Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A redefinition of Boyle's chemistry and corpuscular philosophy.Antonio Clericuzio - 1990 - Annals of Science 47 (6):561-589.
    Summary Robert Boyle did not subordinate chemistry to mechanical philosophy. He was in fact reluctant to explain chemical phenomena by having recourse to the mechanical properties of particles. For him chemistry provided a primary way of penetrating into nature. In his chemical works he employed corpuscles endowed with chemical properties as his explanans. Boyle's chemistry was corpuscular, rather than mechanical. As Boyle's views of seminal principles show, his corpuscular philosophy cannot be described as a purely mechanical theory of matter. Boyle's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • One Hundred Years of Pressure: Hydrostatics From Stevin to Newton.Alan F. Chalmers - 2017 - Cham: Springer Verlag.
    This monograph investigates the development of hydrostatics as a science. In the process, it sheds new light on the nature of science and its origins in the Scientific Revolution. Readers will come to see that the history of hydrostatics reveals subtle ways in which the science of the seventeenth century differed from previous periods. The key, the author argues, is the new insights into the concept of pressure that emerged during the Scientific Revolution. This came about due to contributions from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Intermediate causes and explanations: The key to understanding the scientific revolution.Alan Chalmers - 2012 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 43 (4):551-562.
    It is instructive to view the scientific revolution from the point of view of Robert Boyle’s distinction between intermediate and ultimate causes. From this point of view, the scientific revolution involved the identification of intermediate causes and their investigation by way of experiment as opposed to the specification of ultimate causes of the kind involved in the corpuscular matter theories of the mechanical philosophers. The merits of this point of view are explored in this paper by focussing on the hydrostatics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Importance of Teleology to Boyle's Natural Philosophy.Laurence Carlin - 2011 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19 (4):665 - 682.
    Boyle prefaced his Disquisition about the Final Causes of Natural Things with the claim that there are three dangerous consequences for failing to engage in the pursuit of final causes. Boyle was sincere in this claim, for there is a systematic line of reasoning in his texts that incorporates all three consequences and establishes conceptual connections between his science, his theology, and his value theory. I argue in this paper that Boyle's teleological outlook led him to believe that the natural (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Boyle’s teleological mechanism and the myth of immanent teleology.Laurence Carlin - 2012 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 43 (1):54-63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Boyle on seminal principles.Peter R. Anstey - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 33 (4):597-630.
    This paper presents a comprehensive study of Robert Boyle’s writings on seminal principles or seeds. It examines the role of seeds in Boyle’s account of creation, the generation of plants and animals, spontaneous generation, the generation of minerals and disease. By an examination of all of Boyle’s major extant discussions of seeds it is argued that there were discernible changes in Boyle’s views over time. As the years progressed Boyle became more sceptical about the role of seminal principles in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Alexander of Aphrodisias and his Doctrine of the soul: 1400 years of lasting significance.Eckhard Kessler - 2011 - Boston: Brill.
    This piece of work intends to shed light on Alexander of Aphrodisias from the second-century Aristotle commentator through the history of Aristotelian psychology up to the sixteenth century's clandestine prompter of the new philosophy of nature. In the millennium after his death the head of the Peripatetic school in Athens served as the authority on Aristotle in the Neo-Platonic school, survived the Arabic centuries of philosophy as Averroes' exemplary exponent of the mortality of the soul and as such was not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Two Conceptions of Soul in Aristotle.Christopher Frey - 2015 - In David Ebrey (ed.), Theory and Practice in Aristotle's Natural Science. Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press. pp. 137-160.
    Aristotle outlines two methods in De Anima that one can employ when one investigates the soul. The first focuses on the exercises of a living organism’s vital capacities and the proper objects upon which these activities are directed. The second focuses on a living organism’s nature, its internal principle of movement and rest, and the single end for the sake of which this principle is exercised. I argue that these two methods yield importantly different, and prima facie incompatible, views about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Concept of Mind.Gilbert Ryle - 1949 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 141:125-126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2196 citations  
  • What is the science of the soul? A case study in the evolution of late medieval natural philosophy.Jack Zupko - 1997 - Synthese 110 (2):297-334.
    This paper aims at a partial rehabilitation of E. A. Moody''s characterization of the 14th century as an age of rising empiricism, specifically by contrasting the conception of the natural science of psychology found in the writings of a prominent 13th-century philosopher (Thomas Aquinas) with those of two 14th-century philosophers (John Buridan and Nicole Oresme). What emerges is that if the meaning of empiricism can be disengaged from modern and contemporary paradigms, and understood more broadly in terms of a cluster (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Buridan and skepticism.Jack Zupko - 1993 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 31 (2):191-221.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Notes on avicenna's concept of thingness (šay'iyya).Robert Wisnovsky - 2000 - Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 10 (2):181-221.
    Did classical kalām debates about how thing and existent relate to each other pave the way for Avicenna's distinction between essence and existence? There are some indications that the concept of thingness may have played a bridging role between the mutakallimūn's discussions and those of Avicenna. Nevertheless, Avicenna's appeals to thingness occur most densely in passages devoted to analyzing the relationship between efficient and final causes, an entirely Aristotelian topic. A philological question arises: should these passages be emended to read (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • God and nature in the thought of Robert Boyle.Timothy Shanahan - 1988 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 26 (4):547-569.
    THERE IS WIDESPREAD AGREEMENT among historians that the writings of Robert Boyle (1697-1691) constitute a valuable archive for understanding the concerns of seventeenth-century British natural philosophers. His writings have often been seen as representing, in one fashion or another, all of the leading intellectual currents of his day. ~ There is somewhat less consensus, however, on the proper historiographic method for interpreting these writings, as well as on the specific details of the beliefs expressed in them. Studies seeking to explicate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Der Alexandrismus an den Universitäten im späten Mittelalter.Olaf Pluta - 1996 - Bochumer Philosophisches Jahrbuch Fur Antike Und Mittelalter 1 (1):81-109.
    This essay outlines the history of Alexandrism in the Middle Ages, focusing on the reception of Alexander of Aphrodisias in the late-medieval universities. Alexander of Aphrodisias met with severe criticism in the 13th century from William of Auvergne, Albert the Great and Thomas of Aquinas among others, but in the 14th century this attitude changed completely with John Buridan, giving way to a positive and productive adoption of his theories. The centerpiece of the controversy was Alexander's doctrine that the human (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Avicenna's Metaphysics in Context.Jon McGinnis & Robert Wisnovsky - 2004 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 124 (2):392.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Contrastive Explanation.Peter Lipton - 1990 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 27:247-266.
    According to a causal model of explanation, we explain phenomena by giving their causes or, where the phenomena are themselves causal regularities, we explain them by giving a mechanism linking cause and effect. If we explain why smoking causes cancer, we do not give the cause of this causal connection, but we do give the causal mechanism that makes it. The claim that to explain is to give a cause is not only natural and plausible, but it also avoids many (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • The Unity of Efficient and Final Causality: The Mind/Body Problem Reconsidered.Henrik Lagerlund - 2011 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19 (4):587 - 603.
    In this paper, I argue that it is in the fourteenth century that the problem of the compatibility or unity of efficient and final causality emerges. William Ockham and John Buridan start to flirt with a mechanized view of nature solely explainable by efficient causality, and they hence push final causality into the human mind and use it to explain for example action, morality and the good. Their argumentation introduces the problem of how to give a unified account of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • John Buridan and the problems of dualism in the early fourteenth century.Henrik Lagerlund - 2004 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 42 (4):369-387.
    : In this paper I argue that the famous problems of dualism between mind (soul) and body, that is, the problems of interaction and unification, concerned philosophers already in a medieval Aristotelian tradition. The problems, although traceable earlier, become particularly visible after William Ockham in the early fourteenth century, and in formulating his own position on the animal and human souls I argue that Buridan realized these problems and laid down the only views on the soul he thought to be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Galileo and the scientific revolution of the seventeenth century.Alexandre Koyre - 1943 - Philosophical Review 52 (4):333-348.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Animism, Aristotelianism, and the Legacy of William Gilbert’s De Magnete.Jeff Kochan - 2021 - Perspectives on Science 29 (2):157-188.
    William Gilbert’s 1600 book, De magnete, greatly influenced early modern natural philosophy. The book describes an impressive array of physical experiments, but it also advances a metaphysical view at odds with the soon to emerge mechanical philosophy. That view was animism. I distinguish two kinds of animism – Aristotelian and Platonic – and argue that Gilbert was an Aristotelian animist. Taking Robert Boyle as an example, I then show that early modern arguments against animism were often effective only against Platonic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Materials and Expertise in Early Modern Europe: Between Market and Laboratory. [REVIEW]Ursula Klein & E. Spary - 2011 - Isis 102:356-357.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Occult qualities and the experimental philosophy: Active principles in pre-Newtonian matter theory.John Henry - 1986 - History of Science 24 (4):335-381.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Automata compared Boyle, Leibniz and the debate on the notion of life and M.Guido Giglioni - 1995 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 3 (2):249 – 278.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Newton as Final Cause and First Mover.B. Dobbs - 1994 - Isis 85:633-643.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Newton as Final Cause and First Mover.B. J. T. Dobbs - 1994 - Isis 85 (4):633-643.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Life’s Form: Late Aristotelian Conceptions of the Soul.Dennis des Chene - 2002 - Philosophical Quarterly 52 (208):390-392.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The intellective soul.Eckhard Kessler - 1988 - In Charles B. Schmitt, Quentin Skinner & Eckhard Kessler (eds.), The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. pp. 485--534.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Aristotelian Mechanistic Explanation.Monte Johnson - 2017 - In J. Rocca (ed.), Teleology in the Ancient World: philosophical and medical approaches. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 125-150.
    In some influential histories of ancient philosophy, teleological explanation and mechanistic explanation are assumed to be directly opposed and mutually exclusive alternatives. I contend that this assumption is deeply flawed, and distorts our understanding both of teleological and mechanistic explanation, and of the history of mechanistic philosophy. To prove this point, I shall provide an overview of the first systematic treatise on mechanics, the short and neglected work Mechanical Problems, written either by Aristotle or by a very early member of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Body and Mind: a History and a Defence of Animism.William Mcdougall - 1912 - Mind 21 (81):104-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • The Idea of Nature.R. G. Collingwood - 1945 - Philosophy 20 (77):260-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Forms of Explanation: Rethinking the Questions in Social Theory.Alan Garfinkel - 1982 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 33 (4):438-441.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Avicenna.L. Goodman - 1995 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 57 (1):136-137.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Boyle Against Thinking Matter.Peter R. Anstey - 2001 - In Christopher Luthy, John E. Murdoch & William R. Newman (eds.), Late Medieval and Early Modern Corpuscular Matter Theories. Netherlands: pp. 483-514.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • De ipsa natura: Leibniz on Substance, Force and Activity.Catherine Wilson - 1987 - Studia Leibnitiana 19:148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Intentionality and final causes.Robert Pasnau - 2001 - In Dominik Perler (ed.), Ancient and Medieval Theories of Intentionality. Brill. pp. 301--24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Christian Materiality: An Essay on Religion in Late Medieval Europe. [REVIEW]Caroline Bynum - 2012 - The Medieval Review 3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations