Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology.Ned Block - 1986 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1):615-678.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   352 citations  
  • Objective Similarity and Mental Representation.Alistair M. C. Isaac - 2013 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91 (4):683-704.
    The claim that similarity plays a role in representation has been philosophically discredited. Psychologists, however, routinely analyse the success of mental representations for guiding behaviour in terms of a similarity between representation and the world. I provide a foundation for this practice by developing a philosophically responsible account of the relationship between similarity and representation in natural systems. I analyse similarity in terms of the existence of a suitable homomorphism between two structures. The key insight is that by restricting attention (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • (1 other version)Truth and meaning.Donald Davidson - 1967 - Synthese 17 (1):304-323.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   498 citations  
  • The Nature and Implementation of Representation in Biological Systems.Mike Collins - 2009 - Dissertation, City University of New York
    I defend a theory of mental representation that satisfies naturalistic constraints. Briefly, we begin by distinguishing (i) what makes something a representation from (ii) given that a thing is a representation, what determines what it represents. Representations are states of biological organisms, so we should expect a unified theoretical framework for explaining both what it is to be a representation as well as what it is to be a heart or a kidney. I follow Millikan in explaining (i) in terms (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Defending the structural concept of representation.Andreas Bartels - 2006 - Theoria 21 (55):7-19.
    The aim of this paper is to defend the structural concept of representation, as defined by homomorphisms, against its main objections, namely: logical objections, the objection from misrepresentation, theobjection from failing necessity, and the copy theory objection. The logical objections can be met by reserving the relation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes.Fred I. Dretske - 1988 - MIT Press.
    In this lucid portrayal of human behavior, Fred Dretske provides an original account of the way reasons function in the causal explanation of behavior.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   980 citations  
  • Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories: New Foundations for Realism.Ruth Garrett Millikan - 1984 - MIT Press.
    Preface by Daniel C. Dennett Beginning with a general theory of function applied to body organs, behaviors, customs, and both inner and outer representations, ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1306 citations  
  • Psychosemantics, or, where do truth conditions come from?Jerry A. Fodor - 1990 - In William G. Lycan (ed.), Mind and cognition: a reader. Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Wide computationalism.Robert A. Wilson - 1994 - Mind 103 (411):351-72.
    The computational argument for individualism, which moves from computationalism to individualism about the mind, is problematic, not because computationalism is false, but because computational psychology is, at least sometimes, wide. The paper provides an early, or perhaps predecessor, version of the thesis of extended cognition.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   113 citations  
  • Real narrow content.Uriah Kriegel - 2008 - Mind and Language 23 (3):304–328.
    The purpose of the present paper is to develop and defend an account of narrow content that would neutralize the commonplace charge that narrow content.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Explaining Behaviour: Reasons in a World of Causes.Andy Clark - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (158):95-102.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   537 citations  
  • Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories.Ruth Garrett Millikan - 1984 - Behaviorism 14 (1):51-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1721 citations  
  • Reasons and causes.Fred I. Dretske - 1989 - Philosophical Perspectives 3:1-15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Individualism and psychology.Tyler Burge - 1986 - Philosophical Review 95 (January):3-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   467 citations  
  • Propositional attitudes.Jerry Fodor - 1978 - The Monist 61 (4):501-23.
    Some philosophers hold that philosophy is what you do to a problem until it’s clear enough to solve it by doing science. Others hold that if a philosophical problem succumbs to empirical methods, that shows it wasn’t really philosophical to begin with. Either way, the facts seem clear enough: questions first mooted by philosophers are sometimes coopted by people who do experiments. This seems to be happening now to the question: “what are propositional attitudes?” and cognitive psychology is the science (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   130 citations  
  • Reply to Millikan.Robert Cummins - 2000 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (1):113-127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Defending the Structural Concept of Representation.Andreas Bartels - 2006 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 21 (1):7-19.
    The aim of this paper is to defend the structural concept of representation, as defined by homomorphisms, against its main objections, namely: logical objections, the objection from misrepresentation, theobjection from failing necessity, and the copy theory objection. The logical objections can be met by reserving the relation ‘to be homomorphic to’ for the explication of potential representation (or, of the representational content). Actual reference objects (‘targets’) of representations are determined by (intentional or causal) representational mechanisms. Appealing to the independence of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • (1 other version)Notes toward a structuralist theory of mental representation.Jonathan Opie & Gerard O'Brien - 2004 - In Hugh Clapin (ed.), Representation in Mind: New Approaches to Mental Representation. Elsevier. pp. 1--20.
    Any creature that must move around in its environment to find nutrients and mates, in order to survive and reproduce, faces the problem of sensorimotor control. A solution to this problem requires an on-board control mechanism that can shape the creature’s behaviour so as to render it “appropriate” to the conditions that obtain. There are at least three ways in which such a control mechanism can work, and Nature has exploited them all. The first and most basic way is for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Representations, Targets, and Attitudes.Robert Cummins - 1996 - MIT Press.
    "This is an important new Cummins work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   160 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Defending the structural concept of representation.Andreas Bartels - 2010 - Theoria 21 (1):7-19.
    The paper defends the structural concept of representation, defined by homomorphisms, against the main objections that have been raised against it: Logical objections, the objection from misrepresentation, the objection from failing necessity, and the copy theory objection. Homomorphic representations are not necessarily ‘copies’ of their representanda, and thus can convey scientific insight.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Representations, targets and attitudes.Ruth Garrett Millikan - 2000 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (1):103-111.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Individualism and Supervenience.Jerry Fodor & Martin Davies - 1986 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 60 (1):235-283.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Banish discontent.Jerry A. Fodor - 1986 - In Jeremy Butterfield (ed.), Language, mind and logic. New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Meaning and Content in Cognitive Science.Robert Cummins & Martin Roth - 2012 - In Richard Schantz (ed.), Prospects for Meaning. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 365-382.
    What are the prospects for a cognitive science of meaning? As stated, we think this question is ill posed, for it invites the conflation of several importantly different semantic concepts. In this paper, we want to distinguish the sort of meaning that is an explanandum for cognitive science—something we are going to call meaning—from the sort of meaning that is an explanans in cognitive science—something we are not going to call meaning at all, but rather content. What we are going (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Defending the structural concept of representation.Andreas Bartels - 2006 - Theoria 21 (1):7-19.
    The paper defends the structural concept of representation, defined by homomorphisms, against the main objections that have been raised against it: Logical objections, the objection from misrepresentation, the objection from failing necessity, and the copy theory objection. Homomorphic representations are not necessarily ‘copies’ of their representanda, and thus can convey scientific insight.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • The role of representation in computation.Gerard O'Brien & Jon Opie - 2009 - Cognitive Processing 10 (1):53-62.
    Reformers urge that representation no longer earns its explanatory keep in cognitive science, and that it is time to discard this troublesome concept. In contrast, we hold that without representation cognitive science is utterly bereft of tools for explaining natural intelligence. In order to defend the latter position, we focus on the explanatory role of representation in computation. We examine how the methods of digital and analog computation are used to model a relatively simple target system, and show that representation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Why there is no symbol grounding problem?Robert C. Cummins - 1996 - In Robert Cummins (ed.), Representations, Targets, and Attitudes. MIT Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Representations, Targets, and Attitudes. [REVIEW]Graham Macdonald - 1998 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (1):175-180.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • Reply.Brian Cantwell Smith - 2002 - In Hugh Clapin (ed.), Philosophy of Mental Representation. New York: Oxford University Press UK.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations