Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Meaning.Herbert Paul Grice - 1957 - Philosophical Review 66 (3):377-388.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   974 citations  
  • Hart's expressivism and his Benthamite project.Kevin Toh - 2005 - Legal Theory 11 (2):75-123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Raz on Detachment, Acceptance and Describability.Kevin Toh - 2007 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 27 (3):403-427.
    According to H.L.A. Hart's analysis, to utter an internal legal statement is partly to express an acceptance of a set of norms. This article attempts to defend Hart's conception of internal legal discourse by responding to the following three lines of criticism that can be found in Joseph Raz's writings: (i) that Hart's analysis fails to account for what Raz calls ‘detached legal statements’; (ii) that Hart's deployment of the notion of acceptance in his analysis vitiates his legal positivist project (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Normativity.J. J. Thomson - 2008 - Analysis 70 (4):713-715.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   179 citations  
  • Modality in Language.Eric Swanson - 2008 - Philosophy Compass 3 (6):1193-1207.
    This article discusses some of the ways in which natural language can express modal information – information which is, to a first approximation, about what could be or must be the case, as opposed to being about what actually is the case. It motivates, explains, and raises problems for Angelika Kratzer's influential theory of modal auxiliaries, and introduces a new approach to one important debate about the relationships between modality, evidentiality, context change, and imperative force.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality.David Lyons & Joseph Raz - 1982 - Philosophical Review 91 (3):461.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • What 'must' and 'can' must and can mean.Angelika Kratzer - 1977 - Linguistics and Philosophy 1 (3):337--355.
    In this paper I offer an account of the meaning of must and can within the framework of possible worlds semantics. The paper consists of two parts: the first argues for a relative concept of modality underlying modal words like must and can in natural language. I give preliminary definitions of the meaning of these words which are formulated in terms of logical consequence and compatibility, respectively. The second part discusses one kind of insufficiency in the meaning definitions given in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   374 citations  
  • Requirements, reasons, and Raz: Legal positivism and legal duties.Matthew H. Kramer - 1999 - Ethics 109 (2):375-407.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Deontic Modals: Why Abandon the Classical Semantics?John Horty - 2014 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 95 (4):424-460.
    I begin by reviewing classical semantics and the problems presented by normative conflicts. After a brief detour through default logic, I establish some connections between the treatment of conflicts in each of these two approaches, classical and default, and then move on to consider some further issues: priorities among norms, or reasons, conditional oughts, and reasons about reasons.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Positivism and the internal point of view.Richard Holton - 1998 - Law and Philosophy 17 (s 5-6):597-625.
    Can one consistently (i) be a positivist, and (ii) think that the internal attitude to the law is a moral attitude? Two objections are raised in the literature. The first is that the combination is straight-out contradictory. The second is that if the internal attitude is a moral attitude, those who take it cannot be positivists. Arguments from Shiner, Goldsworthy and Raz are examined. It is concluded that neither objection works. The arguments are based on scope errors, conflations of what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Essays on Bentham: Jurisprudence and Political Theory. [REVIEW]Gerald J. Postema - 1985 - Philosophical Review 94 (4):571-574.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • Studies in the Way of Words.D. E. Over - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (160):393-395.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   431 citations  
  • Allan Gibbard, Thinking How to Live. [REVIEW]David O. Brink - 2007 - Philosophical Review 116 (2):267-272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   229 citations  
  • Comments on Gibbard’s Thinking How to Live.Allan Gibbard - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (3):699-706.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   298 citations  
  • Vagueness's puzzles, polysemy's vagaries.Dirk Geeraerts - 1993 - Cognitive Linguistics 4 (3):223-272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Beyond the Separability Thesis: Moral Semantics and the Methodology of Jurisprudence.Jules L. Coleman - 2007 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 27 (4):581-608.
    Next SectionIn emphasizing the importance of the separability thesis, legal philosophers have inadequately appreciated other philosophically important ways in which law and morality are or might be connected with one another. In this article, I argue that the separability thesis cannot shoulder the philosophical burdens that it has been asked to bear. I then turn to two issues of greater importance to jurisprudence. These are ‘the moral semantics of law’ and ‘the normativity of theory construction in jurisprudence’. The moral semantics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The Concept of Law.Stuart M. Brown - 1963 - Philosophical Review 72 (2):250.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   366 citations  
  • Expressivism and Varieties of Normativity.Daniel Wodak - 2017 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 12:265-293.
    The expressivist advances a view about how we explain the meaning of a fragment of language, such as claims about what we morally ought to do. Critics evaluate expressivism on those terms. This is a serious mistake. We don’t just use that fragment of language in isolation. We make claims about what we morally, legally, rationally, and prudentially ought to do. To account for this linguistic phenomenon, the expressivist owes us an account not just of each fragment of language, but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Normativity.Judith Jarvis Thomson - 2007 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 2:240-266.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   148 citations  
  • Quasi-Expressivism about Statements of Law: A Hartian Theory.Stephen Finlay & David Plunkett - 2018 - In John Gardner, Leslie Green & Brian Leiter (eds.), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law, vol. 3. Oxford University Press. pp. 49-86.
    Speech and thought about what the law is commonly function in practical ways, to guide or assess behavior. These functions have often been seen as problematic for legal positivism in the tradition of H.L.A. Hart. One recent response is to advance an expressivist analysis of legal statements (Toh), which faces its own, familiar problems. This paper advances a rival, positivist-friendly account of legal statements which we call “quasi-expressivist”, explicitly modeled after Finlay’s metaethical theory of moral statements. This consists in a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Ambiguity.Adam Sennet - 2011 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • How many meanings for ‘may’? The case for modal polysemy.Barbara Vetter & Emanuel Viebahn - 2016 - Philosophers' Imprint 16.
    The standard Kratzerian analysis of modal auxiliaries, such as ‘may’ and ‘can’, takes them to be univocal and context-sensitive. Our first aim is to argue for an alternative view, on which such expressions are polysemous. Our second aim is to thereby shed light on the distinction between semantic context-sensitivity and polysemy. To achieve these aims, we examine the mechanisms of polysemy and context-sensitivity and provide criteria with which they can be held apart. We apply the criteria to modal auxiliaries and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Practical Reason and Norms.Joseph Raz - 1975 - Law and Philosophy 12 (3):329-343.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   332 citations  
  • Logic and Conversation.H. Paul Grice - 1989 - In Studies in the Way of Words. Harvard University Press. pp. 22-40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   337 citations  
  • Polysemy: Current perspectives and approaches.Ingrid Lossius Falkum & Agustin Vicente - 2015 - Lingua:DOI: 10.1016/j.lingua.2015.02.00.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Semantics in context.Jason Stanley - 2005 - In Gerhard Preyer & Georg Peter (eds.), Contextualism in Philosophy: Knowledge, Meaning, and Truth. Oxford University Press. pp. 221--54.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Obligations.Leslie Green - 2002 - In Jules Coleman & Scott J. Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence & Philosophy of Law. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Why 'Ought' Detaches: Or, Why You Ought to Get with My Friends (If You Want to Be My Lover).Alex Silk - 2014 - Philosophers' Imprint 14.
    This paper argues that a standard analysis of modals from formal semantics suggests a solution to the detaching problem — the problem of whether un-embedded 'ought'-claims can "detach" (be derived) from hypothetical imperatives and their antecedent conditions. On a broadly Kratzerian analysis, modals have a skeletal conventional meaning and receive a particular reading (e.g., deontic, epistemic, teleological) only relative to certain forms of contextual supplementation. I argue that 'ought'-claims can detach — subject to an important qualification — but only as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations