Switch to: Citations

References in:

Integrity and Impartial Morality

Dialogue 51 (2):289-312 (2012)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Self to Self.J. David Velleman - 1996 - Philosophical Review 105 (1):39-76.
    Images of myself being Napoleon can scarcely merely be images of the physical figure of Napoleon.... They will rather be images of, for instance, the desolation at Austerlitz as viewed by me vaguely aware of my short stature and my cockaded hat, my hand in my tunic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   109 citations  
  • The Survival Lottery.John Harris - 1975 - Philosophy 50 (191):81 - 87.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Consequentialism, integrity, and ordinary morality.Alex Rajczi - 2009 - Utilitas 21 (3):377-392.
    According to the moral standards most of us accept and live by, morality generally permits us to refrain from promoting the good of others and instead engage in non-harmful projects of our own choice. This aspect of so-called ‘ordinary morality’ has turned out to be very difficult to justify. Recently, though, various authors, including Bernard Williams and Samuel Scheffler, have proposed “Integrity Theories” that would vindicate this aspect of ordinary morality, at least in part. They are generated by treating as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)What we owe to each other.Thomas Scanlon - 1998 - Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
    In this book, T. M. Scanlon offers new answers to these questions, as they apply to the central part of morality that concerns what we owe to each other.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2524 citations  
  • Equality, priority, and compassion.Roger Crisp - 2003 - Ethics 113 (4):745-763.
    In recent years there has been a good deal of discussion of equality’s place in the best account of distribution or distributive justice. One central question has been whether egalitarianism should give way to a principle requiring us to give priority to the worse off. In this article, I shall begin by arguing that the grounding of equality is indeed insecure and that the priority principle appears to have certain advantages over egalitarianism. But I shall then claim that the priority (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   200 citations  
  • (1 other version)Equality and priority.Derek Parfit - 1997 - Ratio 10 (3):202–221.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   316 citations  
  • Should we strive for integrity?Damian Cox, Marguerite LaCaze & M. P. Levine - 1999 - Journal of Value Inquiry 33 (4):519-530.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Alienation, consequentialism, and the demands of morality.Peter Railton - 1984 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (2):134-171.
    The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   409 citations  
  • Love and death.Dan Moller - 2007 - Journal of Philosophy 104 (6):301-316.
    Empirical evidence indicates that bereaved spouses are surprisingly muted in their responses to their loss, and that after a few months many of the bereaved return to their emotional baseline. Psychologists think this is good news: resilience is adaptive, and we should welcome evidence that there is less suffering in the world. I explore various reasons we might have for regretting our resilience, both because of what resilience tells us about our own significance vis-à-vis loved ones, and because resilience may (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Williams on negative responsibility and integrity.John Harris - 1974 - Philosophical Quarterly 24 (96):265-273.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Standing for something.Cheshire Calhoun - 1995 - Journal of Philosophy 92 (5):235-260.
    Three pictures of integrity have gained philosophical currency. On the integrated self picture, integrity involves the integration of "parts" of oneself into a whole. On the identity picture, integrity means fidelity to projects and principles constitutive of one's core identity. On the clean hands picture, integrity means maintaining the purity of one's agency, especially in dirty hands situations. I sketch each picture and suggest two general criticisms. First, integrity is reduced to something else with which it is not equivalent--to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations  
  • Integrity and Demandingness.Timothy Chappell - 2007 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 10 (3):255-265.
    I discuss Bernard Williams’ ‘integrity objection’ – his version of the demandingness objection to unreasonably demanding ‘extremist’ moral theories such as consequentialism – and argue that it is best understood as presupposing the internal reasons thesis. However, since the internal reasons thesis is questionable, so is Williams’ integrity objection. I propose an alternative way of bringing out the unreasonableness of extremism, based on the notion of the agent’s autonomy, and show how an objection to this proposal can be outflanked by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Needs , Projects , and Reasons.Sarah Buss - 2006 - Journal of Philosophy 103 (8):373-402.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Utilitarianism, Integrity and Partiality.Elizabeth Ashford - 2000 - Journal of Philosophy 97 (8):421.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • The Value of Agency. [REVIEW]Paul Guyer - 1993 - Ethics 106 (2):404-423.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  • Integrity: A Philosophical Inquiry.Lynne McFall - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (2):463.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Reasonable Partiality and the Agent’s Point of View.Alan Thomas - 2005 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 8 (1-2):25-43.
    It is argued that reasonable partiality allows an agent to attach value to particular objects of attachment via recognition of the value of the holding of that relation between agent and object. The reasonableness of partiality is ensured by a background context set by the agent's virtues, notably justice. It is argued that reasonable partiality is the only view that is compatible with our best account of the nature of self-knowledge. That account rules out any instrumental relationship between moral demands (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Persons, Character, and Morality.Bernard Williams - 1981 - In Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973–1980. New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   379 citations  
  • Integrity, practical deliberation and utilitarianism.Edward Harcourt - 1998 - Philosophical Quarterly 48 (191):189-198.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • (1 other version)Common Sense Morality and Consequentialism.Michael A. Slote - 1986 - Philosophical Quarterly 36 (144):399-412.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • (1 other version)Integrity and Moral Danger.Greg Scherkoske - 2010 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 40 (3):335-358.
    While it isn't clear that we are right to value integrity — or so I shall argue — most of us do. Persons of integrity merit respect. Compromising one's integrity — or failing completely to exhibit it — seems a serious flaw. Two influential accounts suggest why. For Bernard Williams, integrity is ‘a person's sticking by what [she] regards as ethically necessary or worthwhile.’ To this Cheshire Calhoun adds a helpful negative gloss:To lack integrity is to underrate both formulating and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Relationships and Responsibilities.Samuel Scheffler - 1997 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 26 (3):189-209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   119 citations  
  • The publicity of reasons.R. Jay Wallace - 2009 - Philosophical Perspectives 23 (1):471-497.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Can an act-consequentialist theory be agent relative?Douglas Portmore - 2001 - American Philosophical Quarterly 38 (4):363-77.
    A theory is agent neutral if it gives every agent the same set of aims and agent relative otherwise. Most philosophers take act-consequentialism to be agent-neutral, but I argue that at the heart of consequentialism is the idea that all acts are morally permissible in virtue of their propensity to promote value and that, given this, it is possible to have a theory that is both agent-relative and act-consequentialist. Furthermore, I demonstrate that agent-relative act-consequentialism can avoid the counterintuitive implications associated (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Does integrity require moral goodness?Jody L. Graham - 2001 - Ratio 14 (3):234–251.
    Most accounts of integrity agree that the person of integrity must have a relatively stable sense of who he is, what is important to him, and the ability to stand by what is most important to him in the face of pressure to do otherwise. But does integrity place any constraints on the kind of principles that the person of integrity stands for? In response to several recent accounts of integrity, I argue that it is not enough that a person (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Integrity and Impartiality.Barbara Herman - 1983 - The Monist 66 (2):233-250.
    Most of us have been brought up on the idea that moral theories divide as they are, at the root, either deontological or consequentialist. A new point of division has been emerging that places deontological and consequentialist theories together against theories of virtue, or a conception of morality constrained at the outset by the requirements of the “personal.” In a series of important essays Bernard Williams has offered striking arguments for the significance of the personal in moral thought based on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Sacrifices, Aspirations and Morality: Williams Reconsidered.Lisa Rivera - 2007 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 10 (1):69-87.
    When a person gives up an end of crucial importance to her in order to promote a moral aim, we regard her as having made a moral sacrifice. The paper analyzes these sacrifices in light of some of Bernard Williams’ objections to Kantian and Utilitarian accounts of them. Williams argues that an implausible consequence of these theories is that that we are expected to sacrifice projects that make our lives worth living and contribute to our integrity. Williams’ arguments about integrity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Demands of Consequentialism.Tim Mulgan - 2004 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 194 (3):355-355.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Demands of Consequentialism.Tim Mulgan - 2003 - Philosophy 78 (304):289-296.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Agent-neutral Consequentialism from the Inside-out: Concern for Integrity without Self-indulgence.Michael Ridge - 2001 - Utilitas 13 (2):236-254.
    Consequentialists are sometimes accused of being unable to accommodate all the ways in which an agent should care about her own integrity. Here it is helpful to follow Stephen Darwall in distinguishing two approaches to moral theory. First, we might begin with the value of states of affairs and then work our way ‘inward’ to our integrity, explaining the value of the latter in terms of their contribution to the value of the former. This is the ‘outside-in’ approach, and Darwall (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Critical Notice.Robert Hanna - 1998 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 28 (3):453-470.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Scope of Moral Requirement.Barbara Herman - 2001 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 30 (3):227-256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Alienation and Internal Reasons for Action.Evan Tiffany - 2003 - Social Theory and Practice 29 (3):387-418.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Agent-centered restrictions: Clearing the air of paradox.Paul Hurley - 1997 - Ethics 108 (1):120-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations