Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Common Sense and Pragmatism: Reid and Peirce on the Justification of First Principles.Nate Jackson - 2014 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 12 (2):163-179.
    This paper elucidates the pragmatist elements of Thomas Reid's approach to the justification of first principles by reference to Charles S. Peirce. Peirce argues that first principles are justified by their surviving a process of ‘self-criticism’, in which we come to appreciate that we cannot bring ourselves to doubt these principles, in addition to the foundational role they play in inquiries. The evidence Reid allows first principles bears resemblance to surviving the process of self-criticism. I then argue that this evidence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Skeptic and The Madman: The Proto‐Pragmatism of Thomas Reid.Erik Lundestad - 2006 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 4 (2):125-137.
    Even though the philosophy of common sense is not justifi able as such, the assump- tion upon which it rests, namely that there are things which we are not in position to doubt is correct. The reason why Thomas Reid was unable to bring this assumption out in a justifi able manner is that his views, both on knowledge and nature, are to be considered dogmatic. American pragmatists such as Charles Sanders Peirce and John Dewey on the other hand, may (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Proof of an external world.George Edward Moore - 1939 - Proceedings of the British Academy 25 (5):273--300.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   230 citations  
  • Reid's defense of common sense.P. D. Magnus - 2008 - Philosophers' Imprint 8:1-14.
    Thomas Reid is often misread as defending common sense, if at all, only by relying on illicit premises about God or our natural faculties. On these theological or reliabilist misreadings, Reid makes common sense assertions where he cannot give arguments. This paper attempts to untangle Reid's defense of common sense by distinguishing four arguments: (a) the argument from madness, (b) the argument from natural faculties, (c) the argument from impotence, and (d) the argument from practical commitment. Of these, (a) and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Animal in Epistemology.Danièle Moyal-Sharrock - 2016 - International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 6 (2-3):97-119.
    _ Source: _Volume 6, Issue 2-3, pp 97 - 119 In this paper, I briefly summarize the nature of Wittgenstein’s ‘hinge certainties,’ showing how they radically differ from traditional basic beliefs in their being nonepistemic, grammatical, nonpropositional, and enacted. I claim that it is these very features that enable hinge certainties to put a logical stop to justification, and thereby solve the regress problem of basic beliefs. This is a ground-breaking achievement—worthy of calling _On Certainty_ Wittgenstein’s ‘third masterpiece.’ As I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Thomas Reid - Essays on the Active Powers of Man.Thomas Reid, Knud Haakonssen & James Harris - 2010 - Edinburgh University Press.
    The Essays on the Active Powers of Man was Thomas Reid's last major work. It was conceived as part of one large work, intended as a final synoptic statement of his philosophy. The first and larger part was published three years earlier as Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man. These two works are united by Reid's basic philosophy of common sense, which sets out native principles by which the mind operates in both its intellectual and active aspects. The Active (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Epistemic Angst: Radical Skepticism and the Groundlessness of Our Believing.Duncan Pritchard - 2015 - Princeton: Princeton University Press.
    Epistemic Angst offers a completely new solution to the ancient philosophical problem of radical skepticism—the challenge of explaining how it is possible to have knowledge of a world external to us. Duncan Pritchard argues that the key to resolving this puzzle is to realize that it is composed of two logically distinct problems, each requiring its own solution. He then puts forward solutions to both problems. To that end, he offers a new reading of Wittgenstein's account of the structure of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   159 citations  
  • (1 other version)Review of Philip De Bary: Thomas Reid and Scepticism: His Reliabilist Response[REVIEW]Terence Cuneo - 2004 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 2 (2):194-199.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Thomas Reid and the Story of Epistemology.Nicholas Wolterstorff - 2001 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    The two great philosophical figures at the culminating point of the Enlightenment are Thomas Reid in Scotland and Immanuel Kant in Germany. Reid was by far the most influential across Europe and the United States well into the nineteenth century. Since that time his fame and influence have been eclipsed by his German contemporary. This important book by one of today's leading philosophers of knowledge and religion will do much to reestablish the significance of Reid for philosophy today. Nicholas Wolterstorff (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • (1 other version)Critical Notice.Terence Cuneo - 2004 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 2 (2):194-199.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Scottish Pragmatist? The Dilemma of Common Sense and the Pragmatist Way Out.Peter Baumann - 1999 - Reid Studies 2 (2):47-58.
    One of the great attractions of Thomas Reid's account of knowledge is that he attempted to avoid the alternative between skepticism and dogmatism. This attempt, however, faces serious problems. It is argued here that there is a pragmatist way out of the problems, and that there are even hints to this solution in Reid's writings.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • On the Subtleties of Reidian Pragmatism: A Reply to Magnus.Peter Baumann - 2004 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 2 (1):73-77.
    In this paper I respond to P.D. Magnus’ critique of an earlier paper of mine on Thomas Reid’s theory of common sense. In the earlier paper (The Scottish Pragmatist? The Dilemma of Common Sense and the Pragmatist Way Out, Reid Studies 2, 1999, 47-57) I argued that Reid faces a dilemma between dogmatism and scepticism but that there are also hints in his work towards a pragmatist way out of the problem. P.D. Magnus, in a response to this paper (Reid’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Our Natural Constitution: Wolterstorff on Reid and Wittgenstein.Bob Plant - 2003 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 1 (2):157-170.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Reid's Dilemma and the uses of Pragmatism.P. D. Magnus - 2004 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 2 (1):69-72.
    Peter Baumann offers the tantalizing suggestion that Thomas Reid is almost, but not quite, a pragmatist. He motivates this claim by posing a dilemma for common sense philosophy: Will it be dogmatism or scepticism? Baumann claims that Reid points to but does not embrace a pragmatist third way between these unsavory options. If we understand `pragmatism' differently than Baumann does, however, we need not be so equivocal in attributing it to Reid. Reid makes what we could call an argument from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Reid on Common Sense, with Wittgenstein’s Assistance.Nicholas Wolterstorff - 2000 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 74 (3):491-517.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Epistemic circularity.William P. Alston - 1986 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47 (1):1-30.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   121 citations  
  • Cause and effect: Intuitive awareness.L. Wittgenstein - 1976 - Philosophia 6 (3-4):409-425.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • The necessity of pragmatism: Overcoming the stalemate of common sense.Erik Lundestad - 2008 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 6 (2):175-187.
    The paper argues that the relation between the philosophy of common sense and skepticism ought to be perceived of as the relation between the two horns of a dilemma. Each position, it is therefore said, is able to confront the other with a valid objection, something which implies that neither of the two positions are defensible as such. The dilemma is only resolved, it is argued, by the way in which a pragmatic approach to knowledge enables us to incorporate the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Reid on ridicule and common sense.Giovanni B. Grandi - 2008 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 6 (1):71-90.
    According to Reid, opinions that contradict the principles of common sense are not only false but also absurd. Nature has given us an emotion that reveals the absurdity of an opinion: the emotion of ridicule. An appeal to ridicule in philosophical arguments may easily be discounted as a logical fallacy in the same manner as an appeal to the common consent of people. This essay traces the origins of Reid's defense of ridicule in the works of Addison, Hutcheson, Shaftesbury and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Critical common-sensism and rational self-control.Christopher Hookway - 1990 - Noûs 24 (3):397-411.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Reid's First Principle #7.Patrick Rysiew - 2011 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1):167-182.
    By Reid's own account, ‘That the natural faculties, by which we distinguish truth from error, are not fallacious’, has a special place among the First Principles of Contingent Truths. Some have found that claim puzzling, but it is not. Contrary to what's usually assumed, certain FPs preceding FP#7 do not already assert the better part of what FP#7 explicitly states. FP#7 is needed because there is nothing epistemological in the FPs that precede it; and its special place among the FPs (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Common Knowledge.John Greco - 2016 - International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 6 (2-3):309-325.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Thomas Reid between Externalism and Internalism.René Van Woudenberg - 2013 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 51 (1):75-92.
    This paper argues that next to the now widely recognized ‘externalist’ elements, Reid’s thought about belief with positive epistemic status contains a number of so-far unrecognized ‘internalist’ features. This claim is substantiated by (1) identifying a number of conditions that Reid holds beliefs of various sorts must satisfy if they are to have positive epistemic status, and by (2) arguing that, for Reid, many of these conditions are internal conditions. The conclusion is that the externalist and internalist elements in Reid (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Review of Philip de bary, Thomas Reid and Scepticism: His Reliabilist Response[REVIEW]James Somerville - 2002 - Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2002 (8).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reid and epistemic naturalism.Patrick Rysiew - 2002 - Philosophical Quarterly 52 (209):437–456.
    Central to the contemporary dispute over 'naturalizing epistemology' is the question of the continuity of epistemology with science, i.e., how far purely descriptive, psychological matters can or should inform the traditional evaluative epistemological enterprise. Thus all parties tend to agree that the distinction between psychology and epistemology corresponds to a firm fact/value distinction. This is something Reid denies with respect to the first principles of common sense: while insisting on the continuity of epistemology with the rest of science, he does (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Common Sense Lynd Forguson London and New York: Routledge, 1989. vi + 193 p., $42.00. [REVIEW]D. D. Todd - 1992 - Dialogue 31 (1):165-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A New Look at Wittgenstein and Pragmatism.Sami Pihlström - 2012 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 4 (2).
    This essay reconsiders Wittgenstein’s relation to the pragmatist tradition. I first discuss, from a pragmatist perspective, three key issues of Wittgenstein studies: the distinction – invoked in recent discussions of On Certainty, in particular – between the propositional and the non-propositional (section 2); the tension between anti-Cartesian fallibilism and what has been called the ‘truth in skepticism’ in Wittgenstein (section 3); as well as the relation between metaphysics and the criticism of metaphysics in Wittgenstein’s philosophy, and Wittgensteinian philosophy more generally (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Wittgenstein's Pragmatism.Robin Haack - 1982 - American Philosophical Quarterly 19 (2):163 - 171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Peirce on Cartesian Doubt.Robert G. Meyers - 1967 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 3 (1):13 - 23.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Reidian Evidence.Patrick Rysiew - 2005 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 3 (2):107-121.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Thomas Reid and the Story of Epistemology.James van Cleve - 2004 - Mind 113 (450):405-416.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Common Sense.Lynd Forguson - 1989 - .
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Who’s Calling Wittgenstein a Pragmatist?Judy M. Hensley - 2012 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 4 (2).
    In this paper, I focus on the debate that surrounds “pragmatic” interpretations of Ludwig Wittgenstein. By this, I mean the debate between those who read Wittgenstein as a pragmatist or as having pragmatic affinities and those who object to this reading.In particular, drawing on Hilary Putnam’s lecture “Was Wittgenstein a Pragmatist?” and Stanley Cavell’s response “What’s the Use of Calling Emerson a Pragmatist?,” I will spell out the similarities seen between Wittgenstein and pragmatism as well as the divergences emphasized between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Avoiding Broken Noses.Adrian Sackson - 2014 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 6 (2).
    The intellectual affinity between Thomas Reid, on one hand, and American pragmatists such as Charles Sanders Peirce, William James, and John Dewey, on the other, has been noted by several scholars. Indeed, Peirce himself professed an admiration for Reid and referred to his own Pragmatism as entailing what he called “Critical Common-sensism.” In recent times, a number of scholars – chiefly Baumann, Magnus, and Lundestad – have investigated the pragmatist elements in Reid’s thought. Each has identified important ways in which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations