Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Aristotle's Practical Side: On His Psychology, Ethics, Politics and Rhetoric.William Fortenbaugh - 2006 - Boston: Brill.
    Aristotle’s analysis of emotion and his moral psychology are discussed, as are the relation of virtue to emotion, the status of animals, human friendship and the subordinate role of slaves and women. Persuasion through words and character also receive attention.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Aristotle and the Problem of Intentionality.Victor Caston - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2):249-298.
    Aristotle not only fonnulates the problem of intentionality explicitly, he makes a solution to it a requirement for any adequate theory of mind. His own solution, however, is not to be found in his theory of sensation, as Brentano and others have thought. In fact, it is precisely because Aristotle regards this theory as inadequate that he goes on to argue for a distinct new ability he calls “phantasia.” The theory of content he develops on this basis (unlike Brentano’s) is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Aristotle and the problem of intentionality.Victor Caston - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2):249-298.
    Aristotle not only formulates the problem of intentionality explicitly, he makes a solution to it a requirement for any adequate theory of mind. His own solution, however, is not to be found in his theory of sensation, as Brentano and others have thought. In fact, it is precisely because Aristotle regards this theory as inadequate that he goes on to argue for a distinct new ability he calls "phantasia." The theory of content he develops on this basis (unlike Brentano's) is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Animal belief.Roger Fellows - 2000 - Philosophy 75 (294):587-599.
    Non language-using animals cannot have beliefs, because believing entails the ability to distinguish true from false beliefs and also the ability to distinguish changes in belief from changes in the world. For these abilities we need both the fixation of belief and counter-factual thought, for both of which language is necessary. The argument of the paper extends Davidson's argument to the same conclusion (which is found wanting). But denying beliefs to animals has no moral implications.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Animal Belief.Roger Fellows - 2000 - Philosophy 75 (4):587-598.
    Non language-using animals cannot have beliefs, because believing entails the ability to distinguish true from false beliefs and also the ability to distinguish changes in belief from changes in the world. For these abilities we need both the fixation of belief and counter-factual thought, for both of which language is necessary. The argument of the paper extends Davidson's argument to the same conclusion. But denying beliefs to animals has no moral implications.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Mimesis as make-believe: on the foundations of the representational arts.Kendall L. Walton - 1990 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Mimesis as Make-Believe is important reading for everyone interested in the workings of representational art.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   465 citations  
  • Fearing fictions.Kendall L. Walton - 1978 - Journal of Philosophy 75 (1):5-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   195 citations  
  • The paradox(es) of pitying and fearing fictions.Jennifer Wilkinson - 2000 - South African Journal of Philosophy 19 (1):8-25.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Aristotle, thought, and mimesis: Our responses to fiction.Sarah E. Worth - 2000 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 58 (4):333-339.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mind and imagination in Aristotle.Michael Vernon Wedin - 1988 - New Haven: Yale University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts.Kendall L. Walton - 1990 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 49 (2):161-166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   396 citations  
  • Aristotle's Two Intellects: A Modest Proposal.Victor Caston - 1999 - Phronesis 44 (3):199-227.
    In "De anima" 3.5, Aristotle argues for the existence of a second intellect, the so-called "Agent Intellect." The logical structure of his argument turns on a distinction between different types of soul, rather than different faculties within a given soul; and the attributes he assigns to the second species make it clear that his concern here -- as at the climax of his other great works, such as the "Metaphysics," the "Nicomachean" and the "Eudemian Ethics" -- is the difference between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Sympathy and Insight in Aristotle'sPoetics.Paul A. Taylor - 2008 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 66 (3):265-280.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Animal minds and human morals: the origins of the Western debate.Richard Sorabji (ed.) - 1993 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Emotional Animals: Do Aristotelian Emotions Require Beliefs?Juha Sihvola - 1996 - Apeiron 29 (2):105 - 144.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Cognitive Penetrability and Perceptual Justification.Susanna Siegel - 2012 - Noûs 46 (2).
    In this paper I argue that it's possible that the contents of some visual experiences are influenced by the subject's prior beliefs, hopes, suspicions, desires, fears or other mental states, and that this possibility places constraints on the theory of perceptual justification that 'dogmatism' or 'phenomenal conservativism' cannot respect.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   211 citations  
  • Mind and Imagination in Aristotle.Christopher Shields - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (2):371.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Aristotle, De Anima.Harald A. T. Reiche & David Ross - 1963 - American Journal of Philology 84 (2):205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Is perception informationally encapsulated? The issue of the theory‐ladenness of perception.Athanassios Raftopoulos - 2001 - Cognitive Science 25 (3):423-451.
    Fodor has argued that observation is theory neutral, since the perceptual systems are modular, that is, they are domain‐specific, encapsulated, mandatory, fast, hard‐wired in the organism, and have a fixed neural architecture. Churchland attacks the theoretical neutrality of observation on the grounds that (a) the abundant top‐down pathways in the brain suggest the cognitive penetration of perception and (b) perceptual learning can change in the wiring of the perceptual systems. In this paper I introduce a distinction between sensation, perception, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Sympathy and Insight in Aristotle's "Poetics".Paul A. Taylor - 2008 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 66 (3):265 - 280.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Fragility of Goodness.Martha Nussbaum - 1986 - Journal of Philosophy 85 (7):376-383.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   397 citations  
  • The fragility of goodness: luck and ethics in Greek tragedy and philosophy.Martha Craven Nussbaum - 1986 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This book is a study of ancient views about 'moral luck'. It examines the fundamental ethical problem that many of the valued constituents of a well-lived life are vulnerable to factors outside a person's control, and asks how this affects our appraisal of persons and their lives. The Greeks made a profound contribution to these questions, yet neither the problems nor the Greek views of them have received the attention they deserve. This book thus recovers a central dimension of Greek (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   188 citations  
  • De Anima II 5.M. F. Burnyeat - 2002 - Phronesis 47 (1):28 - 90.
    This is a close scrutiny of "De Anima II 5", led by two questions. First, what can be learned from so long and intricate a discussion about the neglected problem of how to read an Aristotelian chapter? Second, what can the chapter, properly read, teach us about some widely debated issues in Aristotle's theory of perception? I argue that it refutes two claims defended by Martha Nussbaum, Hilary Putnam, and Richard Sorabji: (i) that when Aristotle speaks of the perceiver becoming (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Found: The Missing Explanation.Peter Menzies & Philip Pettit - 1993 - Analysis 53 (2):100 - 109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Found: the missing explanation.Peter Menzies & Alonso Church - 1993 - Analysis 53 (2):100.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Circularity, reliability, and the cognitive penetrability of perception.Jack Lyons - 2011 - Philosophical Issues 21 (1):289-311.
    Is perception cognitively penetrable, and what are the epistemological consequences if it is? I address the latter of these two questions, partly by reference to recent work by Athanassios Raftopoulos and Susanna Seigel. Against the usual, circularity, readings of cognitive penetrability, I argue that cognitive penetration can be epistemically virtuous, when---and only when---it increases the reliability of perception.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • Three Dogmas of Response-Dependence.Mark Lebar - 2005 - Philosophical Studies 123 (3):175-211.
    Response-dependent accounts of value claim that to understand what we are saying about the objects of our value judgments, we must take into account the responses those objects provoke. Recent discussions of the proposal that value is response-dependent are obscured by dogmas about response-dependence, that (1) response-dependency must be known a priori, (2) must hold necessarily, and (3) the terms involved must designate rigidly. These “dogmas” stand in the way of formulating and assessing a clear conception of value as response-dependent. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Katharsis.Jonathan Lear - 1988 - Phronesis 33 (1):297-326.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Aristotle on Empeiria.Scott LaBarge - 2006 - Ancient Philosophy 26 (1):23-44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Moralistic Fallacy.Daniel Jacobson - 2000 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (1):65-90.
    Philosophers often call emotions appropriate or inappropriate. What is meant by such talk? In one sense, explicated in this paper, to call an emotion appropriate is to say that the emotion is fitting: it accurately presents its object as having certain evaluative features. For instance, envy might be thought appropriate when one’s rival has something good which one lacks. But someone might grant that a circumstance has these features, yet deny that envy is appropriate, on the grounds that it is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   311 citations  
  • Aristotle: De Anima.R. D. Hicks & Aristotle (eds.) - 1907 - Cambridge University.
    Hicks' edition of the De Anima contains valuable commentary from Hicks as well as useful summaries of the views of earlier commentators.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Why is Aristotle's Brave Man So Frightened? The Paradox of Courage in the Eudemian Ethics.John F. Heil - 1996 - Apeiron 29 (1):47 - 74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Why is Aristotle's Brave Man So Frightened? The Paradox of Courage in the Eudemian Ethics.John F. Heil - 1996 - Apeiron 29 (1):47-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Aristotle De Anima.Wm A. Hammond & R. D. Hicks - 1909 - Philosophical Review 18 (2):234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Aristotle's De Motu Animalium.D. W. Hamlyn - 1980 - Philosophical Quarterly 30 (120):246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  • Aristotle's notion of experience.Pavel Gregorić & Filip Grgić - 2006 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 88 (1):1-30.
    Aristotle's notion of experience plays an important role in his epistemology as the link between perception and memory on the one side, and higher cognitive capacities on the other side. However, Aristotle does not say much about it, and what he does say seems inconsistent. Notably, some passages suggest that it is a non-rational capacity, others that it is a rational capacity and that it provides the principles of science. This paper presents a unitary account of experience. It explains how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Toward an epistemology of certain substantive a priori truths.Joshua Gert - 2009 - Metaphilosophy 40 (2):214-236.
    Abstract: This article explains and motivates an account of one way in which we might have substantive a priori knowledge in one important class of domains: domains in which the central concepts are response-dependent. The central example will be our knowledge of the connection between something's being harmful and the fact that it is irrational for us to fail to be averse to that thing. The idea is that although the relevant responses (basic aversion in the case of harm, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle on the Sense-Organs.Todd Ganson & T. K. Johansen - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (1):89.
    Aristotle’s philosophy of mind is often understood as anticipating present-day functionalist approaches to the mental. In Aristotle on the Sense-Organs Johansen argues at length that such interpretations of what Aristotle has to say about the senses are untenable. First, Aristotle does not allow that the matter of a sense-organ can be identified without reference to the form or function of the organ, so sense-organs are not compositionally plastic. Second, Aristotle’s conception of sense-perception is radically different from anything a philosopher today, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Rationality in Greek thought.Michael Frede & Gisela Striker (eds.) - 1996 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This book, a collection of specially written essays by leading international scholars, reexamines ancient ideas of reason and rationality. The application of changing notions of rationality down the ages has led to consistent misinterpretation of standard ancient philosophical texts: the distinguished contributors here redress the balance, clarifying how the great thinkers of antiquity themselves conceived of rationality.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Aristotle and Animal Phronesis.S. E. Foster - 1997 - Philosophical Inquiry 19 (3-4):27-38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Observation reconsidered.Jerry Fodor - 1984 - Philosophy of Science 51 (March):23-43.
    Several arguments are considered which purport to demonstrate the impossibility of theory-neutral observation. The most important of these infers the continuity of observation with theory from the presumed continuity of perception with cognition, a doctrine widely espoused in recent cognitive psychology. An alternative psychological account of the relation between cognition and perception is proposed and its epistemological consequences for the observation/theory distinction are then explored.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   291 citations  
  • Aristotle on Emotion.J. Dybikowski & W. W. Fortenbaugh - 1976 - Philosophical Quarterly 26 (102):102.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Animal beliefs and their contents.Frank Dreckmann - 1999 - Erkenntnis 51 (1):597-615.
    This paper investigates whether, or not, the behavior of animals without speech can manifest beliefs and desires. Criteria for the attribution of such beliefs and desires are worked out with reference to Jonathan Bennett's theory of cognitive teleology: A particular ability for learning justifies attributing such beliefs and desires. The conceptual analysis is illustrated by examinations of cognitive ethology and considers higher-order intentionality. It is argued that the behavioral evidence only supports the attribution of first order beliefs and that languageless (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Moralistic Fallacy: On the 'Appropriateness' of Emotions.Justin D'Arms & Daniel Jacobson - 2000 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 61 (1):65-90.
    Philosophers often call emotions appropriate or inappropriate. What is meant by such talk? In one sense, explicated in this paper, to call an emotion appropriate is to say that the emotion is fitting: it accurately presents its object as having certain evaluative features. For instance, envy might be thought appropriate when one's rival has something good which one lacks. But someone might grant that a circumstance has these features, yet deny that envy is appropriate, on the grounds that it is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   302 citations  
  • Praktische Syllogismen bei Aristoteles.Klaus Corcilius - 2008 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 90 (3):247-297.
    This paper discusses Aristotle's notion of the practical syllogism. It is argued that the notion of ‘practical’ reasoning in the sense of reasoning which implies motion in one sense or the other is alien to Aristotle's philosophy of nature. All (at least in type) the relevant passages will be discussed. The outcome is that there are three different contexts in which it would be justified to speak of practical syllogisms: (i) human deliberation, (ii) the illustration of the triggering cause of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Philosophy of Action.David Charles - 1984 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Empeiria in Aristotle.Travis Butler - 2003 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (3):329-350.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • De anima II 5.Myles F. Burnyeat - 2002 - Phronesis 47 (1):28-90.
    This is a close scrutiny of De Anima II 5, led by two questions. First, what can be learned from so long and intricate a discussion about the neglected problem of how to read an Aristotelian chapter? Second, what can the chapter, properly read, teach us about some widely debated issues in Aristotle's theory of perception? I argue that it refutes two claims defended by Martha Nussbaum, Hilary Putnam, and Richard Sorabji: that when Aristotle speaks of the perceiver becoming like (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Some more thoughts about thought and talk: Davidson and fellows on animal belief.David Beisecker - 2002 - Philosophy 77 (1):115-124.
    Donald Davidson's argument that non-linguistic creatures lack beliefs rests on two premises: (1) to be a believer, one must have the concept of belief, and (2) to have the concept of belief, one must interpret the utterances of others. However, Davidson's defense of these premises is overly compressed and unconvincing. In a recent issue of Philosophy, Roger Fellows provides new arguments for these premises. In this paper, I explain why I'm not persuaded by Fellows' attempt to bolster Davidson's line of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aristote: Traite de L'Ame. Aristotle & G. Rodier - 1900 - Leux. Edited by G. Rodier.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations