Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The content and epistemology of phenomenal belief.David Chalmers - 2002 - In Aleksandar Jokic & Quentin Smith (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 220--72.
    Experiences and beliefs are different sorts of mental states, and are often taken to belong to very different domains. Experiences are paradigmatically phenomenal, characterized by what it is like to have them. Beliefs are paradigmatically intentional, characterized by their propositional content. But there are a number of crucial points where these domains intersect. One central locus of intersection arises from the existence of phenomenal beliefs: beliefs that are about experiences.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   262 citations  
  • The Knowledge Argument and Epiphenomenalism.Yujin Nagasawa - 2010 - Erkenntnis 72 (1):37 - 56.
    Frank Jackson endorses epiphenomenalism because he thinks that his knowledge argument undermines physicalism. One of the most interesting criticisms of Jackson's position is what I call the 'inconsistency objection'. The inconsistency objection says that Jackson's position is untenable because epiphenomenalism undermines the knowledge argument. The inconsistency objection has been defended by various philosophers independently, including Michael Watkins, Fredrik Stjernberg, and Neil Campbell. Surprisingly enough, while Jackson himself admits explicitly that the inconsistency objection is 'the most powerful reply to the knowledge (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The knowledge argument against the knowledge argument.Michael Watkins - 1989 - Analysis 49 (June):158-60.
    Epiphenomenalism => qualia don't cause beliefs => we don't know about qualia.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • A Limited Defense of Epiphenomenalism.Steve Tammelleo - 2008 - South African Journal of Philosophy 27 (1):40-51.
    The present paper shows that the clearest formulation of J. M. E. McTaggart's antipassage argument, that of D. H. Mellor in _Real Time II, is unsound when its premises are interpreted so that it is valid. This argument need mislead us no longer. The crucial item in the interpretation of the premises is the copula 'is', as in 'E is past'. The copula may be either tensed or tenseless. While this ambiguity of the copula has been noted before, its implications (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Thirty years on -- is consciousness still a brain process?Ullin T. Place - 1988 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 66 (2):208-19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Why qualia are not epiphenomenal.Hans Muller - 2008 - Ratio 21 (1):85–90.
    In this article, I give an original objection to Frank Jackson's argument for the conclusion that the subjective, felt properties of experience are causally inert. I show that the very act of asserting the existence of these properties undermines the claim that they are epiphenomenal. If this objection goes through, it is fatal to the argument in question.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • More troubles for epiphenomenalism.Hans Muller - 2008 - Philosophia 37 (1):109-112.
    I have argued that to say qualia are epiphenomenal is to say a world without qualia would be physically identical to a world with qualia. Dan Cavedon-Taylor has offered an alternative interpretation of the commitments of qualia epiphenomenalism according to which qualia cause beliefs and those beliefs can and do cause changes to the physical world. I argue that neither of these options works for the qualia epiphenomenalist and thus that theory faces far more serious difficulties than has previously been (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology.Marie McGinn & Jonathan Dancy - 1986 - Philosophical Quarterly 36 (145):574.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • V*—The Rational Role of Experience.Michael Martin - 1993 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 93 (1):71-88.
    Michael Martin; V*—The Rational Role of Experience, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 93, Issue 1, 1 June 1993, Pages 71–88, https://doi.org/10.10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Consciousness Explained.William G. Lycan - 1993 - Philosophical Review 102 (3):424.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1124 citations  
  • Comments on Jaegwon Kim’s Mind and the Physical World.Barry Loewer - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (3):655–662.
    NRP is a family of views differing by how they understand “reduction” and “physicalism.” Following Kim I understand the non-reduction as holding that some events and properties are distinct from any physical events and properties. A necessary condition for physicalism is that mental properties, events, and laws supervene on physical ones. Kim allows various understandings of “supervenience” but I think that physicalism requires at least the claim that any minimal physical duplicate of the actual world is a duplicate simpliciter. Some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • The inconceivability of zombies.Robert Kirk - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 139 (1):73-89.
    If zombies were conceivable in the sense relevant to the ‘conceivability argument’ against physicalism, a certain epiphenomenalistic conception of consciousness—the ‘e-qualia story’—would also be conceivable. But the e-qualia story is not conceivable because it involves a contradiction. The non-physical ‘e-qualia’ supposedly involved could not perform cognitive processing, which would therefore have to be performed by physical processes; and these could not put anyone into ‘epistemic contact’ with e-qualia, contrary to the e-qualia story. Interactionism does not enable zombists to escape these (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Methodological epiphenomenalism.Alec Hyslop - 2000 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78 (1):61-70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Cause for Concern.Daniel Hutto - 1999 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (2):381-401.
    This paper argues against causalism about reasons in three stages. First, the paper investigates Professor Davidson's sophisticated version of the claim that we must understand reason-explanations as a kind of causal explanation to highlight the fact that this move does no explanatory work in telling us how we determine for which reasons we act. Second, the paper considers Davidson's true motivation for regarding reasons-explanations as causal which connects with his claim that reasons are causes. He advocates anomalous monism in order (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Supervenient qualia.Terence Horgan - 1987 - Philosophical Review 96 (October):491-520.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Introspecting phenomenal states.Brie Gertler - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (2):305-28.
    This paper defends a novel account of how we introspect phenomenal states, the Demonstrative Attention account (DA). First, I present a set of necessary and sufficient conditions for phenomenal state introspection which are not psychological, but purely metaphysical and semantic. Next, to explain how these conditions can be satisfied, I describe how demonstrative reference to a phenomenal content can be achieved through attention alone. This sort of introspective demonstration differs from perceptual demonstration in being non-causal. DA nicely explains key intuitions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  • The threat of eliminativism.Elizabeth Fricker - 1993 - Mind and Language 8 (2):253-281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Review of P sychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning In the Philosophy of Mind. [REVIEW]Jay L. Garfield - 1991 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (1):235-240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   645 citations  
  • Making mind matter more.Jerry Fodor - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy 84 (11):642.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   121 citations  
  • Making mind matter more.Jerry A. Fodor - 1989 - Philosophical Topics 17 (11):59-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  • Explaining Behaviour: Reasons in a World of Causes.Andy Clark - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (158):95-102.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   535 citations  
  • The Rediscovery of the Mind by John Searle. [REVIEW]Daniel C. Dennett - 1993 - Journal of Philosophy 90 (4):193-205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   534 citations  
  • Still epiphenomenal qualia: Response to Muller.Dan Cavedon-Taylor - 2009 - Philosophia 37 (1):105-107.
    Hans Muller has recently attempted to show that Frank Jackson cannot assert the existence of qualia without thereby falsifying himself on the matter of such mental states being epiphenomenal with respect to the physical world. I argue that Muller misunderstands the commitments of qualia epiphenomenalism and that, as a result, his arguments against Jackson do not go through.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Reply to Nagasawa on the Inconsistency Objection to the Knowledge Argument.Neil Campbell - 2012 - Erkenntnis 76 (1):137-145.
    Yujin Nagasawa has recently defended Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument from the “inconsistency objection.” The objection claims that the premises of the knowledge argument are inconsistent with qualia epiphenomenalism. Nagasawa defends Jackson by showing that the objection mistakenly assumes a causal theory of phenomenal knowledge. I argue that although this defense might succeed against two versions of the inconsistency objection, mine is unaffected by Nagasawa’s argument, in which case the inconsistency in the knowledge argument remains.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • An inconsistency in the knowledge argument.Neil Campbell - 2003 - Erkenntnis 58 (2):261-266.
    I argue that Frank Jackson's knowledge argument cannot succeed in showing that qualia are epiphenomenal. The reason for this is that there is, given the structure of the argument, an irreconcilable tension between his support for the claim that qualia are non-physical and his conclusion that they are epiphenomenal. The source of the tension is that his argument for the non-physical character of qualia is plausible only on the assumption that they have causal efficacy, while his argument for the epiphenomenal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Trying out epiphenomenalism.Peter Bieri - 1992 - Erkenntnis 36 (3):283-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Why the exclusion problem seems intractable and how, just maybe, to tract it.Karen Bennett - 2003 - Noûs 37 (3):471-97.
    The basic form of the exclusion problem is by now very, very familiar. 2 Start with the claim that the physical realm is causally complete: every physical thing that happens has a sufficient physical cause. Add in the claim that the mental and the physical are distinct. Toss in some claims about overdetermination, give it a stir, and voilá—suddenly it looks as though the mental never causes anything, at least nothing physical. As it is often put, the physical does all (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   170 citations  
  • Zombies, Epiphenomenalism, and Physicalist Theories of Consciousness.Andrew Bailey - 2006 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36 (4):481-509.
    In its recent history, the philosophy of mind has come to resemble an entry into the genre of Hammer horror or pulpy science fiction. These days it is unusual to encounter a major philosophical work on the mind that is not populated with bats, homunculi, swamp-creatures, cruelly imprisoned genius scientists, aliens, cyborgs, other-worldly twins, self-aware Computer programs, Frankenstein-monster-like ‘Blockheads,’ or zombies. The purpose of this paper is to review the role in the philosophy of mind of one of these fantastic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Anomalous monism and the problem of explanatory force.Louise Antony - 1989 - Philosophical Review 98 (April):153-87.
    Concern about two problems runs through the work of davidson: the problem of accounting for the "explanatory force" of rational explanations, and the problem posed for materialism by the apparent anomalousness of psychological events. davidson believes that his view of mental causation, imbedded in his theory of "anomalous monism," can provide satisfactory answers to both questions. however, it is argued in this paper that davidson's program contains a fundamental inconsistency; that his metaphysics, while grounding the doctrine of anomalous monism, makes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Epiphenomenalism.Sven Walter - 2007 - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Introspective knowledge of experience and its role in consciousness studies.Jesse Butler - 2011 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 18 (2):128-145.
    In response to Petitmengin and Bitbol's recent account of first-person methodologies in the study of consciousness, I provide a revised model of our introspective knowledge of our own conscious experience. This model, which I call the existential constitution model of phenomenal knowledge, avoids the problems that Petitmengin and Bitbol identify with standard observational models of introspection while also avoiding an underlying metaphorical misconception in their own proximity model, which misconstrues first-person knowledge of consciousness in terms of a dichotomous epistemic relationship. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Physicalism, or Something near Enough.Jaegwon Kim - 2006 - Philosophical Quarterly 56 (223):306-310.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   486 citations  
  • Current issues in the philosophy of mind.Daniel C. Dennett - 1978 - American Philosophical Quarterly 15 (4):249-261.
    This article is an introduction to current issues in the field via a brief review of the history of the field since ryle's "the concept of mind" in 1949. The contributions of ordinary language philosophy and the first wave of identity theory provide the background for the development of the various brands of functionalism that occupy the center of attention today. Problems with functionalism concerned with mental representation, "qualia" and other presumed features of conscious experience are examined. There is an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Feeling causes.Michael Pauen - 2006 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 13 (1-2):129-152.
    According to qualia-epiphenomenalism, phenomenal properties are causally inefficacious, they are metaphysically distinct from, and nomologically connected with certain physical properties. The present paper argues that the claim of causal inefficacy undermines any effort to establish the alleged nomological connection. Epiphenomenalists concede that variations of phenomenal properties in the absence of any variation of physical/functional properties are logically possible, however they deny that these variations are nomologically possible. But if such variations have neither causal nor functional consequences, there is no way (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Painless pain: Property dualism and the causal role of phenomenal consciousness.Michael Pauen - 2000 - American Philosophical Quarterly 37 (1):51-64.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Mind-body causation and explanatory practice.Tyler Burge - 1993 - In John Heil & Alfred R. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation. Oxford University Press.
    Argument for Epiphenomenalism [I]: (A) Mental event-tokens are identical with physical event-tokens. (B) The causal powers of a physical event are determined only by its physical properties; and (C) mental properties are not reducible to physical properties.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   115 citations  
  • Could anyone justifiably believe epiphenomenalism?Richard Swinburne - 2011 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 18 (3-4):196--216.
    Epiphenomenalism claims that all conscious events are caused immediately by brain events, and no conscious events cause brain events. In order to have a justified belief in a theory someone needs a justified belief that it or some higher-level theory predicts certain events and those events occurred. To have either of the latter beliefs we depend ultimately on the evidence of apparent experience, memory, and testimony, which is credible in the absence of defeaters; it is an undermining defeater to a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Knowing epiphenomena.William S. Robinson - 2006 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 13 (1-2):85-100.
    This paper begins with a summary of an argument for epiphenomenalism and a review of the author's previous work on the self-stultification objection to that view. The heart of the paper considers an objection to this previous work and provides a new response to it. Questions for this new response are considered and a view is developed in which knowledge of our own mentality is seen to differ from our knowledge of external things.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • In defence of qualia-epiphenomenalism.Volker Gadenne - 2006 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 13 (1-2):101-114.
    Epiphenomenalism has been criticized with several objections. It has been argued that epiphenomenalism is incompatible with the alleged causal relevance of mental states, and that it renders knowledge of our own conscious states impossible. In this article, it is demonstrated that qualia-epiphenomenalism follows from some well- founded assumptions, and that it meets the cited objections. Though not free from difficulties, it is at least superior to its main competitors, namely, physicalism and interactionism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Epistemological challenges to qualia-epiphenomenalism.Alexander Staudacher - 2006 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 13 (1-2):153-175.
    One of the strongest objections to epiphenomenalism is that it precludes any kind of knowledge of qualia, since empirical knowledge has to include a causal relationship between the respective belief and the object of knowledge. It is argued that this objection works only if the causal relationship is understood in a very specific sense (as a 'direct' causal relationship). Epiphenomenalism can, however, live well with other kinds of causal relationships ('indirect' causal relationships) or even with a reliability account of knowledge (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations