptical paradoxes?Alex Byrne - 2004 - Noûs 38 (2):299–325.
    The sceptic about the external world presents us with a paradox: an apparently acceptable argument for an apparently unacceptable conclusion—that we do not know anything about the external world. Some paradoxes, for instance the liar and the sorites, are very hard. The defense of a purported solution to either of these two inevitably deploys the latest in high-tech philosophical weaponry. On the other hand, some paradoxes are not at all hard, and may be resolved without much fuss. They do not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Semantical paradox.Tyler Burge - 1979 - Journal of Philosophy 76 (4):169-198.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   137 citations  
  • Content preservation.Tyler Burge - 1993 - Philosophical Review 102 (4):457-488.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   593 citations  
  • A subject with no object: strategies for nominalistic interpretation of mathematics.John P. Burgess & Gideon Rosen - 1997 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by Gideon A. Rosen.
    Numbers and other mathematical objects are exceptional in having no locations in space or time or relations of cause and effect. This makes it difficult to account for the possibility of the knowledge of such objects, leading many philosophers to embrace nominalism, the doctrine that there are no such objects, and to embark on ambitious projects for interpreting mathematics so as to preserve the subject while eliminating its objects. This book cuts through a host of technicalities that have obscured previous (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   153 citations  
  • The structure of the skeptical argument.Anthony Brueckner - 1994 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (4):827-835.
    Much has been written about epistemological skepticism in the last ten or so years, but there remain some unanswered questions concerning the structure of what has become the canonical Cartesian skeptical argument. In this paper, I would like to take a closer look at this structure in order to determine just which epistemic principles are required by the argument.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  • Brains in a vat.Anthony L. Brueckner - 1986 - Journal of Philosophy 83 (3):148-167.
    In chapter 1 of Reason, Truth, and History, Hilary Putnam argues from some plausible assumptions about the nature of reference to the conclusion that it is not possible that all sentient creatures are brains in a vat. If this argument is successful, it seemingly refutes an updated form of Cartesian skepticism concerning knowledge of physical objects. In this paper, I will state what I take to be the most promising interpretation of Putnam's argument. My reconstructed argument differs from an argument (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Intelligence without representation.Rodney A. Brooks - 1991 - Artificial Intelligence 47 (1--3):139-159.
    Artificial intelligence research has foundered on the issue of representation. When intelligence is approached in an incremental manner, with strict reliance on interfacing to the real world through perception and action, reliance on representation disappears. In this paper we outline our approach to incrementally building complete intelligent Creatures. The fundamental decomposition of the intelligent system is not into independent information processing units which must interface with each other via representations. Instead, the intelligent system is decomposed into independent and parallel activity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   647 citations  
  • Five Types of Ethical Theory.C. D. Broad - 1930 - Mind 39 (155):338-346.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   129 citations  
  • Five Types of Ethical Theory.C. D. Broad - 1930 - Humana Mente 5 (19):463-465.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   138 citations  
  • Moral Realism: Facts and Norms. [REVIEW]David O. BRINK - 1991 - Ethics 101 (3):610-624.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   479 citations  
  • Ethical theory.Richard B. Brandt - 1959 - Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   108 citations  
  • Logic and Arithmetic.David Bostock - 1981 - Noûs 15 (4):551-559.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The word of others.Steffen Borge - 2003 - Journal of Applied Logic 1 (1-2):107-118.
    Tyler Burge has argued that one has an a priori prima facie entitlement to believe in the truth of what one takes to have been presented as true by an interlocutor. This thesis, however, is problematic, since the alleged a priori prima facie entitlement to believe in the truth of our seeming understanding of things presented as true to us, rests on the possibility of determining assertoric force on a purely intellectual basis. This thesis is not plausible and Burge's analogy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The iterative conception of set.George Boolos - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (8):215-231.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   195 citations  
  • The Logic of Provability.Timothy Williamson - 1996 - Philosophical Quarterly 46 (182):110-116.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Iteration Again.George Boolos - 1989 - Philosophical Topics 17 (2):5-21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • The rule-following considerations.Paul Boghossian - 1989 - Mind 98 (392):507-49.
    I. Recent years have witnessed a great resurgence of interest in the writings of the later Wittgenstein, especially with those passages roughly, Philosophical Investigations p)I 38 — 242 and Remarks on the Foundations of mathematics, section VI that are concerned with the topic of rules. Much of the credit for all this excitement, unparalleled since the heyday of Wittgenstein scholarship in the early IIJ6os, must go to Saul Kripke's I4rittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. It is easy to explain why. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   287 citations  
  • What psychological states are not.Ned Block & Jerry A. Fodor - 1972 - Philosophical Review 81 (April):159-81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   233 citations  
  • Do causal powers drain away.Ned Block - 2003 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67 (1):133-150.
    In this note, I will discuss one issue concerning the main argument of Mind in a Physical World (Kim, 1998), the Causal Exclusion Argument. The issue is whether it is a consequence of the Causal Exclusion Argument that all macro level causation (that is, causation above the level of fundamental physics) is an illusion, with all of the apparent causal powers of mental and other macro properties draining into the bottom level of physics. I will argue that such a consequence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • How metaphors work : a reply to Donald Davidson.Max Black - 2010 - In Darragh Byrne & Max Kölbel (eds.), Arguing about language. New York: Routledge. pp. 131.
    To be able to produce and understand metaphorical statements is nothing much to boast about: these familiar skills, which children seem to acquire as they learn to talk, are perhaps no more remarkable than our ability to tell and to understand jokes. How odd then that it remains difficult to explain what we do in grasping metaphorical statements. In a provocative paper, "What Metaphors Mean,"1 Donald Davidson has recently charged many students of metaphor, ancient and modern, with having committed a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • How Metaphors Work: A Reply to Donald Davidson.Max Black - 1979 - Critical Inquiry 6 (1):131-143.
    To be able to produce and understand metaphorical statements is nothing much to boast about: these familiar skills, which children seem to acquire as they learn to talk, are perhaps no more remarkable than our ability to tell and to understand jokes. How odd then that it remains difficult to explain what we do in grasping metaphorical statements. In a provocative paper, "What Metaphors Mean,"1 Donald Davidson has recently charged many students of metaphor, ancient and modern, with having committed a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Arthur Prior and Hybrid Logic.Patrick Blackburn - 2006 - Synthese 150 (3):329-372.
    Contemporary hybrid logic is based on the idea of using formulas as terms, an idea invented and explored by Arthur Prior in the mid-1960s. But Prior’s own work on hybrid logic remains largely undiscussed. This is unfortunate, since hybridisation played a role that was both central to and problematic for his philosophical views on tense. In this paper I introduce hybrid logic from a contemporary perspective, and then examine the role it played in Prior’s work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Further antidotes: A response to Gundersen.Alexander Bird - 2000 - Philosophical Quarterly 50 (199):229-233.
    In my 'Dispositions and Antidotes', The Philosophical Quarterly, 48 (1998), I raise an objection to the conditional analysis of dispositions, both in its simple formulation and in a more sophisticated version due to David Lewis, The Philosophical Quarterly, 47 (1997). The objection suggests that a disposition may be continuously present and the appropriate stimulus occur without the manifestation occurring, because some outside influence, an antidote, interferes. Gundersen in The Philosophical Quarterly, 50 (2000), argues that my objection rests on an equivocation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Dispositions and antidotes.Alexander Bird - 1998 - Philosophical Quarterly 48 (191):227-234.
    In ‘Finkish Dispositions’1 David Lewis proposes an analysis of dispositions which improves on the simple conditional analysis. In this paper I show that Lewis’ analysis still fails. I also argue that repairs are of no avail, and suggest why this is so.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   260 citations