Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Husserl and Gurwitsch on Horizonal Intentionality: The Gurwitch Memorial Lecture 2018.Dermot Moran - 2019 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 50 (1):1-41.
    Gurwitsch is the philosopher of consciousness par excellence. This paper presents a systematic exposition of Aron Gurwitsch’s main contribution to phenomenology, namely his theory of the ‘field of consciousness’ with its a priori structure of theme, thematic field, margin. I present Gurwitsch as an orthodox defender of Husserlian descriptive phenomenology, albeit one who rejected Husserl’s reduction to the transcendental ego and Husserl’s overt idealism. He maintained with Husserl the priority of consciousness as the source of all meaning and validity but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Mind, Self, and Society from the Standpoint of a Social Behaviorist. By Wilson D. Wallis. [REVIEW]George H. Mead - 1934 - International Journal of Ethics 45:456.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Collective Intentions and Actions.John Searle - 1990 - In Philip R. Cohen Jerry Morgan & Martha Pollack (eds.), Intentions in Communication. MIT Press. pp. 401-415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   355 citations  
  • (1 other version)Shared agency and contralateral commitments.Abraham Sesshu Roth - 2004 - Philosophical Review 113 (3):359-410.
    My concern here is to motivate some theses in the philosophy of mind concerning the interpersonal character of intentions. I will do so by investigating aspects of shared agency. The main point will be that when acting together with others one must be able to act directly on the intention of another or others in a way that is relevantly similar to the manner in which an agent acts on his or her own intentions. What exactly this means will become (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Beyond empathy: Phenomenological approaches to intersubjectivity.Dan Zahavi - 2001 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 8 (5-7):151-167.
    Drawing on the work of Scheler, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, Husserl and Sartre, this article presents an overview of some of the diverse approaches to intersubjectivity that can be found in the phenomenological tradition. Starting with a brief description of Scheler's criticism of the argument from analogy, the article continues by showing that the phenomenological analyses of intersubjectivity involve much more than a 'solution' to the 'traditional' problem of other minds. Intersubjectivity doesn't merely concern concrete face-to-face encounters between individuals. It is also (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   129 citations  
  • Second-Person Engagement, Self-Alienation, and Group-Identification.Dan Zahavi - 2019 - Topoi 38 (1):251-260.
    One of the central questions within contemporary debates about collective intentionality concerns the notion and status of the we. The question, however, is by no means new. At the beginning of the last century, it was already intensively discussed in phenomenology. Whereas Heidegger argued that a focus on empathy is detrimental to a proper understanding of the we, and that the latter is more fundamental than any dyadic interaction, other phenomenologists, such as Stein, Walther and Husserl, insisted on the importance (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Edmund Husserl's Phenomenology of Habituality and Habitus.Dermot Moran - 2011 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 42 (1):53-77.
    The concept of habit enfolds an enormous richness and diversity of meanings. According to Husserl, habit, along with association, memory, and so on, belongs to the very essence of the psychic.1 Husserl even speaks of an overall genetic “phenomenology of habitualities”. In this paper, as an initial attempt to explicate the complexity of phenomenological treatments of habit, want to trace Husserl’s conception of habit as it emerged in his mature genetic phenomenology, in order to highlight his enormous and neglected original (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Social Acts and Communities: Walther Between Husserl and Reinach.Alessandro Salice & Genki Uemura - 2018 - In Antonio Calcagno (ed.), _Gerda Walther’s Phenomenology of Sociality, Psychology, and Religion_, ed. Antonio Calcagno, in series History of Women Philosophers and Scientists, vol 2. Dordrecht, Cham: Springer Verlag. pp. 27-46.
    The chapter contextualizes and reconstructs Walther’s theory of social acts. In her view a given act qualifies as social if it is performed in the name of or on behalf of a community. Interestingly, Walther’s understanding of that notion is patently at odds with the idea of a social act originally propounded by Reinach. According to Reinach, an act is social if it “addresses” other persons and if it, for its success, requires them to grasp it. We claim that to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Self-Awareness and Alterity: A Phenomenological Investigation.Dan Zahavi - 1999 - The Personalist Forum 15 (2):444-448.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   282 citations  
  • I and thou.Martin Buber - 1970 - New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons 57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   429 citations  
  • On the Very Idea of Social Construction: Deconstructing Searle’s and Hacking’s Critical Reflections.Martin Endreß - 2016 - Human Studies 39 (1):127-146.
    The starting point of the following inquiry addresses John Searle’s and Ian Hacking’s most prominent critique of contemporary “constructionism” in the 1990s. It is stimulated by the astonishing fact that neither Hacking nor Searle take into account Peter Berger’s and Thomas Luckmann’s classical essay and sociological masterpiece The Social Construction of Reality in their contributions. Critically revisiting Searle’s and Hacking’s critique on the so-called constructivist approach, the article demonstrates that both authors have failed to put forth a sociologically valid understanding (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Structures of a Life-Work: A Reconstruction of the Oeuvre of Thomas Luckmann.Jochen Dreher & Andreas Göttlich - 2016 - Human Studies 39 (1):27-49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Introduction to Phenomenology.Dermot Moran - 2000 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 62 (4):772-773.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   137 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The Social Dynamics of George H. Mead.Maurice Natanson & Horace M. Kallen - 1956 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 12 (2):259-260.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A comparison of Mead's “self” and Heidegger's “dasein”: Toward a regrounding of social psychology. [REVIEW]Valerie Ann Malhotra - 1987 - Human Studies 10 (3-4):357 - 382.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Critique of Dialectical Reason.Jean-Paul Sartre - 1978 - Studies in Soviet Thought 18 (2):163-164.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Einleitung. Aufgabe und Methode der Ontologie und Phänomenologie.Gerda Walther - 1923 - Jahrbuch für Philosophie Und Phänomenologische Forschung 6:1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • There are No Primitive We-Intentions.Alessandro Salice - 2015 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 6 (4):695-715.
    John Searle’s account of collective intentions in action appears to have all the theoretical pros of the non-reductivist view on collective intentionality without the metaphysical cons of committing to the existence of group minds. According to Searle, when we collectively intend to do something together, we intend to cooperate in order to reach a collective goal. Intentions in the first-person plural form therefore have a particular psychological form or mode, for the we-intender conceives of his or her intended actions as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Heidegger, geography, and politics.Jeff Malpas - 2008 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 2 (2):185-213.
    It is often argued that there is a connection between certain forms of environmental or place-oriented thinking and conservative or reactionary politics. Frequently, the philosopher Martin Heidegger is taken to exemplify this connection through his own involvement with Nazism. In this essay, I explore the relations between Heidegger's thought and that of certain other key thinkers, principally the ethologist Jakob von Uexküll, and the geographers Friedrich Ratzel and Paul Vidal de la Blache, as well as with elements of Nazi ideology. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations