Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Subjects among other things.Ernest Sosa - 1987 - Philosophical Perspectives 1:155-187.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • The principle of conservatism in cognitive ethology.Elliott Sober - 2001 - In D. Walsh (ed.), Evolution, Naturalism and Mind. Cambridge University Press. pp. 225-238.
    Philosophy of mind is, and for a long while has been, 99% metaphysics and 1% epistemology. But the fundamental question cognitive ethologists face is epistemological: what count as evidence that a creature has a mind, and if the creature does have a mind, what evidence is relevant to deciding which mental state should be attributed to it? The usual answer that cognitive ethologists give is that one’s explanation should be “conservative”. It recommends a two-part plausibility ordering: mindless is preferred to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Principle of Conservatism in Cognitive Ethology.Elliott Sober - 2001 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 49:225-238.
    Philosophy of mind is, and for a long while has been, 99% metaphysics and 1% epistemology. Attention is lavished on the question of the nature of mind, but questions concerning how we know about minds are discussed much less thoroughly. University courses in philosophy of mind routinely devote a lot of time to dualism, logical behaviourism, the mind/brain identity theory, and functionalism. But what gets said about the kinds of evidence that help one determine what mental states, if any, an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The modal argument: Wide scope and rigidified descriptions.Scott Soames - 1998 - Noûs 32 (1):1-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • The modal argument: Wide scope and rigidified descriptions.Scott Soames - 2009 - In Philosophical Essays, Volume 2: The Philosophical Significance of Language. Princeton University Press. pp. 139-164.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Semantics, Tense, and Time.Quentin Smith - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (2):278-281.
    The primary goal of Peter Ludlow's Semantics, Tense, and Time is to illustrate how one can study metaphysical issues from a linguistic/semantic perspective by addressing the debate between tenseless theorists and tensed theorists. Ludlow's book is noteworthy in part because of the novelty of its approach to this debate and in part because it addresses and endeavors to solve the metaphysical problems of temporal solipsism that other temporal solipsists have not addressed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Naive physics.Barry Smith & Roberto Casati - 1994 - Philosophical Psychology 7 (2):227 – 247.
    The project of a 'naive physics' has been the subject of attention in recent years above all in the artificial intelligence field, in connection with work on common-sense reasoning, perceptual representation and robotics. The idea of a theory of the common-sense world is however much older than this, having its roots not least in the work of phenomenologists and Gestalt psychologists such as K hler, Husserl, Schapp and Gibson. This paper seeks to show how contemporary naive physicists can profit from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Dispositional Theories of Value.Michael Smith, David Lewis & Mark Johnston - 1989 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 63 (1):89-174.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   398 citations  
  • Dispositional properties.A. D. Smith - 1977 - Mind 86 (343):439-445.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Sensations and brain processes.Jjc Smart - 1959 - Philosophical Review 68 (April):141-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   698 citations  
  • Types of inter-theoretic reduction.Lawrence Sklar - 1967 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 18 (2):109-124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   104 citations  
  • The reduction(?) Of thermodynamics to statistical mechanics.Lawrence Sklar - 1999 - Philosophical Studies 95 (1-2):187 - 202.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Reduction, emergence and explanation.Michael Silberstein - 2002 - In Peter Machamer & Michael Silberstein (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science. Cambridge: Blackwell. pp. 80--107.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Introduction: The Problem of Emergence and Reduction The Varieties of Reductionism: Ontological and Epistemological The Reduction and Emergence Debate Today: Specific Cases Seeming to Warrant the Label of Ontological or Epistemological Emergence Questions for Future Research.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Common Knowledge and Convention.Giacomo Sillari - 2008 - Topoi 27 (1-2):29-39.
    This paper investigates the epistemic assumptions that David Lewis makes in his account of social conventions. In particular, I focus on the assumption that the agents have common knowledge of the convention to which they are parties. While evolutionary analyses show that the common knowledge assumption is unnecessary in certain classes of games, Lewis’ original account (and, more recently, Cubitt and Sugden’s reconstruction) stresses the importance of including it in the definition of convention. I discuss arguments pro et contra to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • A Logical Framework for Convention.Giacomo Sillari - 2005 - Synthese 147 (2):379-400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Four Dimensionalism.Theodore Sider - 1997 - Philosophical Review 106 (2):197-231.
    Persistence through time is like extension through space. A road has spatial parts in the subregions of the region of space it occupies; likewise, an object that exists in time has temporal parts in the various subregions of the total region of time it occupies. This view — known variously as four dimensionalism, the doctrine of temporal parts, and the theory that objects “perdure” — is opposed to “three dimensionalism”, the doctrine that things “endure”, or are “wholly present”.1 I will (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   627 citations  
  • Kim on Emergence.Sydney Shoemaker - 2002 - Philosophical Studies 108 (1-2):53-63.
    Emergence requires that the ultimate physical micro-entities have “micro-latent” causal powers, which manifest themselves only when the entities are combined in ways that are “emergence-engendering,” in addition to the “micro-manifest” powers that account for their behavior in other circumstances. Subjects of emergent properties will have emergent micro-structural properties, specified partly in terms of these micro-latent powers, each of which will be determined by a micro-structural property specified only in terms of the micro-manifest powers of the constituents and the way they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Minds, Brains and Science.John R. Searle - 1984 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    As Louisiana and Cuba emerged from slavery in the late nineteenth century, each faced the question of what rights former slaves could claim. Degrees of Freedom compares and contrasts these two societies in which slavery was destroyed by war, and citizenship was redefined through social and political upheaval. Both Louisiana and Cuba were rich in sugar plantations that depended on an enslaved labor force. After abolition, on both sides of the Gulf of Mexico, ordinary people-cane cutters and cigar workers, laundresses (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   321 citations  
  • Intrinsic intentionality.John Searle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):450-457.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations  
  • On engendering an illusion of understanding.Dana Scott - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (21):787-807.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Is there a fundamental level?Jonathan Schaffer - 2003 - Noûs 37 (3):498–517.
    ‘‘Thus I believe that there is no part of matter which is not—I do not say divisible—but actually divided; and consequently the least particle ought to be considered as a world full of an infinity of different creatures.’’ (Leibniz, letter to Foucher).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   249 citations  
  • Approaches to reduction.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1967 - Philosophy of Science 34 (2):137-147.
    Four current accounts of theory reduction are presented, first informally and then formally: (1) an account of direct theory reduction that is based on the contributions of Nagel, Woodger, and Quine, (2) an indirect reduction paradigm due to Kemeny and Oppenheim, (3) an "isomorphic model" schema traceable to Suppes, and (4) a theory of reduction that is based on the work of Popper, Feyerabend, and Kuhn. Reference is made, in an attempt to choose between these schemas, to the explanation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   228 citations  
  • Just how ab initio is ab initio quantum chemistry?Eric R. Scerri - 2004 - Foundations of Chemistry 6 (1):93-116.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The mechanisms of emergence.R. Keith Sawyer - 2004 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 34 (2):260-282.
    This article focuses on emergence in social systems. The author begins by proposing a new tool to explore the mechanisms of social emergence: multi agent–based computer simulation. He then draws on philosophy of mind to develop an account of social emergence that raises potential problems for the methodological individualism of both social mechanism and of multi agent simulation. He then draws on various complexity concepts to propose a set of criteria whereby one can determine whether a given social mechanism generates (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Causality without counterfactuals.Wesley C. Salmon - 1994 - Philosophy of Science 61 (2):297-312.
    This paper presents a drastically revised version of the theory of causality, based on analyses of causal processes and causal interactions, advocated in Salmon (1984). Relying heavily on modified versions of proposals by P. Dowe, this article answers penetrating objections by Dowe and P. Kitcher to the earlier theory. It shows how the new theory circumvents a host of difficulties that have been raised in the literature. The result is, I hope, a more satisfactory analysis of physical causality.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   152 citations  
  • Causality and explanation.Wesley C. Salmon - 1998 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Wesley Salmon is renowned for his seminal contributions to the philosophy of science. He has powerfully and permanently shaped discussion of such issues as lawlike and probabilistic explanation and the interrelation of explanatory notions to causal notions. This unique volume brings together twenty-six of his essays on subjects related to causality and explanation, written over the period 1971-1995. Six of the essays have never been published before and many others have only appeared in obscure venues. The volume includes a section (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   263 citations  
  • Wesley Salmon, Causality and Explanation. [REVIEW]Raffaella Campaner - 2000 - Erkenntnis 52 (1):121-125.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • The Principles of Mathematics.Bertrand Russell - 1903 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 11 (4):11-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   689 citations  
  • The Analysis of Mind.J. S. Mackenzie - 1921 - International Journal of Ethics 32 (2):212-215.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations  
  • Mathematical Logic as Based on the Theory of Types.Bertrand Russell - 1908 - American Journal of Mathematics 30 (3):222-262.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   278 citations  
  • Robust supervenience and emergence.Alexander Rueger - 2000 - Philosophy of Science 67 (3):466-491.
    Non-reductive physicalists have made a number of attempts to provide the relation of supervenience between levels of properties with enough bite to analyze interesting cases without at the same time losing the relation's acceptability for the physicalist. I criticize some of these proposals and suggest an alternative supplementation of the supervenience relation by imposing a requirement of robustness which is motivated by the notion of structural stability familiar from dynamical systems theory. Robust supervenience, I argue, captures what the non-reductive physicalist (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Transcendental arguments revisited.Jay F. Rosenberg - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (18):611-624.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Ontology in the Tractatus of L. Wittgenstein.Roman Suszko - 1968 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 9 (1):7-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability.Hartley Rogers - 1971 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 36 (1):141-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   595 citations  
  • Wittgenstein's inversion of gödel's theorem.Victor Rodych - 1999 - Erkenntnis 51 (2-3):173-206.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Two perspectives on Kant's appearances and things in themselves.Hoke Robinson - 1994 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 32 (3):411-441.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Particularism and principles.Toni Rønnow-Rasmussen - 1999 - Theoria 65 (2-3):114-126.
    Jonathan Dancy argues in his book Moral Reasons that neither general nor specific moral principles are of any important use in moral decision making. I examine his reasons for denying any important role to such principles. With regard to general moral principles, I suggest that there are such principles that appear useful ‐ an idea that Dancy in some passages actually seems to endorse. When it comes to highly specific principles, Dancy's advice is less open to interpretation; since such principles (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hans Vaihinger and Some Recent Intentionalist Readings of Kant.Richard E. Aquila - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (2):231-250.
    BRENTANO'S APPROPRIATION OF THE Scholastic notion of intentionality, and of what Brentano called "the intentional (or mental) inexistence of an object," was early on exploited in a reading of Kant's theory of objects and appearances. Apparently the first systematic attempt was undertaken by Hans Vaihinger. However, Vaihinger's is radically different from more recent intentionalist readings of Kant. Albeit not in every respect, I propose that a return to this aspect of Vaihinger's approach supports a rewarding advance on such readings. After (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Functionalism and reductionism.Robert C. Richardson - 1979 - Philosophy of Science 46 (4):533-58.
    It is here argued that functionalist constraints on psychology do not preclude the applicability of classic forms of reduction and, therefore, do not support claims to a principled, or de jure, autonomy of psychology. In Part I, after isolating one minimal restriction any functionalist theory must impose on its categories, it is shown that any functionalism imposing an additional constraint of de facto autonomy must also be committed to a pure functionalist--that is, a computationalist--model for psychology. Using an extended parallel (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • Mathematics as a science of patterns.Michael David Resnik - 1997 - New York ;: Oxford University Press.
    This book expounds a system of ideas about the nature of mathematics which Michael Resnik has been elaborating for a number of years. In calling mathematics a science he implies that it has a factual subject-matter and that mathematical knowledge is on a par with other scientific knowledge; in calling it a science of patterns he expresses his commitment to a structuralist philosophy of mathematics. He links this to a defense of realism about the metaphysics of mathematics--the view that mathematics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   242 citations  
  • Crazy minimalism.François Recanati - 2006 - Mind and Language 21 (1):21–30.
    Review of Insensitive Semantics, by H. Cappelen and E. Lepore.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • On Specifying Truth-Conditions.Agustín Rayo - 2008 - Philosophical Review 117 (3):385-443.
    This essay is a study of ontological commitment, focused on the special case of arithmetical discourse. It tries to get clear about what would be involved in a defense of the claim that arithmetical assertions are ontologically innocent and about why ontological innocence matters. The essay proceeds by questioning traditional assumptions about the connection between the objects that are used to specify the truth-conditions of a sentence, on the one hand, and the objects whose existence is required in order for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Justice as fairness.John Rawls - 1958 - Philosophical Review 67 (2):164-194.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   318 citations  
  • The Foundations of Mathematics and other Logical Essays.Frank Plumpton Ramsey, R. B. Braithwaite & G. E. Moore - 1931 - Mind 40 (160):476-482.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   219 citations  
  • Two Dogmas of Empiricism.Willard V. O. Quine - 1951 - Philosophical Review 60 (1):20–43.
    Modern empiricism has been conditioned in large part by two dogmas. One is a belief in some fundamental cleavage between truths which are analytic, or grounded in meanings independently of matters of fact, and truth which are synthetic, or grounded in fact. The other dogma is reductionism: the belief that each meaningful statement is equivalent to some logical construct upon terms which refer to immediate experience. Both dogmas, I shall argue, are ill founded. One effect of abandoning them is, as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1335 citations  
  • III.—Properties and Classes.Anthony Quinton - 1958 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 58 (1):33-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Cognitive Meaning.W. V. Quine - 1979 - The Monist 62 (2):129-142.
    Words and phrases refer to things in either of two ways. A name or singular description designates its object, if any. A predicate denotes each of the objects of which it is true. Such are the two sorts of reference: designation and denotation. We are often told, and rightly, that neither sort is to be confused with meaning. The descriptions ‘the author of Waverley’ and ‘the author of Ivanhoe’ designate the same man, after all, but differ in meaning; and a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A Theory of Classes Presupposing no Canons of Type.W. V. Quine - 1936 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 1 (2):70-70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The structure of the paradoxes of self-reference.Graham Priest - 1994 - Mind 103 (409):25-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • The nation and the individual.Arthur N. Prior - 1937 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 15 (4):294 – 298.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations