Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. An essay on the origin of evil.William King - 1731 - New York: Garland. Edited by John Gay.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Reflections Upon Ancient and Modern Learning.William Wotton - 1694 - Printed by J. Leake for Peter Buck.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Malebranche.Andrew Pyle - 2003 - New York: Routledge.
    Nicolas Malebranche is one of the most important philosophers of the 17th Century after Descartes. A pioneer of Rationalism, he was one of the first to champion and to further Cartesian ideas. Andrew Pyle places Malebranche's work in the context of Descartes and other philosophers, and also in its relation to ideas about faith and reason. He examines the entirety of Malebranche's writings, including the famous The Search After Truth , which was admired and criticized by both Leibniz and Locke. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous.George Berkeley (ed.) - 1713 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    First published in 1713, this work was designed as a vivid and persuasive presentation of the remarkable picture of reality that Berkeley had first presented two years earlier in his Principles of Human Knowledge. His central claim there, as here, was that physical things consist of nothing but ideas in minds--that the world is not material but mental. Berkeley uses this thesis as the ground for a new argument for the existence of God, and the dialogue form enables him to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   115 citations  
  • The light of the soul: theories of ideas in Leibniz, Malebranche, and Descartes.Nicholas Jolley - 1990 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The concept of an "idea" played a central role in 17th-century theories of mind and knowledge, but philosophers were divided over the nature of ideas. This book examines an important, but little-known, debate on this question in the work of Leibniz, Malebranche, and Descartes. Looking closely at the issues involved, as well as the particular context in which the debate took place, Jolley demonstrates that the debate has serious implications for a number of major topics in 17th-century philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Locke’s Resemblance Theses.Michael Jacovides - 1999 - Philosophical Review 108 (4):461-496.
    Locke asserts that “the Ideas of primary Qualities of Bodies, are Resemblances of them, and their Patterns do really exist in the Bodies themselves; But the Ideas, produced in us by these Secondary Qualities, have no resemblance of them at all.”1 On an unsophisticated way of taking his words, he means that ideas of primary qualities are like the qualities they represent and ideas of secondary qualities are unlike the qualities they represent.2 I will show that if we take his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • First page preview.Andreas Blank, David Bostock, Girolamo Cardano & Daniel Carey - 2006 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 14 (3).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Malebranche on Ideas and the Vision in God.Tad Schmaltz - 2000 - In Steven Nadler (ed.), The Cambridge companion to Malebranche. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 59--86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The Malebranche–Arnauld Debate.Denis Moreau - 2000 - In Steven Nadler (ed.), The Cambridge companion to Malebranche. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 87--111.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Primary and secondary qualities: the historical and ongoing debate.Lawrence Nolan (ed.) - 2011 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    Fourteen newly commissioned essays trace the historical development of the distinction between primary and secondary qualities, which lies at the intersection of issues in metaphysics, epistemology, and philosophy of perception. 'Primary and Secondary Qualities' focuses on the age of the Scientific Revolution, the 'locus classicus' of the distinction, but begins with chapters on ancient Greek and Scholastic accounts of qualities in an effort to identify its origins. The remainder of the volume is devoted to philosophical reflections on qualities from the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • John Locke and natural philosophy.Peter R. Anstey - 2011 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Peter Anstey presents a thorough and innovative study of John Locke's views on the method and content of natural philosophy. Focusing on Locke's Essay concerning Human Understanding, but also drawing extensively from his other writings and manuscript remains, Anstey argues that Locke was an advocate of the Experimental Philosophy: the new approach to natural philosophy championed by Robert Boyle and the early Royal Society who were opposed to speculative philosophy. On the question of method, Anstey shows how Locke's pessimism about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Locke, Boyle, and the distinction between primary and secondary qualities.E. M. Curley - 1972 - Philosophical Review 81 (4):438-464.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The ontological status of Malebranchean ideas.Monte Cook - 1998 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 36 (4):525-544.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Ontological Status of Malebranchean IdeasMonte CookOnce again... we are brought back to a fundamental problem in Malebranche’s theory of ideas. What is the ontological status or nature of ideas? They are neither substances nor modifications of any substance. Yet in the Cartesian schema these are the only alternatives: something is either a substance or a modification of a substance. And Malebranche, however modified his Cartesianism, is at least (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Malebranche versus Arnauld.Monte Cook - 1991 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 29 (2):183-199.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Arnauld's alleged representationalism.Monte Cook - 1974 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 12 (1):53-62.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Locke and the Methodology of Newton’s Principia.Patrick J. Connolly - 2018 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 100 (3):311-335.
    A number of commentators have recently suggested that there is a puzzle surrounding Locke’s acceptance of Newton’s Principia. On their view, Locke understood natural history as the primary methodology for natural philosophy and this commitment was at odds with an embrace of mathematical physics. This article considers various attempts to address this puzzle and finds them wanting. It then proposes a more synoptic view of Locke’s attitude towards natural philosophy. Features of Locke’s biography show that he was deeply interested in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Thomas Reid: Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man: A Critical Edition.Derek R. Brookes & Knud Haakonssen (eds.) - 2001 - Edinburgh University Press.
    This is Thomas Reid's greatest work. It covers far more philosophical ground than the earlier, more popular Inquiry. The Intellectual Powers and its companion volume, Essays on the Active Powers of Man, constitute the fullest, most original presentation of the philosophy of Common Sense. In the process, Reid provides acutely critical discussions of an impressive array of thinkers but especially of David Hume. In Reid's eyes, Hume had driven a deep tendency in modern philosophy to its ultimate conclusions by creating (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Locke on the semantic and epistemic role of simple ideas of sensation.Martha Brandt Bolton - 2004 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 85 (3):301–321.
    This paper argues that Locke has a representative theory of sensitive knowledge. Perceivers are immediately aware of nothing but sensory ideas in the mind; yet perceivers think of real external substances that correspond to and cause those ideas, and they are warranted in believing that those substances exist (at that time). The theory poses two questions: what warrants the truth of such beliefs? What is it in virtue of which sensory ideas represent external objects and how do they make perceivers (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • On True and False Ideas.Antoine Arnauld & Stephen Gaukroger - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (4):849-851.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Mechanism, resemblance and secondary qualities: From Descartes to Locke.Keith Allen - 2008 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 16 (2):273 – 291.
    Locke’s argument for the primary-secondary quality distinction is compared with Descartes’s argument (in the Principles of Philosophy) for the distinction between mechanical modifications and sensible qualities. I argue that following Descartes, Locke’s argument for the primary-secondary quality distinction is an essentially a priori argument, based on our conception of substance, and the constraints on intelligible bodily interaction that this conception of substance sets.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Locke and the Nature of Ideas.Keith Allen - 2010 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 92 (3):236-255.
    What, according to Locke, are ideas? I argue that Locke does not give an account of the nature of ideas. In the Essay, the question is simply set to one side, as recommended by the “Historical, plain Method” that Locke employs. This is exemplified by his characterization of ‘ideas’ in E I.i.8, and the discussion of the inverted spectrum hypothesis in E II.xxxii. In this respect, Locke's attitude towards the nature of ideas in the Essay is reminiscent of Boyle's diffident (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Primary and secondary qualities in Locke's 'Essay'.Michael Ayers - 2011 - In Lawrence Nolan (ed.), Primary and secondary qualities: the historical and ongoing debate. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. pp. 136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Locke's distinction between primary primary qualities and secondary primary qualities.Edwin McCann - 2011 - In Lawrence Nolan (ed.), Primary and secondary qualities: the historical and ongoing debate. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man.Thomas Reid - 1785 - University Park, Pa.: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Derek R. Brookes & Knud Haakonssen.
    Thomas Reid was a philosopher who founded the Scottish school of 'common sense'. Much of Reid's work is a critique of his contemporary, David Hume, whose empiricism he rejects. In this work, written after Reid's appointment to a professorship at the university of Glasgow, and published in 1785, he turns his attention to ideas about perception, memory, conception, abstraction, judgement, reasoning and taste. He examines the work of his predecessors and contemporaries, arguing that 'when we find philosophers maintaining that there (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   500 citations  
  • Idea and Ontology: An Essay in Early Modern Metaphysics of Ideas.Marc A. Hight - 2008 - Penn State Press.
    The prevailing view about the history of early modern philosophy, which the author dubs “the early modern tale” and wants to convince us is really a fairy tale, has it that the focus on ideas as a solution to various epistemological puzzles, first introduced by Descartes, created difficulties for the traditional ontological scheme of substance and mode. The early modern tale depicts the development of “the way of ideas” as abandoning ontology at least by the time of Berkeley. This, in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous.George Berkeley - 1713 - New York: G. James. Edited by Jonathan Dancy.
    <Hylas> It is indeed something unusual; but my thoughts were so taken up with a subject I was discoursing of last night, that finding I could not sleep, ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • Malebranche.Andrew Pyle - 2003 - New York: Routledge.
    Nicolas Malebranche is one of the most important philosophers of the seventeenth century after Descartes. A pioneer of rationalism, he was one of the first to champion and to further Cartesian ideas. Andrew Pyle places Malebranche's work in the context of Descartes and other philosophers, and also in its relation to ideas about faith and reason. He examines the entirety of Malebranche's writings, including the famous The Search After Truth, which was admired and criticized by both Leibniz and Locke. Pyle (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Berkeley's Thought.George Sotiros Pappas - 2000 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
    In this highly original account of Bishop George Berkeley's epistemological and metaphysical theories, George S. Pappas seeks to determine precisely what doctrines the philosopher held and what arguments he put forward to support them. Specifically, Pappas overturns accepted opinions about Berkeley's famous attack on the Lockean doctrine of abstract ideas. Berkeley's criticism of these ideas had been thought relevant only to his views on language and to his nominalism; Pappas persuasively argues that Berkeley's ideas about abstraction are crucial to nearly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • The Battle of the Gods and Giants: The Legacies of Descartes and Gassendi, 1655-1715.Thomas M. Lennon - 1993 - Princeton University Press.
    By the mid-1600s, the commonsense, manifest picture of the world associated with Aristotle had been undermined by skeptical arguments on the one hand and by the rise of the New Science on the other. What would be the scientific image to succeed the Aristotelian model? Thomas Lennon argues here that the contest between the supporters of Descartes and the supporters of Gassendi to decide this issue was the most important philosophical debate of the latter half of the seventeenth century. Descartes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The Works of John Locke. to Which Is Added the Life of the Author and a Collection of Several of His Pieces, Publ. by Mr. Desmaizeaux.John Locke - 2018 - Palala Press.
    This work has been selected by scholars as being culturally important, and is part of the knowledge base of civilization as we know it. This work was reproduced from the original artifact, and remains as true to the original work as possible. Therefore, you will see the original copyright references, library stamps (as most of these works have been housed in our most important libraries around the world), and other notations in the work. This work is in the public domain (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Descartes, Malebranche, and the Crisis of Perception.Walter R. Ott - 2017 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    The seventeenth century witnesses the demise of two core doctrines in the theory of perception: naive realism about color, sound, and other sensible qualities and the empirical theory, drawn from Alhacen and Roger Bacon, which underwrote it. This created a problem for seventeenth century philosophers: how is that we use qualities such as color, feel, and sound to locate objects in the world, even though these qualities are not real? -/- Ejecting such sensible qualities from the mind-independent world at once (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Perceptual Acquaintance: From Descartes to Reid.John W. Yolton - 1984 - University of Minnesota Press.
    Rich with historical and cultural value, these works are published unaltered from the original University of Minnesota Press editions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Ideas and knowledge in seventeenth-century philosophy.John W. Yolton - 1975 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 13 (2):145-165.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Locke on ideas of substance and the veil of perception.Gideon Yaffe - 2004 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 85 (3):255–272.
    John Yolton has argued that Locke held a direct realist position according to which sensory ideas are not perceived intermediaries, as on the representational realist position, but acts that take material substances as objects. This paper argues that were Locke to accept the position Yolton attributes to him he could not at once account for appearance‐reality discrepancies and maintain one of his most important anti‐nativist arguments. The paper goes on to offer an interpretation of Locke's distinction between ideas of substances (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Locke's representationalism without veil.Yasuhiko Tomida - 2005 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 13 (4):675 – 696.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mary Astell's critique of Locke's view of thinking matter.Kathleen M. Squadrito - 1987 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 25 (3):433-439.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Locke and the objects of perception.G. A. J. Rogers - 2004 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 85 (3):245–254.
    It is common to assume that if Locke is to be regarded as a consistent epistemologist he must be read as holding that either ideas are the objects of perception or that (physical) objects are. He must either be a direct realist or a representationalist. But perhaps, paradoxical as it at first sounds, there is no reason to suppose that he could not hold both to be true. We see physical objects and when we do so we have ideas. We (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Representationalism in Arnauld's act theory of perception.Daisie Radner - 1976 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 14 (1):96-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Malebranche.T. M. Schmaltz - 2004 - Mind 113 (449):215-218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Malebranche on Ideas.Andrew Pessin - 2004 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (2):241 - 285.
    I sketch a new interpretation of Malebranche's conception of ideas, thus shedding new light on various of his key doctrines, such as the efficacy of ideas, involuntarism concerning the eternal truths, indirect perception, and vision in God. Briefly, I argue that Malebranche's ideas may be construed as "possible divine volitions," where these are conceptually distinguishable aspects of God, primitively possessed of representational content, by whose exercise God manifests His efficacy. I also defend the claim that Malebranche, in fact, does not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Locke, Arnauld, and Abstract Ideas.Kenneth L. Pearce - 2019 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 27 (1):75-94.
    A great deal of the criticism directed at Locke's theory of abstract ideas assumes that a Lockean abstract idea is a special kind of idea which by its very nature either represents many diverse particulars or represents separately things that cannot exist in separation. This interpretation of Locke has been challenged by scholars such as Kenneth Winkler and Michael Ayers who regard it as uncharitable in light of the obvious problems faced by this theory of abstraction. Winkler and Ayers argue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Arnauld's Verbal Distinction between Ideas and Perceptions.Kenneth L. Pearce - 2016 - History and Philosophy of Logic 37 (4):375-390.
    In his dispute with Malebranche about the nature of ideas, Arnauld endorses a form of direct realism. This appears to conflict with views put forward by Arnauld and his collaborators in the Port-Royal Grammar and Logic where ideas are treated as objects in the mind. This tension can be resolved by a careful examination of Arnauld's remarks on the semantics of ‘perception’ and ‘idea’ in light of the Port-Royal theory of language. This examination leads to the conclusion that Arnauld's ideas (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Locke on sensitive knowledge and the veil of perception – four misconceptions.Lex Newman - 2004 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 85 (3):273–300.
    Interpreters of Locke’s Essay are divided over whether to attribute to him a Representational Theory of Perception (RTP). Those who object to an RTP interpretation cite (among other things) Locke’s Book IV account of sensitive knowledge, contending that the account is incompatible with RTP. The aim of this paper is to rebut this kind of objection – to defend an RTP reading of the relevant Book IV passages. Specifically, I address four influential assumptions (about sensitive knowledge) cited by opponents of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Ideas, pictures, and the directness of perception in Descartes and Locke.Lex Newman - 2008 - Philosophy Compass 4 (1):134-154.
    How are we to understand philosophical claims about sense perception being direct versus indirect? There are multiple relevant notions of perceptual directness, so I argue. Perception of external objects may be direct on some notions, while indirect on others. My interest is with the sense in which ideas count as perceptual mediators in the philosophy of Descartes and Locke. This paper has two broader aims. The first is to clarify four main notions of perceptual directness. The second is to support (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Malebranche and ideas.Steven M. Nadler - 1992 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Nicolas Malebranche's account of the nature of ideas and their role in knowledge and perception has been greatly misunderstood by both his critics and commentators. In this work, Nadler examines Malebranche's theory of ideas and the doctrine of the vision in God with the aim of replacing the standard interpretation of Malebranche's account with a new reading. He argues that Malebranche's ideas should be seen as essences or logical concepts, and that our apprehension of them is thus of a purely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Arnauld and the Cartesian Philosophy of Ideas by Steven M. Nadler. [REVIEW]John W. Yolton - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy 88 (2):109-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Malebranche and British philosophy.Charles James McCracken - 1983 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • The Battle of the Gods and Giants: The Legacies of Descartes and Gassendi, 1655-1715.Thomas M. Lennon - 1993 - Princeton University Press.
    These paperback editions preserve the original texts of these important books while presenting them in durable paperback editions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Direct realism, intentionality, and the objective being of ideas.Paul Hoffman - 2002 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 83 (2):163-179.
    My aim is to arrive at a better understanding of the distinction between direct realism and representationalism by offering a critical analysis of Steven Nadler.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Locke's implicit ontology of ideas.Marc A. Hight - 2001 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 9 (1):17 – 42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations