Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Thinking in Education.Matthew Lipman - 1992 - British Journal of Educational Studies 40 (2):187-189.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   215 citations  
  • (1 other version)Can Children Do Philosophy?Karin Murris - 2000 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 34 (2):261-279.
    Some philosophers claim that young children cannot do philosophy. This paper examines some of those claims, and puts forward arguments against them. Our beliefs that children cannot do philosophy are based on philosophical assumptions about children, their thinking and about philosophy. Many of those assumptions remain unquestioned by critics of Philosophy with Children. My conclusion is that the idea that very young children can do philosophy has not only significant consequences for how we should educate young children, but also for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • (1 other version)Philosophy for children as the wind of thinking.Nancy Vansieleghem - 2005 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 39 (1):19–35.
    In this paper I want to analyse the meaning of education for democracy and thinking as this is generally understood by Philosophy for Children. Although we may be inclined to applaud Philosophy for Children's emphasis on children, critical thinking, autonomy and dialogue, there is reason for scepticism too. Since we are expected as a matter of course to subscribe to the basic assumptions of Philosophy for Children, we seem to become tied, as it were, to the whole package, without reservation. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • (1 other version)Philosophy for Children as the Wind of Thinking.Nancy Vansieleghem - 2005 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 39 (1):19-35.
    In this paper I want to analyse the meaning of education for democracy and thinking as this is generally understood by Philosophy for Children. Although we may be inclined to applaud Philosophy for Children’s emphasis on children, critical thinking, autonomy and dialogue, there is reason for scepticism too. Since we are expected as a matter of course to subscribe to the basic assumptions of Philosophy for Children, we seem to become tied, as it were, to the whole package, without reservation. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Hume's ontological commitments.Wade L. Robison - 1976 - Philosophical Quarterly 26 (102):39-47.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (1 other version)Can children do philosophy?Karin Murris - 2000 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 34 (2):261–279.
    Some philosophers claim that young children cannot do philosophy. This paper examines some of those claims, and puts forward arguments against them. Our beliefs that children cannot do philosophy are based on philosophical assumptions about children, their thinking and about philosophy. Many of those assumptions remain unquestioned by critics of Philosophy with Children. My conclusion is that the idea that very young children can do philosophy has not only significant consequences for how we should educate young children, but also for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • On alleged inconsistency in Reid's theory of moral liberty.W. Dean Hazelton - 1978 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 16 (4):453-455.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Personal Identity: Reid’s Answer to Hume.Daniel N. Robinson & Tom L. Beauchamp - 1978 - The Monist 61 (2):326-339.
    In the third of his Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, Reid devotes the fourth chapter to the concept of‘identity’, and the sixth chapter to Locke’s theory of ‘personal identity’. This latter chapter is widely regarded as a definitive refutation of the thesis that personal identity is no more than memories of a certain sort. It is interesting that the terms ‘identity’ and ‘personal identity’ do not appear as chapter or section titles elsewhere in any of Reid’s works; and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Philosophical Arguments.Charles Taylor - 1997 - Philosophical Quarterly 47 (186):94-96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   178 citations  
  • On Certainty.Ludwig Wittgenstein, G. E. M. Anscombe, G. H. Von Wright & Denis Paul - 1972 - Mind 81 (323):453-457.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   329 citations  
  • Reason and Passion.Michael S. Pritchard - 1978 - The Monist 61 (2):283-298.
    Although Hume’s theory of the passions has been vigorously criticized by contemporary philosophers, Hume’s immediate successors are seldom credited with serious criticisms of that theory. In fact, insofar as their views are considered at all, they typically are summarily dismissed. Alasdair MacIntyre’s treatment is a good illustration.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Personal Identity.Daniel N. Robinson & Tom L. Beauchamp - 1978 - The Monist 61 (2):326-339.
    In the third of his Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, Reid devotes the fourth chapter to the concept of‘identity’, and the sixth chapter to Locke’s theory of ‘personal identity’. This latter chapter is widely regarded as a definitive refutation of the thesis that personal identity is no more than memories of a certain sort. It is interesting that the terms ‘identity’ and ‘personal identity’ do not appear as chapter or section titles elsewhere in any of Reid’s works; and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Dissemination.Betty R. McGraw, Jacques Derrida & Barbara Johnson - 1983 - Substance 12 (2):114.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   186 citations  
  • The Seriousness of Reid’s Sceptical Admissions.Louise Marcil Lacoste - 1978 - The Monist 61 (2):311-325.
    For anyone acquainted with Reid’s works and the literature on them, the idea of proposing a hypothesis to explain contradictory comments on his philosophy, and the further idea of borrowing this hypothesis from Hume’s threefold account of scepticism will not only appear ironical but quite unlikely. Yet, this is what I propose to do in showing that Reid’s sceptical admissions can be seen as a form of “mitigated scepticism.” And while I acknowledge the irony of my hypothesis, I do not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Children's Philosophy in Europe. [REVIEW]Jan De Bruijn - 1992 - Teaching Philosophy 15 (3):255-265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations