Switch to: Citations

References in:

17th and 18th century theories of emotions

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2010)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Hedonism and virtue.Erin Frykholm & Donald Rutherford - 2013 - In Peter R. Anstey (ed.), The Oxford handbook of British philosophy in the seventeenth century. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. pp. 415.
    This chapter examines the views of seventeenth-century British philosophers on the relation between virtue and hedonism, explaining that many philosophers believed that a defense of virtue required rejection of hedonism. It discusses the reformulation of moral philosophy proposed by Thomas Hobbes, and analyzes the reactions of Richard Cumberland and Cambridge Platonists Ralph Cudworth and Henry More. The chapter also considers the revival of Epicureanism and early modern natural law theory.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Passions and affections.Amy Schmitter - 2013 - In Peter R. Anstey (ed.), The Oxford handbook of British philosophy in the seventeenth century. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. pp. 442-471.
    This chapter examines the views of seventeenth-century British philosophers on passions and affections. It explains that about 8,000 books published during this period mentioned passion and that it started with Thomas Wright's Passions of the Mind in General. The chapter also explores the intellectual basis of the writers who wrote about passion – which includes Augustinianism, Aristotelianism, stoicism, Epicureanism, and medicine – and furthermore, analyzes the relevant works of Francis Bacon, Thomas Hobbes, Henry More, and Lord Shaftesbury.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Emotions in ancient and medieval philosophy.Simo Knuuttila - 2004 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Emotions are the focus of intense debate both in contemporary philosophy and psychology, and increasingly also in the history of ideas. Simo Knuuttila presents a comprehensive survey of philosophical theories of emotion from Plato to Renaissance times, combining rigorous philosophical analysis with careful historical reconstruction. The first part of the book covers the conceptions of Plato and Aristotle and later ancient views from Stoicism to Neoplatonism and, in addition, their reception and transformation by early Christian thinkers from Clement and Origen (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Descartes and the Ontology of Everyday Life.Deborah J. Brown & Calvin G. Normore - 2019 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. Edited by Calvin G. Normore.
    The seventeenth century was a period of extraordinary invention, discovery and revolutions in scientific, social and political orders. It was a time of expansive automation, biological discovery, rapid advances in medical knowledge, of animal trials and a questioning of the boundaries between species, human and non-human, between social classes, and of the assumed naturalness of political inequality. This book gives a tour through those objects, ordinary and extraordinary, which captivated the philosophical imagination of the single most important French philosopher of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Hume on Art, Emotion, and Superstition: A Critical Study of the Four Dissertations.Amyas Merivale - 2018 - London: Routledge.
    This book offers the first comprehensive critical study of David Hume¿s Four Dissertations of 1757, containing the Natural History of Religion, the Dissertation on the Passions, and the two essays Of Tragedy and Of the Standard of Taste. The author defends two important claims. The first is that these four works were not published together merely for convenience, but that they form a tightly integrated set, unified by the subject matter of the passions. The second is that the theory of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Descartes's Concept of Mind.Lilli Alanen - 2003 - Harvard University Press.
    Descartes's concept of the mind, as distinct from the body with which it forms a union, set the agenda for much of Western philosophy's subsequent reflection on human nature and thought. This is the first book to give an analysis of Descartes's pivotal concept that deals with all the functions of the mind, cognitive as well as volitional, theoretical as well as practical and moral. Focusing on Descartes's view of the mind as intimately united to and intermingled with the body, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Hume, Passion, and Action.Elizabeth Schmidt Radcliffe - 2018 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    David Hume’s theory of action is well known for several provocative theses, including that passion and reason cannot be opposed over the direction of action. In Hume, Passion, and Action, the author defends an original interpretation of Hume’s views on passion, reason and motivation that is consistent with other theses in Hume’s philosophy, loyal to his texts, and historically situated. This book challenges the now orthodox interpretation of Hume on motivation, presenting an alternative that situates Hume closer to “Humeans” than (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • From humility to envy: Q uestioning the usefulness of sad passions as a means towards virtue in Spinoza's Ethics.Sanem Soyarslan - 2020 - European Journal of Philosophy 28 (1):33-47.
    In the Ethics Spinoza defines certain traditional virtues such as humility and repentance as species of sadness and denies that they are virtues. He nonetheless holds that they can turn out to be useful as a means towards virtue—in fact, the greatest virtue of blessedness—in the life of someone who is not guided by reason. In this paper, I examine Spinoza’s relatively overlooked claim regarding the usefulness of sad passions as a means towards blessedness. In taking up Spinoza’s treatment of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Passions, affections, sentiments: Taxonomy and terminology.Amy M. Schmitter - 2013 - In James A. Harris (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of British Philosophy in the Eighteenth Century. Oxford University Press. pp. 197.
    Taxonomy and terminology might seem like dull topics. But the diverse ways that eighteenth-century philosophers identified and classified the emotions crucially shaped the approaches they took. This chapter traces the sources available to eighteenth-century British philosophers for naming and ordering the passions, lays out the main vocabulary and concepts used for description and analysis, including the notions of “reflection” and “sympathy,” and outlines the principles that organized explanation, such as the division of the passions into the pleasurable or painful, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • How to Engineer a Human Being: Passions and Functional Explanation in Descartes.Amy M. Schmitter - 2007 - In Janet Broughton & John Carriero (eds.), A Companion to Descartes. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 426-444.
    This chapter contains section titled: The Rejection of Teleology and Its Limits Reconciling God's Goodness with Misjudgment and Misperception The Clock Analogy and Engineering the Body The Special Place of the Passions The Structure of the Passions of the Soul The Need for a General Remedy Notes References and Further Reading.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Descartes on the Identity of Passion and Action.Joel A. Schickel - 2011 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19 (6):1067 - 1084.
    According to the standard Aristotelian doctrine of the identity of passion and action (Ipa), a passion and the action with which it is identified are distinguished through a distinction of reason, and both passion and action are located in the patient. Descartes has recently been interpreted by some scholars to be rejecting Ipa in favor of a view that throws into contention a dualistic interpretation of his philosophy of mind. This article contends that Descartes did hold Ipa, albeit expressed in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Hobbes and the passions.Arrigo Pacchi - 1987 - Topoi 6 (2):111-119.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Was Hume a Humean?Elijah Millgram - 1995 - Hume Studies 21 (1):75-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Spinoza on Destroying Passions with Reason.Colin Marshall - 2012 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85 (1):139-160.
    Spinoza claims we can control any passion by forming a more clear and distinct idea of it. The interpretive consensus is that Spinoza is either wrong or over-stating his view. I argue that Spinoza’s view is plausible and insightful. After breaking down Spinoza’s characterization of the relevant act, I consider four existing interpretations and conclude that each is unsatisfactory. I then consider a further problem for Spinoza: how his definitions of ‘action’ and ‘passion’ make room for passions becoming action. I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Hume.Peter Jones - 2002 - In Nicholas Bunnin & E. P. Tsui‐James (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 709–724.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Biography Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Three Dualist Theories of the Passions.Paul Hoffman - 1991 - Philosophical Topics 19 (1):153-200.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Cartesian Passions and Cartesian Dualism.Paul Hoffman - 1990 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 71 (4):310.
    Descartes retains the Aristotelian doctrine that when an agent acts on a patient, the action of the agent is one and the same as the passion in the patient. However, unlike his Aristotelian predecessors who located the agent's action in the patient, Descartes locates the agent's action in the agent. I examine briefly his motives for modifying, but not abandoning this doctrine. My central claim is that his use of this doctrine implies that he thinks there are modes straddling mind (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Malebranche on the passions: Biology, morality and the fall.Sean Greenberg - 2010 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 18 (2):191 – 207.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Tragedy.Susan Feagin - 2004 - In Peter Kivy (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Aesthetics. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 291–305.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Aristotle After Aristotle Tragedy in the Twentieth Century.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Descartes.Lilli Alanen - 1989 - Journal of Philosophy 86 (1):44-49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Reinterpreting Descartes on the notion of the union of mind and body.Janet Broughton & Ruth Mattern - 1978 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 16 (1):23-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • A progress of sentiments: reflections on Hume's Treatise.Annette Baier - 1991 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    " By the end, we can see the cause to which Hume has been true throughout the work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  • From Passions to Emotions and Sentiments.Amélie Oksenberg Rorty - 1982 - Philosophy 57 (220):159 - 172.
    During the period from Descartes to Rousseau, the mind changed. Its domain was redefined; its activities were redescribed; and its various powers were redistributed. Once a part of cosmic Nous, its various functions delimited by its embodied condition, the individual mind now becomes a field of forces with desires impinging on one another, their forces resolved according to their strengths and directions. Of course since there is no such thing as The Mind Itself, it was not the mind that changed. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Aristotle: Metaphysics, Epistemology, Natural Philosophy.Terence H. Irwin (ed.) - 1999 - Routledge.
    First Published in 1995. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor & Francis, an informa company.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Hume’s True Scepticism.Donald C. Ainslie - 2015 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    David Hume is famous as a sceptical philosopher but the nature of his scepticism is difficult to pin down. Hume's True Scepticism provides the first sustained interpretation of Part 4 of Book 1 of Hume's Treatise: his deepest engagement with sceptical arguments, in which he notes that, while reason shows that we ought not to believe the verdicts of reason or the senses, we do so nonetheless. Donald C. Ainslie addresses Hume's theory of representation; his criticisms of Locke, Descartes, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Reflecting Subjects: Passion, Sympathy, and Society in Hume's Philosophy.Jacqueline Anne Taylor - 2015 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Jacqueline Taylor presents an original reconstruction of Hume's social theory, which examines the passions and imagination in relation to institutions such as government and the economy. She goes on to examine Hume's system of ethics, and argues that the principle of humanity is the central concept of Hume's Enlightenment philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Philosophy and the Passions: Toward a History of Human Nature.Michel Meyer - 2000 - Pennsylvania State University Press.
    For the passions represent a force of excess and lawlessness in humanity that produces troubling, confusing paradoxes.In this book, noted European philosopher Michel Meyer offers a wide-ranging exegesis, the first of its kind, that ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A dissertation on the passions.David Hume - 2007 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by Tom L. Beauchamp & David Hume.
    Tom Beauchamp presents the definitive scholarly edition of two famous works by David Hume, both originally published in 1757. In A Dissertation on the Passions Hume sets out his original view of the nature and central role of passion and emotion. The Natural History of Religion is a landmark work in the study of religion as a natural phenomenon. Authoritative critical texts are accompanied by a full array of editorial matter.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Spinoza on Human Freedom: Reason, Autonomy and the Good Life.Matthew J. Kisner - 2011 - Cambridge University Press.
    Spinoza was one of the most influential figures of the Enlightenment, but his often obscure metaphysics makes it difficult to understand the ultimate message of his philosophy. Although he regarded freedom as the fundamental goal of his ethics and politics, his theory of freedom has not received sustained, comprehensive treatment. Spinoza holds that we attain freedom by governing ourselves according to practical principles, which express many of our deepest moral commitments. Matthew J. Kisner focuses on this theory and presents an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Passion and action: the emotions in seventeenth-century philosophy.Susan James - 1997 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Passion and Action is an exploration of the role of the passions in seventeenth-century thought. Susan James offers fresh readings of a broad range of thinkers, including such canonical figures as Hobbes, Descartes, Malebranche, Spinoza, Pascal, and Locke, and shows that a full understanding of their philosophies must take account of their interpretations of our affective life. This ground-breaking study throws new light upon the shaping of our ideas about the mind, knowledge, and action, and provides a historical context for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Galen: On Antecedent Causes.R. J. Hankinson (ed.) - 1998 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This book is a new edition of a short but fascinating treatise by Galen on causal theory. This text survives only in a Latin translation of the fourteenth century, and it is this which appears here. The volume also contains the first translation of the treatise into any modern language, and the first philosophical commentary thereon. The commentary ranges widely in Galen's voluminous œuvre, and compares his views with those of other ancient theorists. The introduction deals in detail with Galen's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Descartes and the Passionate Mind.Deborah J. Brown - 2006 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Descartes is often accused of having fragmented the human being into two independent substances, mind and body, with no clear strategy for explaining the apparent unity of human experience. Deborah Brown argues that, contrary to this view, Descartes did in fact have a conception of a single, integrated human being, and that in his view this conception is crucial to the success of human beings as rational and moral agents and as practitioners of science. The passions are pivotal in this, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Justus lipsius.Jan Papy - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Stoicism.Dirk Baltzly - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Stoicism was one of the new philosophical movements of the Hellenistic period. The name derives from the porch (stoa poikilê) in the Agora at Athens decorated with mural paintings, where the members of the school congregated, and their lectures were held. Unlike ‘epicurean,’ the sense of the English adjective ‘stoical’ is not utterly misleading with regard to its philosophical origins. The Stoics did, in fact, hold that emotions like fear or envy (or impassioned sexual attachments, or passionate love of anything (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • The passions in metaphysics and the theory of action'.Susan James - 1998 - In Daniel Garber & Michael Ayers (eds.), The Cambridge History of Seventeenth-Century Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. pp. 1--913.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Cognition and Commitment in Hume’s Philosophy.Don Garrett - 1997 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 62 (1):191-196.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   161 citations  
  • Epicurus on Self-Perception.David K. Glidden - 1979 - American Philosophical Quarterly 16 (4):297 - 306.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • From genus to species: the unravelling of Hobbesian glory.Gabriella Slomp - 1998 - History of Political Thought 19 (4):552-569.
    The paper aims at providing an exhaustive analysis of the key concept of glory in Hobbes's works. It is argued that the meaning and role of glory are essentially the same in all Hobbes's writings. The paper claims that in Elements of Law, De Cive, Leviathan, De Homine, Behemoth and in the Correspondence the desire of glory and ambition are given by Hobbes a crucial role in the explanation of human conflict. The paper argues that the status of glory vis-a-vis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Aquinas on the Passions.Peter King - 2002 - In Brian Davies (ed.), Thomas Aquinas: Contemporary Philosophical Perspectives. Oup Usa.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Imagination and the problem of heredity in mechanist embryology.Justin E. H. Smith - 2006 - In The Problem of Animal Generation in Early Modern Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Aristotle: Political Philosophy.Richard Kraut - 2004 - Philosophical Quarterly 54 (216):468-469.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Late scholastic theories of the passions: Controversies in the Thomist tradition.Peter King - 2002 - In Henrik Lagerlund & Mikko Yrjonsuri (eds.), Emotions and Choice From Boethius to Descartes. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 229--258.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Passionate Intellect: Reading the (Non-) Opposition of Intellect and Emotion in Descartes.Amy Morgan Schmitter - 2005 - In Joyce Jenkins, Jennifer Whiting & Christopher Williams (eds.), Persons and Passions: Essays in Honor of Annette Baier. University of Notre Dame Press. pp. 48-82.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Sympathy and comparison : Two principles of human nature.Susan James - 2005 - In Marina Frasca-Spada & P. J. E. Kail (eds.), Impressions of Hume. Oxford University Press. pp. 61--107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations