Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)Radical interpretation.David K. Lewis - 1974 - Synthese 23 (July-August):331-344.
    What knowledge would suffice to yield an interpretation of an arbitrary utterance of a language when such knowledge is based on evidence plausibly available to a nonspeaker of that language? it is argued that it is enough to know a theory of truth for the language and that the theory satisfies tarski's 'convention t' and that it gives an optimal fit to data about sentences held true, Under specified conditions, By native speakers.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   270 citations  
  • The psychological turn.Hilary Kornblith - 1982 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 60 (3):238 – 253.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Concepts of supervenience.Jaegwon Kim - 1984 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45 (December):153-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   334 citations  
  • On the Nature of Moral Values.W. V. Quine - 1978 - Critical Inquiry 5 (3):471-480.
    The distinction between moral values and others is not an easy one. There are easy extremes: the value that one places on his neighbor's welfare is moral, and the value of peanut brittle is not. The value of decency in speech and dress is moral or ethical in the etymological sense, resting as it does on social custom; and similarly for observance of the Jewish dietary laws. On the other hand the eschewing of unrefrigerated oysters in the summer, though it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • (3 other versions)What is Justified Belief?Alvin I. Goldman - 1979 - In George Pappas (ed.), Justification and Knowledge: New Studies in Epistemology. Boston: D. Reidel. pp. 1-25.
    The aim of this paper is to sketch a theory of justified belief. What I have in mind is an explanatory theory, one that explains in a general way why certain beliefs are counted as justified and others as unjustified. Unlike some traditional approaches, I do not try to prescribe standards for justification that differ from, or improve upon, our ordinary standards. I merely try to explicate the ordinary standards, which are, I believe, quite different from those of many classical, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   913 citations  
  • A reply to my critics.George Edward Moore - 1942 - In Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.), The philosophy of G. E. Moore. New York,: Tudor Pub. Co..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   280 citations  
  • (1 other version)Coherence, certainty, and epistemic priority.Roderick Firth - 1964 - Journal of Philosophy 61 (19):545-557.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Two types of foundationalism.William P. Alston - 1976 - Journal of Philosophy 73 (7):165-185.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • (1 other version)Testability and Meaning.Rudolf Carnap - 1951 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 16 (2):137-137.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   172 citations  
  • (1 other version)Epistemic Supervenience and the Circle of Belief.James Van Cleve - 1985 - The Monist 68 (1):90-104.
    I shall begin with a series of quotations to illustrate how widespread are the views I wish to challenge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The foundations of foundationalism.Ernest Sosa - 1980 - Noûs 14 (4):547-564.
    There is a controversy in contemporary philosophy over the question whether or not knowledge must have a foundation. On one side are the foundationalists, who do accept the metaphor and find the foundation in sensory experience or the like. The coherentists, on the other side, reject the foundations metaphor and consider our body of knowledge a coherent whole floating free of any foundations. This controversy grew rapidly with the rise of idealism many years ago, and it is prominent today not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Psychologism.Elliott Sober - 1978 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 8 (July):165-91.
    The end of the nineteenth century is remembered as a time when psychology freed itself from philosophy and carved out an autonomous subject matter for itself. In fact, this time of emancipation was also a time of exile: while the psychologists were leaving, philosophers were slamming the door behind them. Frege is celebrated for having demonstrated the irrelevance of psychological considerations to philosophy. Some of Frege’s reasons for distinguishing psychological questions from philosophical ones were sound, but one of Frege’s most (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • “Are Epistemic Concepts Reducible to Ethical Concepts?Roderick Firth - 1978 - In A. I. Goldman & I. Kim (eds.), Values and Morals. Boston: D. Reidel. pp. 215-229.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • .Hilary Kornblith - 1998
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations  
  • (1 other version)The nature of natural knowledge.Willard V. Quine - 1975 - In Samuel D. Guttenplan (ed.), Mind and language. Oxford [Eng.]: Clarendon Press. pp. 1975--67.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  • Psychophysical laws.Jaegwon Kim - 1985 - In Ernest LePore & Brian P. McLaughlin (eds.), Actions and events: perspectives on the philosophy of Donald Davidson. New York, NY, USA: Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations