Switch to: References

Citations of:

The works of Aristotle

Franklin Center, Pa.: Franklin Library. Edited by W. D. Ross (1908)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The alchemical sources of Robert Boyle's corpuscular philosophy.William R. Newman - 1996 - Annals of Science 53 (6):567-585.
    Summary Robert Boyle is remembered largely for his integration of experiment and the ?mechanical philosophy?. Although Boyle is occasionally elusive as to what he means precisely by the ?mechanical philosophy?, it is clear that a major portion of it concerned his corpuscular theory of matter. Historians of science have traditionally viewed Boyle's corpuscular philosophy as the grafting of a physical theory onto a previously incoherent body of alchemy and iatrochemistry. As this essay shows, however, Boyle owed a heavy debt to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The Promise That Love Will Last.Camilla Kronqvist - 2011 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 54 (6):650 - 668.
    Abstract What sense are we to make of the promise of love against the contingency of human life? I discuss two replies to this question: (1) the suggestion that marriage, based on the probable success of this kind of relationship, is a more or less worthwhile endeavour (cf. Moller and Landau), and (2) Martha Nussbaum's Aristotelian proposal that we only live life fully if we embrace aspects of life, such as loving relationships, that are vulnerable to fortune. I show that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Locke on Real Essence and Water as a Natural Kind: A Qualified Defence.E. J. Lowe - 2011 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 85 (1):1-19.
    ‘Water is H2O’ is one of the most frequently cited sentences in analytic philosophy, thanks to the seminal work of Saul Kripke and Hilary Putnam in the 1970s on the semantics of natural kind terms. Both of these philosophers owe an intellectual debt to the empiricist metaphysics of John Locke's Essay Concerning Human Understanding, while disagreeing profoundly with Locke about the reality of natural kinds. Locke employs an intriguing example involving water to support his view that kinds (or ‘species’), such (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • From substance language to vocabularies of process and change: Translations of key philosophical terms in the Zhongyong.Haiming Wen - 2004 - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 3 (2):217-233.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Anthropology as ritual: Wittgenstein's reading of Frazer's the golden bough.Paul Redding - 1987 - Metaphilosophy 18 (3-4):253-269.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Aquinas' transcendences to Aristotle in the doctrine of essence.Dezhi Duan - 2007 - Frontiers of Philosophy in China 2 (4):572-582.
    Aquinas’ philosophy is revolutionary, especially his doctrine of essence within the context of natural philosophy has transcended that of Aristotle. The principal distinctions between the doctrines of Aquinas and Aristotle are demonstrated in four layers which are entity-nature, compositeness, particularity and potentiality of essence. Aquinas not only overturns and reforms the Western traditional view of essence, but also constructs a prominent “joint” connecting essentialism to existentialism in Western philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Negation as cancellation, and connexive logic.Graham Priest - 1999 - Topoi 18 (2):141-148.
    Of the various accounts of negation that have been offered by logicians in the history of Western logic, that of negation as cancellation is a very distinctive one, quite different from the explosive accounts of modern "classical" and intuitionist logics, and from the accounts offered in standard relevant and paraconsistent logics. Despite its ancient origin, however, a precise understanding of the notion is still wanting. The first half of this paper offers one. Both conceptually and historically, the account of negation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Toward a Practical Theory of Timing: Upbeat and E-Series Time for Organisms.Naoki Nomura, Koichiro Matsuno, Tomoaki Muranaka & Jun Tomita - 2020 - Biosemiotics 13 (3):347-367.
    Timing adjustment is an important ability for living organisms. Wild animals need to act at the right moment to catch prey or escape a predator. Land plants, although limited in their movement, need to decide the right time to grow and bloom. Humans also need to decide the right moment for social actions. Although scientists can pinpoint the timing of such behaviors by observation, we know extremely little about how living organisms as actors or players decide when to act – (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Many-valued modal logics: A simple approach: Many-valued modal logics: A simple approach.Graham Priest - 2008 - Review of Symbolic Logic 1 (2):190-203.
    1.1 In standard modal logics, the worlds are 2-valued in the following sense: there are 2 values that a sentence may take at a world. Technically, however, there is no reason why this has to be the case. The worlds could be many-valued. This paper presents one simple approach to a major family of many-valued modal logics, together with an illustration of why this family is philosophically interesting.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • A systems model of spirituality.David Rousseau - 2014 - Zygon 49 (2):476-508.
    Within the scientific study of spirituality there are substantial ambiguities and uncertainties about relevant concepts, terms, evidences, methods, and relationships. Different disciplinary approaches reveal or emphasize different aspects of spirituality, such as outcomes, behaviors, skills, ambitions, and beliefs. I argue that these aspects interdepend in a way that constitutes a “systems model of spirituality.” This model enables a more holistic understanding of the nature of spirituality, and suggests a new definition that disambiguates spirituality from related concepts such as religion, cultural (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Does the history of psychology have a subject?Roger Smith - 1988 - History of the Human Sciences 1 (2):147-177.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Topoi from the Greater, the Lesser and the Same Degree: An Essay on the σύγκρισις in Aristotle’s Topics. [REVIEW]José Miguel Gambra Gutiérrez - 2012 - Argumentation 26 (4):413-437.
    The presence of premises expressing comparison is a problem for the Aristotelian theory of the dialectical method, first because there is no general theory of comparison in the Organon and secondly because along with propositions on the opposition and inflexion of the terms, comparative statements seem to fall outside the explicit description which Aristotle gives of possible premises. The purpose of this paper is to offer a synthetic theory of comparisons according to Aristotle’s Topics , in an attempt both to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Logic Without Truth.Carlos E. Alchourron & Antonio A. Martino - 1990 - Ratio Juris 3 (1):46-67.
    Between the two horns of Jørgensen's dilemma, the authors opt for that according to which logic deals not only with truth and falsity but also with those concepts not possessing this semantic reference. Notwithstanding the “descriptive” prejudice, deontic logic has gained validity among modal logics. The technical foundation proposed consists in an abstract characterization of logical consequence. By identifying in the abstract notion of consequence the primitive from which to begin, it is possible to define the connectives - even those (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Arabico-Islamic background of Al-Fārābī's logic.Sadik Türker - 2007 - History and Philosophy of Logic 28 (3):183-255.
    This paper examines al-Fārābī's logical thought within its Arabico-Islamic historical background and attempts to conceptualize what this background contributes to his logic. After a brief exposition of al-Fārābī's main problems and goals, I shall attempt to reformulate the formal structure of Arabic linguistics (AL) in terms of the ontological and formal characteristics that Arabic logic is built upon. Having discussed the competence of al-Fārābī in the history of AL, I will further propose three interrelated theses about al-Fārābī's logic, in terms (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Why ethical codes constitute an unconscionable regression.Michael Schwartz - 2000 - Journal of Business Ethics 23 (2):173 - 184.
    The article protests against the usage of ethical codes by business organisations. It asserts that professionals are in a different situation to that of employees; and that with the latter ethical codes are used by management to ensure compliance and are devoid of ethical content. Ethical codes it is argued are part of management's control system in a time of flatter organisational structures with a far wider span of control. It is also asserted that the ambitions of some to utilise (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Evers & Walker and forms of knowledge.Jim Mackenzie - 1985 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 19 (2):199–209.
    Jim Mackenzie; Evers & Walker and Forms of Knowledge, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 19, Issue 2, 30 May 2006, Pages 199–209, https://doi.org/10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Notion of ‘Place’ in the Context of Present-day Physics.Elena Mamchur - 2016 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 30 (4):319-326.
    The article deals with Aristotle’s conception of ‘place’, which is of cruсial importance for his theory of motion. It is shown that in the physics of Aristotle there is no concept of spасe; instead, there is the notion of ‘place’ of a body. Aristotle considered ‘place’ as the first boundary of a body embracing the body in question. The author shows the incommensurability between the spatial ideas of the Stagirite and the similar ideas of Newtonian physics. The article states that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle’s Theory of Deduction and Paraconsistency.Evandro Luís Gomes & Itala M. Loffredo D'Ottaviano - 2010 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 14 (1):71–97.
    In the Organon Aristotle describes some deductive schemata in which inconsistencies do not entail the trivialization of the logical theory involved. This thesis is corroborated by three different theoretical topics by him discussed, which are presented in this paper. We analyse inference schema used by Aristotle in the Protrepticus and the method of indirect demonstration for categorical syllogisms. Both methods exemplify as Aristotle employs classical reductio ad absurdum strategies. Following, we discuss valid syllogisms from opposite premises (contrary and contradictory) studied (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Virgin and the Telescope: The Moons of Cigoli and Galileo.Sara Elizabeth Booth & Albert van Helden - 2000 - Science in Context 13 (3-4):463-486.
    The ArgumentIn 1612, Lodovico Cigoli completed a fresco in the Pauline chapel of the Basilica of Santa Maria Maggiore in Rome depicting Apocalypse 12: “A woman clothed with the sun, and the moon under her feet.” He showed the crescent Moon with spots, as his friend Galileo had observed with the newly invented telescope. Considerations of the orthodox view of the perfect Moon as held by philosophers have led historians to ask why this clearly imperfect Moon in a religious painting (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Virgin and the Telescope: The Moons of Cigoli and Galileo.Sara Elizabeth Booth & Albert van Helden - 2001 - Science in Context 14 (s1):193-216.
    in 1612, lodovico cigoli completed a fresco in the pauline chapel of the basilica of santa maria maggiore in rome depicting apocalypse 12: “a woman clothed with the sun, and the moon under her feet.” he showed the crescent moon with spots, as his friend galileo had observed with the newly invented telescope. considerations of the orthodox view of the perfect moon as held by philosophers have led historians to ask why this clearly imperfect moon in a religious painting raised (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Begging the question, circularity and epistemic propriety.Dilip K. Basu - 1994 - Argumentation 8 (3):217-226.
    In this paper we shall try to understand what it is to beg the question, and since begging the question is generally believed to be linked with circularity, we shall also explore this relationship. Finally, we shall consider whether certain forms of valid argument can go through smoothly in anepistemio context without begging the question. We shall consider, especially, the claims of the disjunctive syllogism in this regard.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle on Necessary Verticality, Body Heat, and Gendered Proper Places in the Polis: A Feminist Critique.Judith M. Green - 1992 - Hypatia 7 (1):70 - 96.
    Feminist critics have charged that Aristotle's mistaken and harmful remarks about women and slaves show inconsistency or bias-driven arbitrariness. However, this analysis shows that these remarks function within a consistent and coherent theoretical corpus. Thus, both Aristotle's hierarchical and dualistic first principles and the methodology on which his entire corpus is based must be unreliable. Moreover, consistency and coherence must be insufficient warrants of theoretical insightfulness. Aristotle's mistakes suggest caveats for feminist philosophical reconstruction.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Responses to 'pathologies of science'.Sven Andersson, Elazar Barkan, Kenneth Caneva, Randall Collins, Stephen Downes, Henry Etzkowitz, Steve Fuller, David Gorman, Frederick Grinnell, David Hollinger, Anne Holmquest & Charles Willard - 1987 - Social Epistemology 1 (3):249-281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Defeating the Inference from General to Particular Norms.Mikael M. Karlsson - 1995 - Ratio Juris 8 (3):271-286.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Biological matter and perceptual powers in Aristotle's de Anima.Theodore Scaltsas - 1996 - Topoi 15 (1):25-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Some fundamental issues in confucian ethics: A selective review of encyclopedia of chinese philosophy.Yong Huang - 2005 - Journal of Chinese Philosophy 32 (3):509–528.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Light of Reason, Light of Nature. Catholic and Protestant Metaphors of Scientific Knowledge.William B. Ashworth - 1989 - Science in Context 3 (1):89-107.
    The ArgumentMany of the epistemological issues that occupied natural philosophers of the seventeenth century were expressed visually in title-page engravings. One of those issues concerned the relative status to be accorded to evidence of the senses, as compared to knowledge gained by faith or reason. In title-page illustrations, the various arguments were often waged by a series of light metaphors: the Light of Reason, the Light of Nature, and the Lights of Sense, Scripture, and Grace. When such illustrations are examined (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Honoré Fabri and the Trojan Horse of Inertia.Michael Elazar - 2008 - Science in Context 21 (1):1-38.
    ArgumentThis paper discusses the theory of motion of the philosopher Honoré Fabri (1608–1688), a senior representative of early modern Jesuit scientists. It argues that the consensus prevailing among historians – according to which Fabri's theory of impetus is diametrically opposed to Galileo's or Descartes' concept of inertia – is false. It shows: that Fabri carefully constructed his concept of impetus in order to easily incorporate the principle of linear conservation of motion (designated here as “limited inertia”), by adopting formal (rather (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Doctors that “doctor” sickness certificates: cunning intelligence as an ability and possibly a virtue among Swedish GPs.Mani Shutzberg - 2020 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 23 (3):445-456.
    The relations of power between healthcare-related institutions and the professionals that interact with them are changing. Generally, the institutions are gaining the upper hand. Consequently, the intellectual abilities necessary for professionals to pursue the internal goods of healthcare are changing as well. A concrete case is the struggle over sickness benefits in Sweden, in which theSwedish Social Insurance Agency(SSIA) and physicians are important stakeholders. The SSIA has recently consolidated its power over the sickness certificates that doctors issue for their patients. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Ernst Mach, George Sarton and the Empiry of Teaching Science Part I.Hayo Siemsen - 2012 - Science & Education 21 (4):447-484.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Learning from Greek Philosophers: The Foundations and Structural Conditions of Ethical Training in Business Schools.Sandrine Frémeaux, Grant Michelson & Christine Noël-Lemaitre - 2018 - Journal of Business Ethics 153 (1):231-243.
    There is an extensive body of work that has previously examined the teaching of ethics in business schools whereby it is hoped that the values and behaviours of students might be provoked to show positive and enduring change. Rather than dealing with the content issues of particular business ethics courses per se, this article explores the philosophical foundations and the structural conditions for developing ethical training programs in business schools. It is informed by historical analysis, specifically, an examination of Platonic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Tropes and Topics in Scientific Discourse: Galileo's De Motu.Ofer Gal - 1994 - Science in Context 7 (1):25-52.
    The ArgumentThis paper contains two main sections. In the first I suggest a mechanism of interpretation, based on a distinction between two aspects of meaning, analyzed using two kinds of rhetorical-poetical constructions:tropesto explore the linguistic relations—metaphors, metonyms, synecdoches, etc.—that endow terms with content, andtopicsto account for the structuring function of key expressions, which enables the recognition and adjudication of phrases, arguments, texts, genres, etc. In the second section I substantiate my claims by demonstrating how new light is shed on Galileo (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Kants Organismusbegriff und seine Transformation in der Naturphilosophie F. W. J. Schellings.Aaron Fellbaum - 2005 - Archiv für Begriffsgeschichte 47:217-223.
    After the exposition of I. Kant's theory of nature as a mechanism, we turn to Kant's idea that organisms are an exception and cannot be explained through the mechanism of nature. Organisms are characterized through a circular causality. The idea of the whole, an idea of the thinking subject, causes the functioning of organisms. F.W.J.Schelling takes up Kant's conception that the organism is characterized through the interaction of the parts, but he dispenses with the idea of the whole as a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Emotions, Ethics, and the "Internal Ought".Robert C. Solomon - 1996 - Cognition and Emotion 10 (5):529-550.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Composition and division.John Woods & Douglas Walton - 1977 - Studia Logica 36 (4):381 - 406.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On the interaction of opposites in psychological processes.Ivana Marková - 1987 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 17 (3):279–299.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Cognitive psychology and the rejection of Brentano.John Macnamara - 1993 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 23 (2):117–137.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation