Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)Minds, Brains, and Programs.John Searle - 2003 - In John Heil (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: A Guide and Anthology. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   666 citations  
  • For Science in the Social Sciences.David Papineau - 1981 - Mind 90 (357):151-153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Cognitive practices: human language and human knowledge.Rita Nolan - 1994 - Cambridge, USA: Blackwell.
    How does human language contribute to the cognitive edge humans have over other species? This question eludes most current theories of language and knowledge. Incorporating research results in psychology and cutting a path through a broad range of philosophical debates, Nolan develops a strikingly original account of language acquisition which holds important implications for standard theories of language and the philosophical foundations of cognitive science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Computers, Minds and Conduct.Graham Button, Jeff Coulter, John Lee & Wes Sharrock - 1995 - Polity.
    This book provides a sustained and penetrating critique of a wide range of views in modern cognitive science and philosophy of the mind, from Turing's famous test for intelligence in machines to recent work in computational linguistic theory. While discussing many of the key arguments and topics, the authors also develop a distinctive analytic approach. Drawing on the methods of conceptual analysis first elaborated by Wittgenstein and Ryle, the authors seek to show that these methods still have a great deal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • (1 other version)Minds, brains, and programs.John Searle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):417-57.
    What psychological and philosophical significance should we attach to recent efforts at computer simulations of human cognitive capacities? In answering this question, I find it useful to distinguish what I will call "strong" AI from "weak" or "cautious" AI. According to weak AI, the principal value of the computer in the study of the mind is that it gives us a very powerful tool. For example, it enables us to formulate and test hypotheses in a more rigorous and precise fashion. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1732 citations  
  • Minds, Brains and Science.John R. Searle - 1984 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    As Louisiana and Cuba emerged from slavery in the late nineteenth century, each faced the question of what rights former slaves could claim. Degrees of Freedom compares and contrasts these two societies in which slavery was destroyed by war, and citizenship was redefined through social and political upheaval. Both Louisiana and Cuba were rich in sugar plantations that depended on an enslaved labor force. After abolition, on both sides of the Gulf of Mexico, ordinary people-cane cutters and cigar workers, laundresses (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   328 citations  
  • The representational theory of mind: an introduction.Kim Sterelny - 1990 - Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell.
    This book is not a conventional introduction to the philosophy of mind, nor is it a contribution to the physicalist/ dualist debate. Instead The Representational Theory of Mind demonstrates that we can construct physicalist theories of important aspects of our mental life. Its aim is to explain and defend a physicalist theory of intelligence in two parts: the first six chapters consist of an exposition, elaboration and defence of human sentience (the functionalist theory of mind), and the second part considers (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   137 citations  
  • The Language of Thought.Jerry A. Fodor - 1975 - Harvard University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1670 citations  
  • The Rediscovery of the Mind.John Searle - 1992 - MIT Press. Edited by Ned Block & Hilary Putnam.
    The title of The Rediscovery of the Mind suggests the question "When was the mind lost?" Since most people may not be aware that it ever was lost, we must also then ask "Who lost it?" It was lost, of course, only by philosophers, by certain philosophers. This passed unnoticed by society at large. The "rediscovery" is also likely to pass unnoticed. But has the mind been rediscovered by the same philosophers who "lost" it? Probably not. John Searle is an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   672 citations  
  • Wittgenstein and Connectionism: a Significant Complementarity?Stephen Mills - 1993 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 34:137-157.
    Between the later views of Wittgenstein and those of connectionism on the subject of the mastery of language there is an impressively large number of similarities. The task of establishing this claim is carried out in the second section of this paper.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Wittgenstein and connectionism: A significant complementarity?Stephen L. Mills - 1993 - Philosophy 34:137-157.
    Between the later views of Wittgenstein and those of connectionism 1 on the subject of the mastery of language there is an impressively large number of similarities. The task of establishing this claim is carried out in the second section of this paper.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Rediscovery of the Mind.John Searle - 1992 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (1):201-207.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   524 citations  
  • Language, sense and nonsense: a critical investigation into modern theories of language.Gordon P. Baker & Peter Michael Stephan Hacker - 1984 - Oxford: Blackwell. Edited by P. M. S. Hacker.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on language and rules.Norman Malcolm - 1989 - Philosophy 64 (January):5-28.
    An attempt is made to answer the question why wittgenstein might have found the analogy between speaking and playing games philosophically exciting. It is argued that on the face of it the two are strikingly disanalogous, But that on reflecting further one can find various features of games (9 are distinguished in all) which are also features of some speech episodes, And the awareness of which could be philosophically significant.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar and Necessity.Gordon P. Baker & P. M. S. Hacker (eds.) - 1980 - New York, NY, USA: Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  • Socrates' Critique of Cognitivism.Wallace I. Matson - 1991 - Philosophy 66 (256):145-167.
    Ethics and lexicography would seem, prima facie, to have little to do with each other. Yet Aristotle testifies that Socrates pursued both:Socrates was busying himself about ethical matters and neglecting the world of nature as a whole but seeking the universal in these ethical matters, and fixed thought for the first time on definitions. Socrates occupied himself with the excellences of character, and in connection with them became the first to raise the problem of universal definitions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Representations don't need rules: Reply to James Garson.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1994 - Mind and Language 9 (1):1-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus.Ludwig Wittgenstein - 1922 - New York, NY: Routledge. Edited by Luciano Bazzocchi & P. M. S. Hacker.
    Bazzocchi disposes the text of the Tractatus in a user-friendly manner, exactly as Wittgenstein's decimals advise. This discloses the logical form of the book by distinct reading units, linked into a fashioned hierarchical tree. The text becomes much clearer and every reader can enjoy, finally, its formal and literary qualities.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   507 citations  
  • No representations without rules: The prospects for a compromise between paradigms in cognitive science.James W. Garson - 1994 - Mind and Language 9 (1):25-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • What makes connectionism different?James H. Fetzer - 1994 - Pragmatics and Cognition 2 (2):327-348.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Language and Problems of Knowledge: The Managua Lectures.Noam Chomsky - 1987 - MIT Press.
    Language and Problems of Knowledge is sixteenth in the series Current Studies in Linguistics, edited by Jay Keyser.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   292 citations  
  • Solitary Rule-Following.T. S. Champlin - 1992 - Philosophy 67 (261):285-306.
    Can a rule be followed by one person who has lived all his life in as complete isolation from other human beings as is consistent with his mere physical survival?This question divides philosophers as sharply today as it did over thirty years ago when, prompted by their reading of Wittgenstein, they first asked it. My aim here is to suggest a way of reconciling the two opposing sides in the current debate. I also hope to explain why it was that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Solitary rule-following.T. Stephen Champlin - 1992 - Philosophy 67 (261):285-306.
    Can a rule be followed by one person who has lived all his life in as complete isolation from other human beings as is consistent with his mere physical survival? This question divides philosophers as sharply today as it did over thirty years ago when, prompted by their reading of Wittgenstein, they first asked it. My aim here is to suggest a way of reconciling the two opposing sides in the current debate. I also hope to explain why it was (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Language, Sense, and Nonsense. [REVIEW]Norbert Hornstein - 1987 - Philosophical Review 96 (3):450-455.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Socrates' Critique of Cognitivism.Wallace I. Matson & Adam Leite - 1991 - Philosophy 66 (256):145 - 167.
    Ethics and lexicography would seem, prima facie, to have little to do with each other. Yet Aristotle testifies that Socrates pursued both:Socrates was busying himself about ethical matters and neglecting the world of nature as a whole but seeking the universal in these ethical matters, and fixed thought for the first time on definitions. Socrates occupied himself with the excellences of character, and in connection with them became the first to raise the problem of universal definitions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Connectionism.Kim Sterelny - 1990 - In The representational theory of mind: an introduction. Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Rediscovery of the Mind, by John Searle. [REVIEW]Mark William Rowe - 1992 - Philosophy 68 (265):415-418.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   649 citations  
  • Chomsky's System of Ideas.G. R. Sampson & Fred D'Agostino - 1987 - Philosophical Quarterly 37 (149):477.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • A Humean canvas of experience can seem to divest all inductions of whatever pre-analytic certainty and rational justification they possess.Solitary Rule-Following & Ts Champlin - 1992 - Philosophy 67 (261).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation