Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Unreadable Poems and How They Mean.Sherri Irvin - 2015 - In John Gibson (ed.), The Philosophy of Poetry. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press. pp. 88-110.
    Several years ago, the poet & critic Joan Houlihan offered a scathing and hilarious indictment of a lot of postmodern poetry for using words in a way that treats them as meaningless (or, perhaps, renders them meaningless). She suggested that word choice in such poems doesn’t really matter, and that the poet could just as well have substituted in other words without any change in meaning or aesthetic qualities. I argue that she’s wrong about this. I offer an account of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Introduction: The Place of Poetry in Contemporary Aesthetics.John Gibson - 2015 - In The Philosophy of Poetry. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press. pp. 1-16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Poetry and Directions for Thought.Eileen John - 2013 - Philosophy and Literature 37 (2):451-471.
    Do poems provide “scripts” for reader’s thoughts? Kendall Walton’s account of poets as thoughtwriters, in which poems can serve to express readers’ thoughts without positing an expressive thinker in the poem, is considered from various angles. While it seems a minimal expressive thinker needs to be posited, this leaves open other questions about poems as the stuff of thought. Can poems be fully thought, and do readers take ownership of the thinking that poetry prompts? Elizabeth Bishop’s “At the Fishhouses” is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Question of Poetic Meaning.John Gibson - 2011 - Nonsite (4).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Bedlam or Parnassus: The Verse Idea.Simon Jarvis - 2012 - Metaphilosophy 43 (1-2):71-81.
    This essay considers some problems in philosophical approaches to poetry. Philosophers’ accounts of what poetry is are often ill informed. They tend to select, as essential, features that can also characterize prose works: conspicuous metaphoricity, imagination, fictionality, and so on. This essay considers instead a humbler term: verse. It argues that the constraints on language implied by composing in verse are not only a handicap but can also be an engine for thinking. Even philosophy has sometimes been thought in verse, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Thoughtwriting—in Poetry and Music.Kendall Walton - 2015 - In Kendall L. Walton (ed.), In Other Shoes: Music, Metaphor, Empathy, Existence. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 54-74.
    Poetry is a literary art, and is often examined alongside the novel, stories, and theater. But poetry, much of it, has more in common with music, in important respects, than with other forms of literature. The emphasis on sound and rhythm in both poetry and music is obvious, but I will explore a very different similarity between them. All or almost all works of literary fiction have narrators—so it is said anyway—characters who, in the world of the fiction, utter or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Representation and make-believe.Alan H. Goldman - 1990 - Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines 36 (3):335 – 350.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   166 citations  
  • Values of Art: Pictures, Poetry and Music.Malcolm Budd - 1997 - Philosophical Quarterly 47 (187):246-248.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Oxford Lectures on Poetry.A. C. Bradley - 1910 - International Journal of Ethics 20 (2):237-242.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Defining "Poetry".Robert B. Pierce - 2003 - Philosophy and Literature 27 (1):151-163.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Literature 27.1 (2003) 151-163 [Access article in PDF] Defining "Poetry" Robert B. Pierce SINCE TERMS ARE THE TOOLS of literary study, it is important to keep these tools in good condition, above all by having clear and functional meanings for them. Notoriously, many critical arguments about texts are in fact differences about terminology, and many confused arguments are built on vague or arbitrarily used terms. Few have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Two Varieties of Literary Imagination: Metaphor, Fiction, and Thought Experiments.Elisabeth Camp - 2009 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 33 (1):107-130.
    Recently, philosophers have discovered that they have a lot to learn from, or at least to ponder about, fiction. Many metaphysicians are attracted to fiction as a model for our talk about purported objects and properties, such as numbers, morality, and possible worlds, without embracing a robust Platonist ontology. In addition, a growing group of philosophers of mind are interested in the implications of our engagement with fiction for our understanding of the mind and emotions: If I don’t believe that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Intending to repeat: A definition of poetry.Anna Christina Ribeiro - 2007 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 65 (2):189–201.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Defining "Poetry".Robert B. Pierce - 2003 - Philosophy and Literature 27 (1):151-163.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Literature 27.1 (2003) 151-163 [Access article in PDF] Defining "Poetry" Robert B. Pierce SINCE TERMS ARE THE TOOLS of literary study, it is important to keep these tools in good condition, above all by having clear and functional meanings for them. Notoriously, many critical arguments about texts are in fact differences about terminology, and many confused arguments are built on vague or arbitrarily used terms. Few have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Poetry and truth.John Koethe - 2009 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 33 (1):53-60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Uses of Poetry: Renewing an Educational Understanding of a Language Art.Karen Simecek & Viv Ellis - 2017 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 51 (1):98-114.
    Poetry holds an important place as part of our cultural heritage.1 However, despite poetry’s apparent cultural value, there have been surprisingly few attempts to articulate clearly how this should be reflected in the teaching curriculum in our schools and universities. As a consequence of this lack of clarity, the cultural value of poetry gives way to the increasing emphasis on providing instrumental justification for the teaching curriculum; including poetry in the curriculum is often justified in terms of promoting transferable skills (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Thought and Poetry.John Koethe - 2001 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 25 (1):5-11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Thought and poetry.John Koethe - 2001 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 25 (1):5–11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The elusiveness of poetic meaning.Peter Lamarque - 2009 - Ratio 22 (4):398-420.
    Various aspects of poetic meaning are discussed, centred on the relation of form and content. A C Bradley's thesis of form-content identity, suitably reformulated, is defended against criticisms by Peter Kivy. It is argued that the unity of form-content is not discovered in poetry so much as demanded of it when poetry is read 'as poetry'. A shift of emphasis from talking about 'meaning' in poetry to talking about 'content' is promoted, as is a more prominent role for 'experience' in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Cultivating Intimacy: The Use of the Second Person in Lyric Poetry.Karen Simecek - 2019 - Philosophy and Literature 43 (2):501-518.
    Lyric poetry is often associated with expression of the personal. For instance, the work of the so-called “confessional” poets, such as Sylvia Plath and Anne Sexton, is often thought to reveal inmost thoughts and feelings of the poetic voice through first personal expression. The lyric poem, with its use of personal pronouns and singularity of voice, appears to invite the reader to experience the unfolding of the words as the intimate expression of another.Intimacy itself is associated with attention to another (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • “Like a Picture or a Bump on the Head”: Vision, Cognition, and the Language of Poetry.Troy Jollimore - 2009 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 33 (1):131-158.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Toward a philosophy of poetry.Anna Christina Ribeiro - 2009 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 33 (1):61-77.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Expressiveness and expression in music and poetry.Robert Stecker - 2001 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 59 (1):85-96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts.Kendall L. WALTON - 1990 - Philosophy 66 (258):527-529.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   389 citations  
  • How not to do things with words.Max De Gaynesford - unknown
    If philosophy and poetry are to illuminate each other, we should first understand their tendencies to mutual antipathy. Examining mutual misapprehension is part of this task. J. L. Austin's remarks on poetry offer one such point of entry: they are often cited by poets and critics as an example of philosophy's blindness to poetry. These remarks are complex and their purpose obscure—more so than those who take exception to them usually allow or admit. But it is reasonable to think that, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Poetic Thickness.R. McGregor - 2014 - British Journal of Aesthetics 54 (1):49-64.
    The purpose of this article is to demonstrate that the experience of a poem qua poem is an experience of poetic thickness , i.e. an experience in which poetic form and poetic content are inseparable. I present a critical analysis of A. C. Bradley’s ‘Poetry for Poetry’s Sake’ lecture in Section 1, indicating both the strengths and weaknesses of his conception of resonant meaning. Section 2 draws on subsequent work by I. A. Richards and Peter Lamarque to advance my account (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Poetry and abstract thought.Peter Lamarque - 2009 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 33 (1):37-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • About about: On poetry and paraphrase.Angela Leighton - 2009 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 33 (1):167-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Beyond Narrative: Poetry, Emotion and the Perspectival View.Karen Simecek - 2015 - British Journal of Aesthetics 55 (4):497-513.
    The view that narrative artworks can offer insights into our lives, in particular, into the nature of the emotions, has gained increasing popularity in recent years. However, talk of narrative often involves reference to a perspective or point of view, which indicates a more fundamental mechanism at work. In this article, I argue that our understanding of the emotions is incomplete without adequate attention to the perspectival structures in which they are embedded. Drawing on Bennett Helm’s theory of emotion, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Truth in poetry : particulars and universals.Richard Eldridge - 2007 - In Garry Hagberg & Walter Jost (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Literature. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 385–398.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts.Noel Carroll - 1995 - Philosophical Quarterly 45 (178):93-99.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Defining "poetry".Robert B. Pierce - 2003 - Philosophy and Literature 27 (1):151-163.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Literature 27.1 (2003) 151-163 [Access article in PDF] Defining "Poetry" Robert B. Pierce SINCE TERMS ARE THE TOOLS of literary study, it is important to keep these tools in good condition, above all by having clear and functional meanings for them. Notoriously, many critical arguments about texts are in fact differences about terminology, and many confused arguments are built on vague or arbitrarily used terms. Few have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How Not To Do Things With Words: J. L. Austin on Poetry: Articles.Maximilian de Gaynesford - 2011 - British Journal of Aesthetics 51 (1):31-49.
    If philosophy and poetry are to illuminate each other, we should first understand their tendencies to mutual antipathy. Examining mutual misapprehension is part of this task. J. L. Austin's remarks on poetry offer one such point of entry: they are often cited by poets and critics as an example of philosophy's blindness to poetry. These remarks are complex and their purpose obscure—more so than those who take exception to them usually allow or admit. But it is reasonable to think that, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Poetry and abstraction.M. W. Rowe - 1996 - British Journal of Aesthetics 36 (1):1-15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations