Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A general method for proving decidability of intuitionistic modal logics.Natasha Alechina & Dmitry Shkatov - 2006 - Journal of Applied Logic 4 (3):219-230.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The two‐variable fragment with counting and equivalence.Ian Pratt-Hartmann - 2015 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 61 (6):474-515.
    We consider the two‐variable fragment of first‐order logic with counting, subject to the stipulation that a single distinguished binary predicate be interpreted as an equivalence. We show that the satisfiability and finite satisfiability problems for this logic are both NExpTime‐complete. We further show that the corresponding problems for two‐variable first‐order logic with counting and two equivalences are both undecidable.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • 2004 Summer Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic.Wolfram Pohlers - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (2):249-312.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Modal and guarded characterisation theorems over finite transition systems.Martin Otto - 2004 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 130 (1-3):173-205.
    We explore the finite model theory of the characterisation theorems for modal and guarded fragments of first-order logic over transition systems and relational structures of width two. A new construction of locally acyclic bisimilar covers provides a useful analogue of the well known tree-like unravellings that can be used for the purposes of finite model theory. Together with various other finitary bisimulation respecting model transformations, and Ehrenfeucht–Fraïssé game arguments, these covers allow us to upgrade finite approximations for full bisimulation equivalence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Modal logic and invariance.Johan Van Benthem & Denis Bonnay - 2008 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 18 (2-3):153-173.
    Consider any logical system, what is its natural repertoire of logical operations? This question has been raised in particular for first-order logic and its extensions with generalized quantifiers, and various characterizations in terms of semantic invariance have been proposed. In this paper, our main concern is with modal and dynamic logics. Drawing on previous work on invariance for first-order operations, we find an abstract connection between the kind of logical operations a system uses and the kind of invariance conditions the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Dynamic Consequence and Public Announcement.Andrés Cordón Franco, Hans van Ditmarsch & Angel Nepomuceno - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (4):659-679.
    In van Benthem (2008), van Benthem proposes a dynamic consequence relation defined as${\psi _1}, \ldots,{\psi _n}{ \models ^d}\phi \,{\rm{iff}}{ \models ^{pa}}[{\psi _1}] \ldots [{\psi _n}]\phi,$where the latter denotes consequence in public announcement logic, a dynamic epistemic logic. In this paper we investigate the structural properties of a conditional dynamic consequence relation$\models _{\rm{\Gamma }}^d$extending van Benthem’s proposal. It takes into account a set of background conditions Γ, inspired by Makinson (2003) wherein Makinson calls this reasoning ‘modulo’ a set Γ. In the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Moorean Phenomena in Epistemic Logic.Wesley H. Holliday & Thomas F. Icard - 2010 - In Lev Dmitrievich Beklemishev, Valentin Goranko & Valentin Shehtman (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic 8. London, England: College Publications. pp. 178-199.
    A well-known open problem in epistemic logic is to give a syntactic characterization of the successful formulas. Semantically, a formula is successful if and only if for any pointed model where it is true, it remains true after deleting all points where the formula was false. The classic example of a formula that is not successful in this sense is the “Moore sentence” p ∧ ¬BOXp, read as “p is true but you do not know p.” Not only is the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • A General Lindström Theorem for Some Normal Modal Logics.Sebastian Enqvist - 2013 - Logica Universalis 7 (2):233-264.
    There are several known Lindström-style characterization results for basic modal logic. This paper proves a generic Lindström theorem that covers any normal modal logic corresponding to a class of Kripke frames definable by a set of formulas called strict universal Horn formulas. The result is a generalization of a recent characterization of modal logic with the global modality. A negative result is also proved in an appendix showing that the result cannot be strengthened to cover every first-order elementary class of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Small substructures and decidability issues for first-order logic with two variables.Emanuel Kieroński & Martin Otto - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (3):729-765.
    We study first-order logic with two variables FO² and establish a small substructure property. Similar to the small model property for FO² we obtain an exponential size bound on embedded substructures, relative to a fixed surrounding structure that may be infinite. We apply this technique to analyse the satisfiability problem for FO² under constraints that require several binary relations to be interpreted as equivalence relations. With a single equivalence relation, FO² has the finite model property and is complete for non-deterministic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Probabilistic Logics and Probabilistic Networks.Rolf Haenni, Jan-Willem Romeijn, Gregory Wheeler & Jon Williamson - 2010 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Synthese Library. Edited by Gregory Wheeler, Rolf Haenni, Jan-Willem Romeijn & and Jon Williamson.
    Additionally, the text shows how to develop computationally feasible methods to mesh with this framework.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • 'One is a Lonely Number': on the logic of communication.Johan van Benthem - unknown
    Logic is not just about single-agent notions like reasoning, or zero-agent notions like truth, but also about communication between two or more people. What we tell and ask each other can be just as 'logical' as what we infer in Olympic solitude. We show how such interactive phenomena can be studied systematically by merging epistemic and dynamic logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Algebraic Logic, Where Does It Stand Today?Tarek Sayed Ahmed - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (3):465-516.
    This is a survey article on algebraic logic. It gives a historical background leading up to a modern perspective. Central problems in algebraic logic (like the representation problem) are discussed in connection to other branches of logic, like modal logic, proof theory, model-theoretic forcing, finite combinatorics, and Gödel’s incompleteness results. We focus on cylindric algebras. Relation algebras and polyadic algebras are mostly covered only insofar as they relate to cylindric algebras, and even there we have not told the whole story. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Decidable fragments of first-order modal logics.Frank Wolter & Michael Zakharyaschev - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (3):1415-1438.
    The paper considers the set ML 1 of first-order polymodal formulas the modal operators in which can be applied to subformulas of at most one free variable. Using a mosaic technique, we prove a general satisfiability criterion for formulas in ML 1 , which reduces the modal satisfiability to the classical one. The criterion is then used to single out a number of new, in a sense optimal, decidable fragments of various modal predicate logics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • A two-variable fragment of English.Ian Pratt-Hartmann - 2003 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 12 (1):13-45.
    Controlled languages are regimented fragments of natural languagedesigned to make the processing of natural language more efficient andreliable. This paper defines a controlled language, E2V, whose principalgrammatical resources include determiners, relative clauses, reflexivesand pronouns. We provide a formal syntax and semantics for E2V, in whichanaphoric ambiguities are resolved in a linguistically natural way. Weshow that the expressive power of E2V is equal to that of thetwo-variable fragment of first-order logic. It follows that the problemof determining the satisfiability of a set (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Fragments of language.Ian Pratt-Hartmann - 2004 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 13 (2):207-223.
    By a fragment of a natural language we mean a subset of thatlanguage equipped with semantics which translate its sentences intosome formal system such as first-order logic. The familiar conceptsof satisfiability and entailment can be defined for anysuch fragment in a natural way. The question therefore arises, for anygiven fragment of a natural language, as to the computational complexityof determining satisfiability and entailment within that fragment. Wepresent a series of fragments of English for which the satisfiabilityproblem is polynomial, NP-complete, EXPTIME-complete,NEXPTIME-complete (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • A guarded fragment for abstract state machines.Antje Nowack - 2005 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 14 (3):345-368.
    Abstract State Machines (ASMs) provide a formal method for transparent design and specification of complex dynamic systems. They combine advantages of informal and formal methods. Applications of this method motivate a number of computability and decidability problems connected to ASMs. Such problems result for example from the area of verifying properties of ASMs. Their high expressive power leads rather directly to undecidability respectively uncomputability results for most interesting problems in the case of unrestricted ASMs. Consequently, it is rather natural to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tolerance logic.Maarten Marx - 2001 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 10 (3):353-374.
    We expand first order models with a tolerance relation on thedomain. Intuitively, two elements stand in this relation if they arecognitively close for the agent who holds the model. This simplenotion turns out to be very powerful. It leads to a semanticcharacterization of the guarded fragment of Andréka, van Benthemand Németi, and highlights the strong analogies between modallogic and this fragment. Viewing the resulting logic – tolerance logic– dynamically it is a resource-conscious information processingalternative to classical first order logic. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Finite conformal hypergraph covers and Gaifman cliques in finite structures.Ian Hodkinson & Martin Otto - 2003 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 9 (3):387-405.
    We provide a canonical construction of conformal covers for finite hypergraphs and present two immediate applications to the finite model theory of relational structures. In the setting of relational structures, conformal covers serve to construct guarded bisimilar companion structures that avoid all incidental Gaifman cliques-thus serving as a partial analogue in finite model theory for the usually infinite guarded unravellings. In hypergraph theoretic terms, we show that every finite hypergraph admits a bisimilar cover by a finite conformal hypergraph. In terms (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Deciding regular grammar logics with converse through first-order logic.Stéphane Demri & Hans De Nivelle - 2005 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 14 (3):289-329.
    We provide a simple translation of the satisfiability problem for regular grammar logics with converse into GF2, which is the intersection of the guarded fragment and the 2-variable fragment of first-order logic. The translation is theoretically interesting because it translates modal logics with certain frame conditions into first-order logic, without explicitly expressing the frame conditions. It is practically relevant because it makes it possible to use a decision procedure for the guarded fragment in order to decide regular grammar logics with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Interpolation, preservation, and pebble games.Jon Barwise & Johan van Benthem - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (2):881-903.
    Preservation and interpolation results are obtained for L ∞ω and sublogics $\mathscr{L} \subseteq L_{\infty\omega}$ such that equivalence in L can be characterized by suitable back-and-forth conditions on sets of partial isomorphisms.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Finite algebras of relations are representable on finite sets.H. Andréka, I. Hodkinson & I. Németi - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (1):243-267.
    Using a combinatorial theorem of Herwig on extending partial isomorphisms of relational structures, we give a simple proof that certain classes of algebras, including Crs, polyadic Crs, and WA, have the `finite base property' and have decidable universal theories, and that any finite algebra in each class is representable on a finite set.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Cognitive synonymy: a dead parrot?Francesco Berto & Levin Hornischer - 2023 - Philosophical Studies 180 (9):2727-2752.
    Sentences \(\varphi\) and \(\psi\) are _cognitive synonyms_ for one when they play the same role in one’s cognitive life. The notion is pervasive (Sect. 1 ), but elusive: it is bound to be hyperintensional (Sect. 2 ), but excessive fine-graining would trivialize it and there are reasons for some coarse-graining (Sect. 2.1 ). Conceptual limitations stand in the way of a natural algebra (Sect. 2.2 ), and it should be sensitive to subject matters (Sect. 2.3 ). A cognitively adequate individuation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Modelwise Interpolation Property of Semantic Logics.Zalán Gyenis, Zalán Molnár & Övge Öztürk - 2023 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 52 (1):59-83.
    In this paper we introduce the modelwise interpolation property of a logic that states that whenever \(\models\phi\to\psi\) holds for two formulas \(\phi\) and \(\psi\), then for every model \(\mathfrak{M}\) there is an interpolant formula \(\chi\) formulated in the intersection of the vocabularies of \(\phi\) and \(\psi\), such that \(\mathfrak{M}\models\phi\to\chi\) and \(\mathfrak{M}\models\chi\to\psi\), that is, the interpolant formula in Craig interpolation may vary from model to model. We compare the modelwise interpolation property with the standard Craig interpolation and with the local interpolation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Modal Loosely Guarded Fragment of Second-Order Propositional Modal Logic.Gennady Shtakser - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (3):511-538.
    In this paper, we introduce a variant of second-order propositional modal logic interpreted on general (or Henkin) frames, \(SOPML^{\mathcal {H}}\), and present a decidable fragment of this logic, \(SOPML^{\mathcal {H}}_{dec}\), that preserves important expressive capabilities of \(SOPML^{\mathcal {H}}\). \(SOPML^{\mathcal {H}}_{dec}\) is defined as a _modal loosely guarded fragment_ of \(SOPML^{\mathcal {H}}\). We demonstrate the expressive power of \(SOPML^{\mathcal {H}}_{dec}\) using examples in which modal operators obtain (a) the epistemic interpretation, (b) the dynamic interpretation. \(SOPML^{\mathcal {H}}_{dec}\) partially satisfies the principle of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On Equivalence Relations Between Interpreted Languages, with an Application to Modal and First-Order Language.Kai F. Wehmeier - 2021 - Erkenntnis 88 (1):193-213.
    I examine notions of equivalence between logics (understood as languages interpreted model-theoretically) and develop two new ones that invoke not only the algebraic but also the string-theoretic structure of the underlying language. As an application, I show how to construe modal operator languages as what might be called typographical notational variants of _bona fide_ first-order languages.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • -Connections of abstract description systems.Oliver Kutz, Carsten Lutz, Frank Wolter & Michael Zakharyaschev - 2004 - Artificial Intelligence 156 (1):1-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Atom-canonicity in varieties of cylindric algebras with applications to omitting types in multi-modal logic.Tarek Sayed Ahmed - 2020 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 30 (3):223-271.
    Fix 2 < n < ω and let C A n denote the class of cylindric algebras of dimension n. Roughly, C A n is the algebraic counterpart of the proof theory of first-order logic restricted to the first n var...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the Concept of a Notational Variant.Alexander W. Kocurek - 2017 - In Alexandru Baltag, Jeremy Seligman & Tomoyuki Yamada (eds.), Logic, Rationality, and Interaction (LORI 2017, Sapporo, Japan). Springer. pp. 284-298.
    In the study of modal and nonclassical logics, translations have frequently been employed as a way of measuring the inferential capabilities of a logic. It is sometimes claimed that two logics are “notational variants” if they are translationally equivalent. However, we will show that this cannot be quite right, since first-order logic and propositional logic are translationally equivalent. Others have claimed that for two logics to be notational variants, they must at least be compositionally intertranslatable. The definition of compositionality these (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Axiomatic and Tableau-Based Reasoning for Kt.Renate A. Schmidt, John G. Stell & David Rydeheard - 2014 - In Rajeev Goré, Barteld Kooi & Agi Kurucz (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic, Volume 10: Papers From the Tenth Aiml Conference, Held in Groningen, the Netherlands, August 2014. London, England: CSLI Publications. pp. 478-497.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Constructionist Philosophy of Logic.Patrick Allo - 2017 - Minds and Machines 27 (3):545-564.
    This paper develops and refines the suggestion that logical systems are conceptual artefacts that are the outcome of a design-process by exploring how a constructionist epistemology and meta-philosophy can be integrated within the philosophy of logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Weakly representable atom structures that are not strongly representable, with an application to first order logic.Tarek Sayed Ahmed - 2008 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 54 (3):294-306.
    Letn > 2. A weakly representable relation algebra that is not strongly representable is constructed. It is proved that the set of all n by n basic matrices forms a cylindric basis that is also a weakly but not a strongly representable atom structure. This gives an example of a binary generated atomic representable cylindric algebra with no complete representation. An application to first order logic is given.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Johan van Benthem on Logic and Information Dynamics.Alexandru Baltag & Sonja Smets (eds.) - 2014 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer International Publishing.
    This book illustrates the program of Logical-Informational Dynamics. Rational agents exploit the information available in the world in delicate ways, adopt a wide range of epistemic attitudes, and in that process, constantly change the world itself. Logical-Informational Dynamics is about logical systems putting such activities at center stage, focusing on the events by which we acquire information and change attitudes. Its contributions show many current logics of information and change at work, often in multi-agent settings where social behavior is essential, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Computational Learning Semantics for Inductive Empirical Knowledge.Kevin T. Kelly - 2014 - In Alexandru Baltag & Sonja Smets (eds.), Johan van Benthem on Logic and Information Dynamics. Cham, Switzerland: Springer International Publishing. pp. 289-337.
    This chapter presents a new semantics for inductive empirical knowledge. The epistemic agent is represented concretely as a learner who processes new inputs through time and who forms new beliefs from those inputs by means of a concrete, computable learning program. The agent’s belief state is represented hyper-intensionally as a set of time-indexed sentences. Knowledge is interpreted as avoidance of error in the limit and as having converged to true belief from the present time onward. Familiar topics are re-examined within (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The guarded fragment with transitive guards.Wiesław Szwast & Lidia Tendera - 2004 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 128 (1-3):227-276.
    The guarded fragment with transitive guards, [GF+TG], is an extension of the guarded fragment of first-order logic, GF, in which certain predicates are required to be transitive, transitive predicate letters appear only in guards of the quantifiers and the equality symbol may appear everywhere. We prove that the decision problem for [GF+TG] is decidable. Moreover, we show that the problem is in 2E. This result is optimal since the satisfiability problem for GF is 2E-complete 1719–1742). We also show that the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Decidable fragments of first-order temporal logics.Ian Hodkinson, Frank Wolter & Michael Zakharyaschev - 2000 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 106 (1-3):85-134.
    In this paper, we introduce a new fragment of the first-order temporal language, called the monodic fragment, in which all formulas beginning with a temporal operator have at most one free variable. We show that the satisfiability problem for monodic formulas in various linear time structures can be reduced to the satisfiability problem for a certain fragment of classical first-order logic. This reduction is then used to single out a number of decidable fragments of first-order temporal logics and of two-sorted (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Complexity of monodic guarded fragments over linear and real time.Ian Hodkinson - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 138 (1):94-125.
    We show that the satisfiability problem for the monodic guarded, loosely guarded, and packed fragments of first-order temporal logic with equality is 2Exptime-complete for structures with arbitrary first-order domains, over linear time, dense linear time, rational number time, and some other classes of linear flows of time. We then show that for structures with finite first-order domains, these fragments are also 2Exptime-complete over real number time and hence over most of the commonly used linear flows of time, including the natural (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On a theorem of Vaught for first order logic with finitely many variables.Tarek Sayed Ahmed - 2009 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 19 (1):97-112.
    We prove that the existence of atomic models for countable atomic theories does not hold for Ln the first order logic restricted to n variables for finite n > 2. Our proof is algebraic, via polyadic algebras. We note that Lnhas been studied in recent times as a multi-modal logic with applications in computer science. 2000 MATHEMATICS SUBJECT CLASSIFICATION. 03C07, 03G15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the general interpretation of first-order quantifiers.G. Aldo Antonelli - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (4):637-658.
    While second-order quantifiers have long been known to admit nonstandard, or interpretations, first-order quantifiers (when properly viewed as predicates of predicates) also allow a kind of interpretation that does not presuppose the full power-set of that interpretationgeneral” interpretations for (unary) first-order quantifiers in a general setting, emphasizing the effects of imposing various further constraints that the interpretation is to satisfy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Atom structures of cylindric algebras and relation algebras.Ian Hodkinson - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 89 (2):117-148.
    For any finite n 3 there are two atomic n-dimensional cylindric algebras with the same atom structure, with one representable, the other, not.Hence, the complex algebra of the atom structure of a representable atomic cylindric algebra is not always representable, so that the class RCAn of representable n-dimensional cylindric algebras is not closed under completions. Further, it follows by an argument of Venema that RCAn is not axiomatisable by Sahlqvist equations, and hence nor by equations where negation can only occur (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Omitting types for finite variable fragments and complete representations of algebras.Hajnal Andréka, István Németi & Tarek Sayed Ahmed - 2008 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 73 (1):65-89.
    We give a novel application of algebraic logic to first order logic. A new, flexible construction is presented for representable but not completely representable atomic relation and cylindric algebras of dimension n (for finite n > 2) with the additional property that they are one-generated and the set of all n by n atomic matrices forms a cylindric basis. We use this construction to show that the classical Henkin-Orey omitting types theorem fails for the finite variable fragments of first order (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Uniform Short Proofs for Classical Theorems.Kees Doets - 2001 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 42 (2):121-127.
    This note exploits back-and-forth characteristics to construct, using a single method, short proofs for ten classics of first-order and modal logic: interpolation theorems, preservation theorems, and Lindström's theorem.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On definability in multimodal logic.Joseph Y. Halpern, Dov Samet & Ella Segev - 2009 - Review of Symbolic Logic 2 (3):451-468.
    Three notions of definability in multimodal logic are considered. Two are analogous to the notions of explicit definability and implicit definability introduced by Beth in the context of first-order logic. However, while by Beth’s theorem the two types of definability are equivalent for first-order logic, such an equivalence does not hold for multimodal logics. A third notion of definability, reducibility, is introduced; it is shown that in multimodal logics, explicit definability is equivalent to the combination of implicit definability and reducibility. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The semijoin algebra and the guarded fragment.Dirk Leinders, Maarten Marx, Jerzy Tyszkiewicz & Jan Van den Bussche - 2005 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 14 (3):331-343.
    In the 1970s Codd introduced the relational algebra, with operators selection, projection, union, difference and product, and showed that it is equivalent to first-order logic. In this paper, we show that if we replace in Codd’s relational algebra the product operator by the “semijoin” operator, then the resulting “semijoin algebra” is equivalent to the guarded fragment of first-order logic. We also define a fixed point extension of the semijoin algebra that corresponds to μGF.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On axiomatising products of Kripke frames.Ágnes Kurucz - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (2):923-945.
    It is shown that the many-dimensional modal logic K n , determined by products of n-many Kripke frames, is not finitely axiomatisable in the n-modal language, for any $n > 2$ . On the other hand, K n is determined by a class of frames satisfying a single first-order sentence.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Guarded fragments with constants.Balder ten Cate & Massimo Franceschet - 2005 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 14 (3):281-288.
    We prove ExpTime-membership of the satisfiability problem for loosely ∀-guarded first-order formulas with a bounded number of variables and an unbounded number of constants. Guarded fragments with constants are interesting by themselves and because of their connection to hybrid logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Modal Logic.Johan van Benthem - 2002 - In Dale Jacquette (ed.), A Companion to Philosophical Logic. Malden, MA, USA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 389–409.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Enriching Extensional Logic with Intensional Notions Changing Views of Modal Logic A Précis of Basic Modal Logic The Major Applications Fine‐Structure of Expressive Power System Combination: Action and Information Back to the Heartland Conclusion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A Simple Logic of Functional Dependence.Alexandru Baltag & Johan van Benthem - 2021 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 50 (5):939-1005.
    This paper presents a simple decidable logic of functional dependence LFD, based on an extension of classical propositional logic with dependence atoms plus dependence quantifiers treated as modalities, within the setting of generalized assignment semantics for first order logic. The expressive strength, complete proof calculus and meta-properties of LFD are explored. Various language extensions are presented as well, up to undecidable modal-style logics for independence and dynamic logics of changing dependence models. Finally, more concrete settings for dependence are discussed: continuous (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Distances between formal theories.Michele Friend, Mohamed Khaled, Koen Lefever & Gergely Székely - unknown - Review of Symbolic Logic 13 (3):633-654.
    In the literature, there have been several methods and definitions for working out whether two theories are “equivalent” or not. In this article, we do something subtler. We provide a means to measure distances between formal theories. We introduce two natural notions for such distances. The first one is that of axiomatic distance, but we argue that it might be of limited interest. The more interesting and widely applicable notion is that of conceptual distance which measures the minimum number of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Propositional Epistemic Logics with Quantification Over Agents of Knowledge.Gennady Shtakser - 2018 - Studia Logica 106 (2):311-344.
    The paper presents a family of propositional epistemic logics such that languages of these logics are extended by quantification over modal operators or over agents of knowledge and extended by predicate symbols that take modal operators as arguments. Denote this family by \}\). There exist epistemic logics whose languages have the above mentioned properties :311–350, 1995; Lomuscio and Colombetti in Proceedings of ATAL 1996. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol 1193, pp 71–85, 1996). But these logics are obtained from first-order (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Completeness and Decidability of General First-Order Logic.Aldo Antonelli - 2017 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 46 (3):233-257.
    This paper investigates the “general” semantics for first-order logic introduced to Antonelli, 637–58, 2013): a sound and complete axiom system is given, and the satisfiability problem for the general semantics is reduced to the satisfiability of formulas in the Guarded Fragment of Andréka et al. :217–274, 1998), thereby showing the former decidable. A truth-tree method is presented in the Appendix.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations