Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The complexity of plane hyperbolic incidence geometry is∀∃∀∃.Victor Pambuccian - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (3):277-281.
    We show that plane hyperbolic geometry, expressed in terms of points and the ternary relation of collinearity alone, cannot be expressed by means of axioms of complexity at most ∀∃∀, but that there is an axiom system, all of whose axioms are ∀∃∀∃ sentences. This remains true for Klingenberg's generalized hyperbolic planes, with arbitrary ordered fields as coordinate fields.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On the relationship between plane and solid geometry.Andrew Arana & Paolo Mancosu - 2012 - Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (2):294-353.
    Traditional geometry concerns itself with planimetric and stereometric considerations, which are at the root of the division between plane and solid geometry. To raise the issue of the relation between these two areas brings with it a host of different problems that pertain to mathematical practice, epistemology, semantics, ontology, methodology, and logic. In addition, issues of psychology and pedagogy are also important here. To our knowledge there is no single contribution that studies in detail even one of the aforementioned areas.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The development of mathematical logic from Russell to Tarski, 1900-1935.Paolo Mancosu, Richard Zach & Calixto Badesa - 2009 - In Leila Haaparanta (ed.), The development of modern logic. New York: Oxford University Press.
    The period from 1900 to 1935 was particularly fruitful and important for the development of logic and logical metatheory. This survey is organized along eight "itineraries" concentrating on historically and conceptually linked strands in this development. Itinerary I deals with the evolution of conceptions of axiomatics. Itinerary II centers on the logical work of Bertrand Russell. Itinerary III presents the development of set theory from Zermelo onward. Itinerary IV discusses the contributions of the algebra of logic tradition, in particular, Löwenheim (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Simplicity.Victor Pambuccian - 1988 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 29 (3):396-411.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The Principles of Mathematics.Bertrand Russell & Susanne K. Langer - 1938 - Philosophy 13 (52):481-483.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   161 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The Principles of Mathematics.Bertrand Russell - 1903 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 11 (4):11-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   819 citations  
  • Axiomatizing geometric constructions.Victor Pambuccian - 2008 - Journal of Applied Logic 6 (1):24-46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Axiomatizations of hyperbolic geometry: A comparison based on language and quantifier type complexity.Victor Pambuccian - 2002 - Synthese 133 (3):331 - 341.
    Hyperbolic geometry can be axiomatized using the notions of order andcongruence (as in Euclidean geometry) or using the notion of incidencealone (as in projective geometry). Although the incidence-based axiomatizationmay be considered simpler because it uses the single binary point-linerelation of incidence as a primitive notion, we show that it issyntactically more complex. The incidence-based formulation requires some axioms of the quantifier-type forallexistsforall, while the axiom system based on congruence and order can beformulated using only forallexists-axioms.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Drawing on the imagination: The limits of illustrated figures in nineteenth-century geometry.Jemma Lorenat - 2020 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 82:75-87.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mathematicians and the Nation in the Second Half of the Nineteenth Century as Reflected in the Luigi Cremona Correspondence.Ana Millán Gasca - 2011 - Science in Context 24 (1):43-72.
    ArgumentUp until the French Revolution, European mathematics was an “aristocratic” activity, the intellectual pastime of a small circle of men who were convinced they were collaborating on a universal undertaking free of all space-time constraints, as they believed they were ideally in dialogue with the Greek founders and with mathematicians of all languages and eras. The nineteenth century saw its transformation into a “democratic” but also “patriotic” activity: the dominant tendency, as shown by recent research to analyze this transformation, seems (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation