Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Comprehension, Demonstration, and Accuracy in Aristotle.Breno Zuppolini - 2020 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 58 (1):29-48.
    according to aristotle's posterior analytics, scientific expertise is composed of two different cognitive dispositions. Some propositions in the domain can be scientifically explained, which means that they are known by "demonstration", a deductive argument in which the premises are explanatory of the conclusion. Thus, the kind of cognition that apprehends those propositions is called "demonstrative knowledge".1 However, not all propositions in a scientific domain are demonstrable. Demonstrations are ultimately based on indemonstrable principles, whose knowledge is called "comprehension".2 If the knowledge (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Aristotle on per se accidents.Breno A. Zuppolini - 2018 - Ancient Philosophy 38 (1):113-135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Ontological Underpinnings of Aristotle's Philosophy of Science.Breno A. Zuppolini - 2017 - Dissertation, University of Campinas, Brazil
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Relationship of aristotle's Two Analytics.Robin Smith - 1982 - Classical Quarterly 32 (2):327-335.
    In 1928, Friedrich Solmsen argued that Aristotle'sPosterior Analyticswas largely composed before thePrior Analytics. Ross rejected Solmsen's position in 1939, and a rather lengthy series of rebuttals and counter-attacks between the two scholars followed. Quite recently, Jonathan Barnes has revived this issue with arguments in favour of something very close to Solmsen's thesis: that Aristotle first developed a theory of demonstration (‘apodeictic’) before he had worked out the syllogistic, and that thePosterior Analyticswas originally conceived against this background. Subsequently, when Aristotle formulated (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Definition of Scientific Knowledge.Lucas Angioni - 2016 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 19 (1):79-104.
    In Posterior Analytics 71b9 12, we find Aristotle’s definition of scientific knowledge. The definiens is taken to have only two informative parts: scientific knowledge must be knowledge of the cause and its object must be necessary. However, there is also a contrast between the definiendum and a sophistic way of knowing, which is marked by the expression “kata sumbebekos”. Not much attention has been paid to this contrast. In this paper, I discuss Aristotle’s definition paying due attention to this contrast (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Aristotle on Necessary Principles and on Explaining X through X’s essence.Lucas Angioni - 2014 - Studia Philosophica Estonica 7 (2):88-112.
    I discuss what Aristotle means when he say that scientific demonstration must proceed from necessary principles. I argue that, for Aristotle, scientific demonstration should not be reduced to sound deduction with necessary premises. Scientific demonstration ultimately depends on the fully appropriate explanatory factor for a given explanandum. This explanatory factor is what makes the explanandum what it is. Consequently, this factor is also unique. When Aristotle says that demonstration must proceed from necessary principles, he means that each demonstration requires the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Forma lógica Das proposições científicas E ontologia da predicação: Um falso dilema nos segundos analíticos de aristóteles.Breno Andrade Zuppolini - 2014 - Philósophos - Revista de Filosofia 19 (2):11-45.
    In the Posterior Analytics, Aristotle imposes some requirements on the formulation of scientific propositions: their terms must be able to perform the role of subject as well as of predicate; their terms should be universal; every demonstration must involve “primary” subjects denoted by terms that “cannot be said of another underlying subject”. Several interpreters, inspired by theses from the Categories, believed that this third requirement refers to names and descriptions of particular substances as basic subjects of predicative statements, since they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Essence and per se predication in Aristotle's metaphysics Z 4.Michail M. Peramatzis - 2010 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Introdução à teoria da predicação em Aristóteles.Lucas Angioni - 2006 - Editora da Unicamp.
    This is an introductory handbook for some of the main themes around the notion of predication in Aristotle. It does not aim at being exhaustive, but only sketches some important lines about the subject; it contains an introductory essay, besides the translation (into Portuguese) and commentary of basic texts (such as Posterior Analytics I-22, Categories 1-5, Interpretation 1-6 etc.).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   159 citations  
  • Aristóteles e a noção de sujeito de predicação (Segundos analíticos I 22, 83a 1-14).Lucas Angioni - 2007 - Philósophos - Revista de Filosofia 12 (2):107-129.
    This paper explores some aspects of Aristotle’s notion of subject for predications. I examine the argument Aristotle develops in Posterior Analytics I.22, 83a1-14. I argue that the notion advanced by Aristotle in that argument is different from the one found in his Categories, although they are far from being incompatible with each other. I also add some philological considerations to justify the Portuguese translation of “hypokeimenon” as “algo subjacente” (“underlying thing”) instead of “sujeito” (“subject”).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • (1 other version)Understanding, Explanation and Insight in the "Posterior Analytics".L. A. Kosman - 1973 - Phronesis 18:374.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Aristotle's Prior Analytics Book I: Translated with an Introduction and Commentary.Gisela Striker - 2009 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    The Prior Analytics marks the beginning of formal logic, and is one of the most influential works in the history of thought. It is here that Aristotle sets out his system of syllogistic reasoning. The first book, to which this volume is devoted, offers a coherent presentation of Aristotle's logic as a general theory of deductive argument.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Immediate Propositions and Aristotle’s Proof Theory.Robin Smith - 1986 - Ancient Philosophy 6:47-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Termos singulares, transcategoriais e Summa Genera na lógica de Aristóteles.Wellington Damasceno de Almeida - 2013 - Manuscrito 36 (1):5-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Immediate Propositions and Aristotle’s Proof Theory.Robin Smith - 1986 - Ancient Philosophy 6:47-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On Finding Compactness in Aristotle.Michael Scanlan - 1983 - History and Philosophy of Logic 4 (1&2):1-8.
    Jonathan Lear has suggested that Aristotle attempts to demonstrate a proof-theoretic analogue of a compactness theorem in Posterior analyticsI, chs. 19?22. Aristotle argues in these chapters that there cannot be in finite series of predications of terms. Lear's analysis of Aristotle's arguments are shown to be based on confusions about the nature of infinite orderings. Three distinct confusions are identified. In final remarks, it is suggested that a compactness claim is irrelevant to the issues which motivate Aristotle's arguments.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Aristotle on Predication.D. W. Hamlyn - 1961 - Phronesis 6 (1):110-126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The structure of substance according to Aristotle.Raphael Demos - 1944 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 5 (2):255-268.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • How Things Are: Studies in Predication and the History of Philosophy and Science.James Bogen & J. E. Mcguire - 1984 - Springer.
    One of the earliest and most influential treatises on the subject of this volume is Aristotle's Categories. Aristotle's title is a form of the Greek verb for speaking against or submitting an accusation in a legal proceeding. By the time of Aristotle, it also meant: to signify or to predicate. Surprisingly, the "predicates" Aristotle talks about include not only bits of language, but also such nonlinguistic items as the color white in a body and the knowledge of grammar in a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations