Switch to: Citations

References in:

On the Pragmatics of Counterfactuals

Noûs 46 (3):561-586 (2010)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A Defense of Conditional Excluded Middle.Robert Stalnaker - 1981 - In William Leonard Harper, Robert Stalnaker & Glenn Pearce (eds.), Ifs. Dordrecht: D. Reidel. pp. 87-104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   163 citations  
  • Beyond Rigidity: The Unfinished Semantic Agenda of Naming and Necessity.[author unknown] - 2002 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 65 (2):376-377.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • Review of The Logic of Conventional Implicatures by Chris Potts. [REVIEW]Chris Potts - 2004 - Linguistics and Philosophy 30 (6):707-749.
    We review Potts’ influential book on the semantics of conventional implicature (CI), offering an explication of his technical apparatus and drawing out the proposal’s implications, focusing on the class of CIs he calls supplements. While we applaud many facets of this work, we argue that careful considerations of the pragmatics of CIs will be required in order to yield an empirically and explanatorily adequate account.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   214 citations  
  • The hidden-indexical theory's logical-form problem: a rejoinder.S. Schiffer - 1996 - Analysis 56 (2):92-97.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Demonstratives in philosophy and linguistics.Lynsey Wolter - 2009 - Philosophy Compass 4 (3):451-468.
    Demonstrative noun phrases (e.g., that guy , this ) are of interest to philosophers of language and semanticists because they are sensitive to demonstrations or speaker intentions. The interpretation of a demonstrative therefore sheds light on the role of the context in natural language semantics. This survey reviews two types of approaches to demonstratives: Kaplan's direct reference treatment of demonstratives and other indexicals, and recent challenges to Kaplan's approach that focus on less obviously context-sensitive uses of demonstratives. The survey then (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Defending Conditional Excluded Middle.J. Robert G. Williams - 2010 - Noûs 44 (4):650-668.
    Lewis (1973) gave a short argument against conditional excluded middle, based on his treatment of ‘might’ counterfactuals. Bennett (2003), with much of the recent literature, gives an alternative take on ‘might’ counterfactuals. But Bennett claims the might-argument against CEM still goes through. This turns on a specific claim I call Bennett’s Hypothesis. I argue that independently of issues to do with the proper analysis of might-counterfactuals, Bennett’s Hypothesis is inconsistent with CEM. But Bennett’s Hypothesis is independently objectionable, so we should (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Conversation and conditionals.J. Robert G. Williams - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 138 (2):211 - 223.
    I outline and motivate a way of implementing a closest world theory of indicatives, appealing to Stalnaker's framework of open conversational possibilities. Stalnakerian conversational dynamics helps us resolve two outstanding puzzles for a such a theory of indicative conditionals. The first puzzle -- concerning so-called 'reverse Sobel sequences' -- can be resolved by conversation dynamics in a theoryneutral way: the explanation works as much for Lewisian counterfactuals as for the account of indicatives developed here. Resolving the second puzzle, by contrast, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Counterfactuals and substitution of equivalent antecedents.Ken Warmbrod - 1981 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 10 (2):267 - 289.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Defaults in update semantics.Frank Veltman - 1996 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 25 (3):221 - 261.
    The aim of this paper is twofold: (i) to introduce the framework of update semantics and to explain what kind of semantic phenomena may successfully be analysed in it: (ii) to give a detailed analysis of one such phenomenon: default reasoning.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   347 citations  
  • The Philosopher’s Projective Error.Bernard W. Kobes - 2007 - Philosophical Studies 132 (3):581-593.
    This paper is a discussion of Michael Thau's interesting critique in Chapter 2 of Consciousness and Cognition, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002, of the common view that beliefs are internal states.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  • Consciousness and Cognition. [REVIEW]David Braun - 2004 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69 (2):484-491.
    Michael Thau’s book challenges much of current orthodox theory about consciousness and cognition. It is an enormously stimulating tour de force. I highly recommend it.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Context and Content. [REVIEW]William W. Taschek - 2003 - Journal of Philosophy 100 (2):98-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Common ground.Robert Stalnaker - 2002 - Linguistics and Philosophy 25 (5-6):701-721.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   498 citations  
  • Complex Demonstratives: A Quantificational Account.Jason Stanley - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (4):605-609.
    Complex demonstrative phrases, in English, are phrases such as ‘that woman in the department’ and ‘that car on the corner’. They are of particular interest to philosophers for two related reasons. The first involves the problem of intentionality. If there are phrases that are candidates for “latching directly onto the world,” they are such phrases, and their “simple” counterparts, as in the occurrences of ‘that’ in ‘that is nice’. As a result, philosophers interested in intentionality, from the sense-data theorists to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Context and logical form.Jason Stanley - 2000 - Linguistics and Philosophy 23 (4):391--434.
    In this paper, I defend the thesis that alleffects of extra-linguistic context on thetruth-conditions of an assertion are traceable toelements in the actual syntactic structure of thesentence uttered. In the first section, I develop thethesis in detail, and discuss its implications for therelation between semantics and pragmatics. The nexttwo sections are devoted to apparent counterexamples.In the second section, I argue that there are noconvincing examples of true non-sentential assertions.In the third section, I argue that there are noconvincing examples of what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   350 citations  
  • The Logic of Natural Language.G. B. Keene - 1984 - Philosophical Quarterly 34 (135):174-175.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Logic of Natural Language by Fred Sommers. [REVIEW]P. F. Strawson - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (12):786-790.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Indexical Predicates.Daniel Rothschild & Gabriel Segal - 2009 - Mind and Language 24 (4):467-493.
    We discuss the challenge to truth-conditional semantics presented by apparent shifts in extension of predicates such as ‘red’. We propose an explicit indexical semantics for ‘red’ and argue that our account is preferable to the alternatives on conceptual and empirical grounds.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Reasons and that‐clauses.James Pryor - 2007 - Philosophical Issues 17 (1):217-244.
    What are reasons? For example, if you’re aware that your secretary plans to expose you, and you resign to avoid a scandal, what is your reason for resigning? Is your reason the fact that your secretary plans to expose you? If so, what kinds of facts are eligible to be reasons? Can merely possible facts be reasons (for actual subjects)? Can merely apparent facts? Or are reasons rather attitudes? Are your reasons for resigning your belief that your secretary plans to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Thought without Representation.John Perry & Simon Blackburn - 1986 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 60 (1):137-166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   225 citations  
  • Twenty-five years of linguistics and philosophy.Francis Jeffry Pelletier & Richmond H. Thomason - 2002 - Linguistics and Philosophy 25 (5-6):507-529.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Do you know what it means to miss new orleans?Geoffrey Nunberg - 2002 - Linguistics and Philosophy 25 (5-6):671-680.
    1. I have fond memories of the Linguistic Society of America meeting in New Orleans just after Christmas in 1988, the last time I was able to see all my humanist friends from graduate school who were attending the concurrent meeting of the MLA. Shortly after that, the LSA decided to forego the company of humanists and assemble by itself during the first week of January. It's hard to fault the decision. Over and above the obvious practical advantages, like not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Semantics and the objects of assertion.Dilip Ninan - 2010 - Linguistics and Philosophy 33 (5):355-380.
    This paper is about the relationship between two questions: the question of what the objects of assertion are and the question of how best to theorise about ‘shifty’ phenomena like modality and tense. I argue that the relationship between these two questions is less direct than is often supposed. I then explore the consequences of this for a number of debates in the philosophy of language.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Universal grammar.Richard Montague - 1970 - Theoria 36 (3):373--398.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   315 citations  
  • Philosophical Essays.Alan McMichael - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (2):310.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The Problem of Counterfactual Conditionals.J. C. C. McKinsey & Nelson Goodman - 1947 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 12 (4):139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Everything That Linguists Have Always Wanted to Know about Logic.James D. McCawley - 1999 - Studia Logica 63 (1):121-123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Unarticulated constituents revisited.Luisa Martí - 2006 - Linguistics and Philosophy 29 (2):135 - 166.
    An important debate in the current literature is whether “all truth-conditional effects of extra-linguistic context can be traced to [a variable at; LM] logical form” (Stanley, ‘Context and Logical Form’, Linguistics and Philosophy, 23 (2000) 391). That is, according to Stanley, the only truth-conditional effects that extra-linguistic context has are localizable in (potentially silent) variable-denoting pronouns or pronoun-like items, which are represented in the syntax/at logical form (pure indexicals like I or today are put aside in this discussion). According to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Proper names and indexicals trigger rigid presuppositions.Emar Maier - 2009 - Journal of Semantics 26 (3):253-315.
    I provide a novel semantic analysis of proper names and indexicals, combining insights from the competing traditions of referentialism, championed by Kripke and Kaplan, and descriptivism, introduced by Frege and Russell, and more recently resurrected by Geurts and Elbourne, among others. From the referentialist tradition, I borrow the proof that names and indexicals are not synonymous to any definite description but pick their referent from the context directly. From the descriptivist tradition, I take the observation that names, and to some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • The adicity of 'believes' and the hidden indexical theory.P. Ludlow - 1996 - Analysis 56 (2):97-101.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The truth about counterfactuals.E. J. Lowe - 1995 - Philosophical Quarterly 45 (178):41-59.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • ”Why Ain’cha Rich?’.David Lewis - 1981 - Noûs 15 (3):377-380.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • General semantics.David K. Lewis - 1970 - Synthese 22 (1-2):18--67.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   635 citations  
  • Counterfactuals. [REVIEW]William Parry - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (2):278-281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   463 citations  
  • Counterfactuals.David K. Lewis - 1973 - Malden, Mass.: Blackwell.
    Counterfactuals is David Lewis' forceful presentation of and sustained argument for a particular view about propositions which express contrary to fact conditionals, including his famous defense of realism about possible worlds and his theory of laws of nature.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1286 citations  
  • Complex Demonstratives: A Quantificational Account.Eros Corazza - 2003 - Mind 112 (448):734-740.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Does Syntax Reveal Semantics? A Case Study of Complex Demonstratives.Kent Johnson & Ernie Lepore - 2002 - Noûs 36 (s16):17 - 41.
    Following Aristotle (who himself was following Parmenides), philosophers have appealed to the distributional reflexes of expressions in determining their semantic status, and ultimately, the nature of the extra-linguistic world. This methodology has been practiced throughout the history of philosophy; it was clarified and made popular by the likes of Zeno Vendler and J.L. Austin, and is realized today in the toolbox of linguistically minded philosophers. Studying the syntax of natural language was fueled by the belief that there is a conceptually (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Formal Properties of 'Now'.Hans Kamp - 1971 - Theoria 37 (3):227-273.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   154 citations  
  • The Logic of Decision.Brian Skyrms - 1965 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (1):247-248.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   104 citations  
  • On linguistics in philosophy, and philosophy in linguistics.James Higginbotham - 2002 - Linguistics and Philosophy 25 (5-6):573-584.
    After reviewing some major features of theinteractions between Linguistics and Philosophyin recent years, I suggest that the depth and breadthof current inquiry into semanticshas brought this subject into contact both with questionsof the nature of linguistic competence and with modern andtraditional philosophical study of the nature ofour thoughts, and the problems of metaphysics.I see this development as promising for thefuture of both subjects.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Might-counterfactuals and gratuitous differences.Mark Heller - 1995 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 73 (1):91 – 101.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Ifs. Conditionals, Belief, Decision, Chance, and Time.Donald Nute - 1984 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 46 (1):181-182.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • The problem of counterfactual conditionals.Nelson Goodman - 1947 - Journal of Philosophy 44 (5):113-128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   176 citations  
  • Counterfactual scorekeeping.Anthony S. Gillies - 2007 - Linguistics and Philosophy 30 (3):329 - 360.
    Counterfactuals are typically thought--given the force of Sobel sequences--to be variably strict conditionals. I go the other way. Sobel sequences and (what I call) Hegel sequences push us to a strict conditional analysis of counterfactuals: counterfactuals amount to some necessity modal scoped over a plain material conditional, just which modal being a function of context. To make this worth saying I need to say just how counterfactuals and context interact. No easy feat, but I have something to say on the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   108 citations  
  • Μεσσαταοσ.M. M. Gillies - 1927 - The Classical Review 41 (01):9-10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Frege's Puzzle. [REVIEW]Graeme Forbes - 1987 - Philosophical Review 96 (3):455.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   299 citations  
  • Linguistic Intuitions.Gareth Fitzgerald - 2010 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 61 (1):123-160.
    This paper defends an orthodox model of the linguistic intuitions which form a central source of evidence for generative grammars. According to this orthodox conception, linguistic intuitions are the upshot of a system of grammatical competence as it interacts with performance systems for perceiving and articulating language. So conceived, probing speakers’ linguistic intuitions allows us to investigate the competence–performance distinction empirically, so as to determine the grammars that speakers are competent in. This model has been attacked by Michael Devitt in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The argument from binding.Paul Elbourne - 2008 - Philosophical Perspectives 22 (1):89-110.
    In some utterances, some material does not seem to be explicitly expressed in words, but nevertheless seems to be part of the literal content of the utterance rather than an implicature. I will call material of this kind implicit content. The following are some relevant examples from the literature. (1) Everyone was sick. (2) I haven’t eaten. (3) It’s raining. In the case of (1), we are supposed to have asked Stephen Neale how his dinner party went last night (Neale, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Choices: An Introduction to Decision Theory.Ellery Eells & Michael D. Resnik - 1990 - Philosophical Review 99 (2):272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Lewis on ‘Might’ and ‘Would’ Counterfactual Conditionals.Keith DeRose - 1994 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 24 (3):413-418.
    Letting denote ‘would’ counterfactual conditionals like If I had looked in my pocket, I would have found a penny and letting denote ‘might’ counterfactual conditionals like If I had looked in my pocket, I might have found a penny,David Lewis’s thesis regarding the connection between these two types of conditionals is that.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations