Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A logic for default reasoning.Ray Reiter - 1980 - Artificial Intelligence 13 (1-2):81-137.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   631 citations  
  • Review of Jonathan Dancy: Moral Reasons[REVIEW]Donald C. Hubin - 1995 - Ethics 106 (1):187-189.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • Moral conflict and its structure.David O. Brink - 1994 - Philosophical Review 103 (2):215-247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • In defence of infringement.Andrew Botterell - 2008 - Law and Philosophy 27 (3):269-292.
    According to a familiar and influential view, rights are not absolute. To the contrary, they can sometimes be permissibly interfered with. I find such a view of rights attractive. John Oberdiek thinks otherwise. In a recent paper in this journal, Oberdiek has argued that any account of rights that incorporates a distinction between infringing and violating a right is indefensible. My aim in this paper is to argue that Oberdiek's worries are misplaced. The paper proceeds as follows. After some terminological (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • How Do Reasons Accrue?Shyam Nair - 2016 - In Errol Lord & Barry Maguire (eds.), Weighing Reasons. Oup Usa. pp. 56–73.
    Reasons can interact in a variety of ways to determine what we ought to do or believe. And there can be cases where two reasons to do an act or have a belief are individually worse than a reason to not do that act or have that belief, but the reasons together are better than the reason to not do that act or have that belief. So the reasons together―which we can call the accrual of those reasons—can have a strength (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Ethical Consistency.B. A. O. Williams & W. F. Atkinson - 1965 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 39 (1):103-138.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   209 citations  
  • On Conflicts between Rights.Christopher Heath Wellman - 1995 - Law and Philosophy 14 (3/4):271 - 295.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The Realm of Rights by Judith Jarvis Thomson. [REVIEW]Carl Wellman - 1992 - Journal of Philosophy 89 (6):326-329.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   177 citations  
  • Rights, restitution, and risk: essays, in moral theory.Judith Jarvis Thomson - 1986 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Edited by William Parent.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  • The structure of a set of compossible rights.Hillel Steiner - 1977 - Journal of Philosophy 74 (12):767-775.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Rights, Restitution, and Risk: Essays in Moral Theory.Holly M. Smith - 1989 - Philosophical Review 98 (3):414.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Deontic logic and the priority of moral theory.Geoffrey Sayre-McCord - 1986 - Noûs 20 (2):179-197.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Prima facie obligations, ceteris paribus laws in moral theory.Paul M. Pietroski - 1993 - Ethics 103 (3):489-515.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Thomson on the moral specification of rights.William A. Parent & William J. Prior - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (4):837-845.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Judith Thomson and the logic of rights.W. A. Parent - 1980 - Philosophical Studies 37 (4):405 - 418.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Specifying Rights Out of Necessity.John Oberdiek - 2008 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 28 (1):19.
    It is the purpose of this article to make the positive case for an under-appreciated conception of rights: specified rights. In contrast to rights conceived generally, a specified right can stand against different behaviour in different circumstances, so that what conflicts with a right in one context may not conflict with it in another. The specified conception of rights thus combines into a single inquiry the two questions that must be answered in invoking the general conception of rights, identifying the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Lost in moral space: On the infringing/violating distinction and its place in the theory of rights.John Oberdiek - 2004 - Law and Philosophy 23 (4):325 - 346.
    The infringing/violating distinction, first drawn by Judith Jarvis Thomson, is central to much contemporary rights theory. According to Thomson, conduct that is in some sense opposed to a right infringes it, while conduct that is also wrong violates the right. This distinction finds a home what I call, borrowing Robert Nozick's parlance, a "moral space" conception of rights, for the infringing/violating distinction presupposes that, as Nozick puts it, "a line (or hyper-plane) circumscribes an area in moral space around an individual." (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Consequences of Reasoning with Conflicting Obligations.Shyam Nair - 2014 - Mind 123 (491):753-790.
    Since at least the 1960s, deontic logicians and ethicists have worried about whether there can be normative systems that allow conflicting obligations. Surprisingly, however, little direct attention has been paid to questions about how we may reason with conflicting obligations. In this paper, I present a problem for making sense of reasoning with conflicting obligations and argue that no deontic logic can solve this problem. I then develop an account of reasoning based on the popular idea in ethics that reasons (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Conflicting reasons, unconflicting ‘ought’s.Shyam Nair - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (3):629-663.
    One of the popular albeit controversial ideas in the last century of moral philosophy is that what we ought to do is explained by our reasons. And one of the central features of reasons that accounts for their popularity among normative theorists is that they can conflict. But I argue that the fact that reasons conflict actually also poses two closely related problems for this popular idea in moral philosophy. The first problem is a generalization of a problem in deontic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Specification and Moral Rights.Phillip Montague - 2015 - Law and Philosophy 34 (3):241-256.
    In this paper, I offer objections to an approach to formulating principles referring to moral rights that has come to known as “specification.” These objections focus on rights-principles in their role as premises of inferences to conclusions regarding the moral rights of individuals in particular situations. I argue on practical grounds that specified principles have no useful role to play in such inferences, and on theoretical grounds that the specificationist position is self-defeating. This latter argument also suggests an interpretation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Moral dilemmas and consistency.Ruth Barcan Marcus - 1980 - Journal of Philosophy 77 (3):121-136.
    Marcus argues that moral dilemmas are real, but that they are not the result of inconsistent moral principles. Moral principles are consistent just in case there is some world where all principles are 'obeyable.' They are inconsistent just in case there is no world where all are 'obeyable.' What this logical point is meant to show is that moral dilemmas do not make moral codes inconsistent. She also discusses guilt, and argues that guilt is still appropriate even in cases of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   140 citations  
  • An essay in deontic logic and the general theory of action: with a bibliography of deontic and imperative logic.Georg Henrik von Wright (ed.) - 1968 - Amsterdam: North-Holland Pub. Co..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • The Moral Specification of Rights: A Restricted Account.Hallie Liberto - 2014 - Law and Philosophy 33 (2):175-206.
    I begin this paper by summarizing and critiquing the debate between two views: Moral Specificationism about rights and Moral Generalism about rights. I then show how the conceptual framework that Wesley Hohfeld uses to describe legal rights can also clarify the discussion of moral rights, in general, and of moral specification, in particular. Drawing upon Hohfeld’s framework, I argue for the Restricted Account of the moral specification of rights, which stakes out a middle-ground between the view that all justified exceptions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Moral realism and moral dilemma.Philippa Foot - 1983 - Journal of Philosophy 80 (7):379-398.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • Reasons as Defaults.John F. Horty - 2012 - Oxford, England: Oup Usa.
    In this volume, John Horty brings to bear his work in logic to present a framework that allows for answers to key questions about reasons and reasoning, namely: What are reasons, and how do they support actions or conclusions?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   104 citations  
  • Thomson on the Moral Specification of Rights.William A. Parent & William J. Prior - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (4):837-845.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Voluntary euthanasia and the inalienable right to life.Joel Feinberg - 1978 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 7 (2):93-123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • Moral Reasons.Jonathan Dancy - 1993 - Philosophy 69 (267):114-116.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   305 citations  
  • Specifying norms as a way to resolve concrete ethical problems.Henry S. Richardson - 1990 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 19 (4):279-310.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • The morality of freedom.J. Raz - 1988 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 178 (1):108-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   627 citations  
  • The Realm of Rights.J. J. Thomson - 1991 - Philosophy 66 (258):538-540.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   165 citations  
  • Reasons as Defaults.John Horty - 2007 - Philosophers' Imprint 7:1-28.
    The goal of this paper is to frame a theory of reasons--what they are, how they support actions or conclusions--using the tools of default logic. After sketching the basic account of reasons as provided by defaults, I show how it can be elaborated to deal with two more complicated issues: first, situations in which the priority relation among defaults, and so reasons as well, is itself established through default reasoning; second, the treatment of undercutting defeat and exclusionary reasons. Finally, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   159 citations  
  • Prima facie obligations.John Searle - 1978 - In Joseph Raz (ed.), Practical Reasoning. Oxford University Press. pp. 81--81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Rights and duties of compensation.Phillip Montague - 1984 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (1):79-88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations