Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Semantics for Non-Declaratives.Kirk Ludwig & Dan Boisvert - 2006 - In Ernest Lepore & Barry C. Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language. Oxford University Press.
    This article begins by distinguishing force and mood. Then it lays out desiderata on a successful account. It sketches as background the program of truth-theoretic semantics. Next, it surveys assimilation approaches and argues that they are inadequate. Then it shows how the fulfillment-conditional approach can be applied to imperatives, interrogatives, molecular sentences containing them, and quantification into mood markers. Next, it considers briefly the recent set of propositions approach to the semantics of interrogatives and exclamatives. Finally, it shows how to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • On Practical Inference with an Excursus on Theoretical Inference. E. Sosa - 1970 - Logique Et Analyse 13 (49):213.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Thinking and Doing, The Philosophical Foundations of Institutions.[author unknown] - 1977 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 39 (2):351-353.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The logical form of imperatives.D. S. Clarke - 1975 - Philosophia 5 (4):417-427.
    This paper attempts to outline the logical structure of imperatives. It criticizes the prevailing view that this structure is isomorphic with that for indicatives. For "mixed" imperatives with constituents in both indicative and imperative moods (e.G., Conditional imperatives with indicative antecedents) there are features unique to imperatives. These features are specified, And consequences of them are traced. Finally, Formation rules for imperatives are stated.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Mood Constancy in Mixed Inferences.D. S. Clarke - 1970 - Analysis 30 (3):100 - 103.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Contrary-to-Duty Imperatives and Deontic Logic.R. M. Chisholm - 1963 - Analysis 24 (2):33-36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   123 citations  
  • Logic and Semantics for Imperatives.Nate Charlow - 2014 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 43 (4):617-664.
    In this paper I will develop a view about the semantics of imperatives, which I term Modal Noncognitivism, on which imperatives might be said to have truth conditions (dispositionally, anyway), but on which it does not make sense to see them as expressing propositions (hence does not make sense to ascribe to them truth or falsity). This view stands against “Cognitivist” accounts of the semantics of imperatives, on which imperatives are claimed to express propositions, which are then enlisted in explanations (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • The Logic of Commands.Hector-Neri Castaneda - 1970 - Philosophical Review 79 (3):439.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Outline of a theory on the general logical structure of the language of action.Hector Neri Castañeda - 1960 - Theoria 26 (3):151-182.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Imperative reasonings.Hector Neri Castaneda - 1960 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 21 (1):21-49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Imperative reasonings.Hector-Neri Castaneda, B. A. O. Williams, P. T. Geach, Nicholas Rescher, John Robison & Andre Gombay - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (2):314-318.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • II—Actions, Imperatives, and Obligations.Hector-Neri Castañeda - 1968 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 68 (1):25-48.
    Hector-Neri Castañeda; II—Actions, Imperatives, and Obligations, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 68, Issue 1, 1 June 1968, Pages 25–48, https://.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Imperatives and Deontic Logic.Hector Neri Castaneda - 1958 - Analysis 19 (2):42 - 48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Incompatibilism and the transfer of power necessity.Erik Carlson - 2000 - Noûs 34 (2):277-290.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Which Modal Models are the Right Ones (for Logical Necessity)?John P. Burgess - 2010 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 18 (2):145-158.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Ethics, Persuasion and Truth.David O. Brink & J. J. C. Smart - 1987 - Philosophical Review 96 (2):290.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The semiotic status of commands.Herbert Gaylord Bohnert - 1945 - Philosophy of Science 12 (4):302-315.
    The large number of writers who have in recent years attacked the problem of the logical nature of commands appear generally in agreement in accepting the distinction of common grammar between imperative and declarative sentences as representing, albeit in no clear one-to-one manner, some real difference in the logical character of the two types of expression, and possibly in the psychological sign-functioning mechanism itself. The crucial logical difference adduced is that commands can apparently rot be classified as true or false. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The Semiotic Status of Commands.Herbert Gaylord Bohnert - 1946 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 11 (3):98-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Words and Deeds. Problems in the Theory of Speech Acts.Graham Bird - 1979 - Philosophical Quarterly 29 (116):272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Imperatives and contradiction.Lars Bergstrom - 1970 - Mind 79 (315):421-424.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Hector-Neri Castañeda. Imperative reasonings. Philosophy and phenomenological research, vol. 21 no. 1 , pp. 21–49. - B. A. O. Williams. Imperative inference. I. Analysis , vol. 23 suppl. , pp. 30–36. - P. T. Geach. Imperative inference. II. Analysis , vol. 23 suppl. , pp. 37–42. - Nicholas Rescher and John Robison. Can one infer commands from commands?Analysis , vol. 24 no. 5 , pp. 176–179. - André Gombay. Imperative inference and disjunction. Analysis , vol. 25 no. 3 , pp. 58–62. - Lennart Åqvist. Choice-offering and alternative-presenting disjunctive commands. Analysis , no. 5 , pp. 182–184. - A. J. Kenny. Practical inference. Analysis , vol. 26 no. 3 , pp. 65–75. - P. T. Geach. Dr. Kenny on practical inference. Analysis , vol. 26 no. 3 , pp. 76–79. - Yehoshua Bar-Hillel. Imperative inference. Analysis , vol. 26 no. 3 , pp. 79–82. - André Gombay. What is imperative inference?Analysis , vol. 27 no. 5 , pp. 145–152. - R. M. Hare. Some alleged differences between imperatives and indicat. [REVIEW]Jonathan Bennett - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (2):314-318.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Hector meets 3-d: A diaphilosophical epic.Marvin Belzer & Barry Loewer - 1994 - Philosophical Perspectives 8:389-414.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Instrumental reasons.Niko Kolodny - 2018 - In Daniel Star (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity. New York, NY, United States of America: Oxford University Press.
    Often our reason for doing something is an "instrumental reason": that doing that is a means to doing something else that we have reason to do. What principles govern this "instrumental transmission" of reasons from ends to means? Negatively, I argue against principles often invoked in the literature, which focus on necessary or sufficient means. Positively, I propose a principle, "General Transmission," which answers to two intuitive desiderata: that reason transmits to means that are "probabilizing" and "nonsuperfluous" with respect to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Imperatives, Logic Of.Peter B. M. Vranas - 2013 - In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Hoboken, NJ: Blackwell. pp. 2575-2585.
    Suppose that a sign at the entrance of a hotel reads: “Don’t enter these premises unless you are accompanied by a registered guest”. You see someone who is about to enter, and you tell her: “Don’t enter these premises if you are an unaccompanied registered guest”. She asks why, and you reply: “It follows from what the sign says”. It seems that you made a valid inference from an imperative premise to an imperative conclusion. But it also seems that imperatives (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A reply to my critics.George Edward Moore - 1942 - In Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.), The philosophy of G. E. Moore. New York,: Tudor Pub. Co..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   279 citations  
  • The Language of Morals.Richard Mervyn Hare - 1952 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    Hare has written a clear, brief, and readable introduction to ethics which looks at all the fundamental problems of the subject.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   487 citations  
  • Ethics, Persuasion and Truth.J. J. C. Smart - 1984 - Boston: Routledge.
    Originally published in 1984, deals with meta-ethics - that is the semantics and pragmatics of ethical language. This book eschews the notions of meaning and analyticity on which meta-ethics normally depends. It discusses questions of free will and responsibility and the relations between ethics on the one hand and science and metaphysics on the other. The author regards ethics as concerned with deciding what to do and with persuading others - not with exploring a supposed realm of ethical fact.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Imperatives and Their Logics.Nichloas J. Moutafakis - 1975 - New Delhi, India: Sterling Publishers.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The logic of commands.Nicholas Rescher - 1966 - New York,: Dover Publications.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Consistency and Realism.Bernard A. O. Williams - 1966 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 40 (1):1-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Poincarés Rule.Ota Weinberger - 1976 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 14 (3):356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ponicarés rule (oder: Ein bisschen hermeneutik, Herr Morscher!).Ota Weinberger - 1976 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 14 (3):356-358.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • New foundations for imperative logic I: Logical connectives, consistency, and quantifiers.Peter B. M. Vranas - 2008 - Noûs 42 (4):529-572.
    Imperatives cannot be true or false, so they are shunned by logicians. And yet imperatives can be combined by logical connectives: "kiss me and hug me" is the conjunction of "kiss me" with "hug me". This example may suggest that declarative and imperative logic are isomorphic: just as the conjunction of two declaratives is true exactly if both conjuncts are true, the conjunction of two imperatives is satisfied exactly if both conjuncts are satisfied—what more is there to say? Much more, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • New Foundations for Imperative Logic: Pure Imperative Inference.P. B. M. Vranas - 2011 - Mind 120 (478):369-446.
    Imperatives cannot be true, but they can be obeyed or binding: `Surrender!' is obeyed if you surrender and is binding if you have a reason to surrender. A pure declarative argument — whose premisses and conclusion are declaratives — is valid exactly if, necessarily, its conclusion is true if the conjunction of its premisses is true; similarly, I suggest, a pure imperative argument — whose premisses and conclusion are imperatives — is obedience-valid (alternatively: bindingness-valid) exactly if, necessarily, its conclusion is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • In Defense of Imperative Inference.Peter B. M. Vranas - 2010 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 39 (1):59 - 71.
    "Surrender; therefore, surrender or fight" is apparently an argument corresponding to an inference from an imperative to an imperative. Several philosophers, however (Williams 1963; Wedeking 1970; Harrison 1991; Hansen 2008), have denied that imperative inferences exist, arguing that (1) no such inferences occur in everyday life, (2) imperatives cannot be premises or conclusions of inferences because it makes no sense to say, for example, "since surrender" or "it follows that surrender or fight", and (3) distinct imperatives have conflicting permissive presuppositions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • In Defense of Imperative Inference.Peter B. M. Vranas - 2018 - Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy 55:85-92.
    “Surrender; therefore, surrender or fight” is apparently an argument corresponding to an inference from an imperative to an imperative. Several philosophers, however, have denied that imperative inferences exist, arguing that no such inferences occur in everyday life, imperatives cannot be premises or conclusions of inferences because it makes no sense to say, for example, “since surrender” or “it follows that surrender or fight”, and distinct imperatives have conflicting permissive presuppositions, so issuing distinct imperatives amounts to changing one’s mind and thus (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • I Ought, Therefore I Can.Peter B. M. Vranas - 2007 - Philosophical Studies 136 (2):167-216.
    I defend the following version of the ought-implies-can principle: (OIC) by virtue of conceptual necessity, an agent at a given time has an (objective, pro tanto) obligation to do only what the agent at that time has the ability and opportunity to do. In short, obligations correspond to ability plus opportunity. My argument has three premises: (1) obligations correspond to reasons for action; (2) reasons for action correspond to potential actions; (3) potential actions correspond to ability plus opportunity. In the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  • Do Cry Over Spilt Milk.Peter B. M. Vranas - 2005 - The Monist 88 (3):370-387.
    There is widespread agreement, even among those who accept the possibility of backward causation, that it is impossible to change the past. I argue that this agreement corresponds to a relatively uninteresting understanding of what changing the past amounts to. In one sense it is indeed impossible to change the past: in no possible world is an action performed which makes the past in that world different from the past in that world. In another sense, however, it may be possible (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Deontic logic without deontic operators.Hermann Vetter - 1971 - Theory and Decision 2 (1):67-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Imperatives, logic, and moral obligation.Robert G. Turnbull - 1960 - Philosophy of Science 27 (4):374-390.
    It is claimed that 'Do x!' means 'Then you will do x'. Answering a "Why?" question concerning the former may take either of two forms, viz., 'Because --' or 'If you wish to --'. The second answer completes the truncated hypothetical. "Ought" sentences are treated as a species of imperatives involving universality in the "if" clause ('If anyone wished to --'). Moral "ought" sentences involve a double universality, viz., the one mentioned above and universality connecting the action with social harmony (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Intentions, beliefs, and imperative logic.R. F. Stalley - 1972 - Mind 81 (321):18-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Imperatives and Referential Opacity.Ernest Sosa - 1966 - Analysis 27 (2):49 - 52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Ethics, persuasion, and truth.John Jamieson Carswell Smart - 1984 - Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
    I INTRODUCTION FIRST ORDER QUESTIONS AND SECOND ORDER QUESTIONS In this book I wish to discuss certain questions that are about ethics rather than in ethics ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Imperatives and Logic.Alf Ross - 1944 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 9 (2):48-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Imperatives and logic.Alf Ross - 1944 - Philosophy of Science 11 (1):30-46.
    The existing literature treats of several investigations with a certain bearing on the question which is roughly indicated by the title “Imperatives and Logic.” Some of those investigations, however, are entirely outside the scope of the present work.Mally sets himself the task of developing a “Logik des Willens” constituting a parallel to the usual logic, the “Logik des Denkens". In order to emphasize its independence, the author also calls this “Logik des Willens” “Deontik”, and he conceives it as being based (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   99 citations  
  • Truthmaking, entailment, and the conjunction thesis.Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra - 2006 - Mind 115 (460):957-982.
    In this paper I undermine the Entailment Principle according to which if an entity is a truthmaker for a certain proposition and this proposition entails another, then the entity in question is a truthmaker for the latter proposition. I argue that the two most promising versions of the principle entail the popular but false Conjunction Thesis, namely that a truthmaker for a conjunction is a truthmaker for its conjuncts. One promising version of the principle understands entailment as strict implication but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Response to My Critics (The Sydney Sessions).Stefanie Rocknak - 2022 - Hume Studies 45 (1):77-93.
    Response to Don Baxter, Don Garrett and Jennifer Marusic regarding my book Imagined Causes: Hume's Conception of Objects; initially delivered at the 2016 Hume Conference in Sydney, Australia as part of the Author Meets Critics session.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Non-Assertoric Inference.Robert P. McArthur & David Welker - 1974 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 15 (2):225--244.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Geach on Murder and Sodomy.R. M. Hare - 1977 - Philosophy 52 (202):467 - 472.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The logic of demand-sentences.Rose Rand - 1962 - Synthese 14 (4):237 - 254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations