Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. On All Strong Kleene Generalizations of Classical Logic.Stefan Wintein - 2016 - Studia Logica 104 (3):503-545.
    By using the notions of exact truth and exact falsity, one can give 16 distinct definitions of classical consequence. This paper studies the class of relations that results from these definitions in settings that are paracomplete, paraconsistent or both and that are governed by the Strong Kleene schema. Besides familiar logics such as Strong Kleene logic, the Logic of Paradox and First Degree Entailment, the resulting class of all Strong Kleene generalizations of classical logic also contains a host of unfamiliar (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • A Gentzen Calculus for Nothing but the Truth.Stefan Wintein & Reinhard Muskens - 2016 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 45 (4):451-465.
    In their paper Nothing but the Truth Andreas Pietz and Umberto Rivieccio present Exactly True Logic, an interesting variation upon the four-valued logic for first-degree entailment FDE that was given by Belnap and Dunn in the 1970s. Pietz & Rivieccio provide this logic with a Hilbert-style axiomatisation and write that finding a nice sequent calculus for the logic will presumably not be easy. But a sequent calculus can be given and in this paper we will show that a calculus for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Functional Completeness and Axiomatizability within Belnap's Four-Valued Logic and its Expansions.Alexej P. Pynko - 1999 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 9 (1):61-105.
    In this paper we study 12 four-valued logics arisen from Belnap's truth and/or knowledge four-valued lattices, with or without constants, by adding one or both or none of two new non-regular operations—classical negation and natural implication. We prove that the secondary connectives of the bilattice four-valued logic with bilattice constants are exactly the regular four-valued operations. Moreover, we prove that its expansion by any non-regular connective (such as, e.g., classical negation or natural implication) is strictly functionally complete. Further, finding axiomatizations (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Bilattices and the Semantics of Logic Programming.Melvin Fitting - unknown
    Bilattices, due to M. Ginsberg, are a family of truth value spaces that allow elegantly for missing or conflicting information. The simplest example is Belnap’s four-valued logic, based on classical two-valued logic. Among other examples are those based on finite many-valued logics, and on probabilistic valued logic. A fixed point semantics is developed for logic programming, allowing any bilattice as the space of truth values. The mathematics is little more complex than in the classical two-valued setting, but the result provides (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • (1 other version)Logic of Paradox.Graham Priest - 1979 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 8 (1):219-241.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Introduction to Metamathematics.H. Rasiowa - 1954 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 19 (3):215-216.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   220 citations  
  • On Partial and Paraconsistent Logics.Reinhard Muskens - 1999 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40 (3):352-374.
    In this paper we consider the theory of predicate logics in which the principle of Bivalence or the principle of Non-Contradiction or both fail. Such logics are partial or paraconsistent or both. We consider sequent calculi for these logics and prove Model Existence. For L4, the most general logic under consideration, we also prove a version of the Craig-Lyndon Interpolation Theorem. The paper shows that many techniques used for classical predicate logic generalise to partial and paraconsistent logics once the right (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • How a computer should think.Nuel Belnap - 1977 - In Gilbert Ryle (ed.), Contemporary aspects of philosophy. Boston: Oriel Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   158 citations  
  • Intuitive semantics for first-degree entailments and 'coupled trees'.J. Michael Dunn - 1976 - Philosophical Studies 29 (3):149-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   238 citations  
  • (1 other version)The logic of paradox.Graham Priest - 1979 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 8 (1):219 - 241.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   455 citations  
  • Reasoning with logical bilattices.Ofer Arieli & Arnon Avron - 1996 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 5 (1):25--63.
    The notion of bilattice was introduced by Ginsberg, and further examined by Fitting, as a general framework for many applications. In the present paper we develop proof systems, which correspond to bilattices in an essential way. For this goal we introduce the notion of logical bilattices. We also show how they can be used for efficient inferences from possibly inconsistent data. For this we incorporate certain ideas of Kifer and Lozinskii, which happen to suit well the context of our work. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   111 citations  
  • (2 other versions)First-order Logic.William Craig - 1975 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (2):237-238.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  • Proof Theory.Gaisi Takeuti - 1990 - Studia Logica 49 (1):160-161.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   165 citations  
  • Nothing but the Truth.Andreas Pietz & Umberto Rivieccio - 2013 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 42 (1):125-135.
    A curious feature of Belnap’s “useful four-valued logic”, also known as first-degree entailment (FDE), is that the overdetermined value B (both true and false) is treated as a designated value. Although there are good theoretical reasons for this, it seems prima facie more plausible to have only one of the four values designated, namely T (exactly true). This paper follows this route and investigates the resulting logic, which we call Exactly True Logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • The value of the four values.Ofer Arieli & Arnon Avron - 1998 - Artificial Intelligence 102 (1):97-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Generalizing Functional Completeness in Belnap-Dunn Logic.Hitoshi Omori & Katsuhiko Sano - 2015 - Studia Logica 103 (5):883-917.
    One of the problems we face in many-valued logic is the difficulty of capturing the intuitive meaning of the connectives introduced through truth tables. At the same time, however, some logics have nice ways to capture the intended meaning of connectives easily, such as four-valued logic studied by Belnap and Dunn. Inspired by Dunn’s discovery, we first describe a mechanical procedure, in expansions of Belnap-Dunn logic, to obtain truth conditions in terms of the behavior of the Truth and the False, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Interpolation and three-valued logics.K. Bendova - 2005 - Reports on Mathematical Logic:127-131.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Natural 3-valued logics—characterization and proof theory.Arnon Avron - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (1):276-294.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • A Rich Paraconsistent Extension Of Full Positive Logic.Diderik Batens & Kristof Clercq - 2004 - Logique Et Analyse 47.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations