Switch to: References

Citations of:

Ad hoc categories

Memory and Cognition 11:211-277 (1983)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The role of similarity in categorization: providing a groundwork.Robert L. Goldstone - 1994 - Cognition 52 (2):125-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • Perceptual symbol systems.Lawrence W. Barsalou - 1999 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (4):577-660.
    Prior to the twentieth century, theories of knowledge were inherently perceptual. Since then, developments in logic, statis- tics, and programming languages have inspired amodal theories that rest on principles fundamentally different from those underlying perception. In addition, perceptual approaches have become widely viewed as untenable because they are assumed to implement record- ing systems, not conceptual systems. A perceptual theory of knowledge is developed here in the context of current cognitive science and neuroscience. During perceptual experience, association areas in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   734 citations  
  • Are there really two types of learning?Yorick Wilks - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):671-671.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How to regulate a practice: The case of cosmetic surgery. [REVIEW]Henri Wijsbek - 2001 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 4 (1):59-74.
    How should a practice, subservient to a public good, be regulated in order to guarantee fair access without encouraging improper claims? In the first place, a clear understanding of the goal of the practice is indispensable for knowing what criteria the regulation must contain. As to the purely formal aspect, the regulation of any practice must include both general rules and particular instances. Finally, to resolve conflicts, committees in which different kinds of expertise are represented should be installed. These three (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The plurality of concepts.Daniel Aaron Weiskopf - 2009 - Synthese 169 (1):145-173.
    Traditionally, theories of concepts in psychology assume that concepts are a single, uniform kind of mental representation. But no single kind of representation can explain all of the empirical data for which concepts are responsible. I argue that the assumption that concepts are uniformly the same kind of mental structure is responsible for these theories’ shortcomings, and outline a pluralist theory of concepts that rejects this assumption. On pluralism, concepts should be thought of as being constituted by multiple representational kinds, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   99 citations  
  • Atomism, pluralism, and conceptual content.Daniel A. Weiskopf - 2009 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79 (1):131-163.
    Conceptual atomists argue that most of our concepts are primitive. I take up three arguments that have been thought to support atomism and show that they are inconclusive. The evidence that allegedly backs atomism is equally compatible with a localist position on which concepts are structured representations with complex semantic content. I lay out such a localist position and argue that the appropriate position for a non-atomist to adopt is a pluralist view of conceptual structure. I show several ways in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Specifying the scope of 13-month-olds' expectations for novel words.Sandra R. Waxman - 1999 - Cognition 70 (3):35-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The hard questions about noninductive learning remain unanswered.Eric Wanner - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):670-670.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pathological prediction: a top-down cause of organic disease.Elena Walsh - 2021 - Synthese 199 (1-2):4127-4150.
    Though predictive processing approaches to the mind were originally applied to exteroceptive perception, i.e., vision and action, recent work has started to explore the role of interoceptive perception, i.e., emotion and affect. This article builds on this work by extending PP beyond emotion to the construction of emotional dispositions. I employ principles from dynamical systems theory and PP to provide a model of how dispositional anger can develop in response to early experiences of psychosocial stress. The model is then deployed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A perceptual account of definitions.Humphrey van Polanen Petel - 2007 - Global Philosophy 17 (1):53-73.
    The traditional definition per genus et differentiam is argued to be cognitively grounded in perception and in order to avoid needless argument, definitions are stipulated to assert boundaries. An analysis of the notion of perspective shows that a boundary is a composite of two distinctions: similarity that includes and difference that excludes. The concept is applied to the type-token distinction and percepts are shown to be the result of a comparison between a token as representing some phenomenon and a type (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Rejecting induction: Using occam's razor too soon.J. T. Tolliver - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):669-670.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • ‘Something that’s very American’: The interactional role of Light-Head Relative Clauses.Sandra A. Thompson & Barend Beekhuizen - 2022 - Discourse Studies 24 (2):149-167.
    In this paper, we examine a specific type of Relative Clause. We look at the construction consisting of a ‘light noun’, that is, a noun with highly non-specific lexical content which does not do referential work, plus a relative clause. It has generally been assumed that the functional contribution of RCs is to narrow the set of referents of the head noun to only those for which the predicate of the RC holds true. However, the ‘Light Head RC construction’ has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is the Mystery of Thought Demystified by Context‐Dependent Categorisation? Towards a New Relation Between Language and Thought.Michael S. C. Thomas, Harry R. M. Purser & Denis Mareschal - 2012 - Mind and Language 27 (5):595-618.
    We argue that are no such things as literal categories in human cognition. Instead, we argue that there are merely temporary coalescences of dimensions of similarity, which are brought together by context in order to create the similarity structure in mental representations appropriate for the task at hand. Fodor contends that context‐sensitive cognition cannot be realised by current computational theories of mind. We address this challenge by describing a simple computational implementation that exhibits internal knowledge representations whose similarity structure alters (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Categorical Structure among Shared Features in Networks of Early-learned Nouns.Linda Smith Thomas T. Hills, Mounir Maouene, Josita Maouene, Adam Sheya - 2009 - Cognition 112 (3):381.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The pragmatics of induction.Paul Thagard - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):668-669.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Authors' Reply: Why a Connectionist Perspective on Emotion is Helpful.Gaurav Suri & James J. Gross - 2022 - Emotion Review 14 (2):116-120.
    Emotion Review, Volume 14, Issue 2, Page 116-120, April 2022. To make progress related to long-standing questions related to the nature of emotion, we offer the Interactive Activation and Competition framework for Emotion. The IAC-E is not another conventional theory of emotion. Rather, it offers a neural-network-based, algorithmic account of how emotion instances and categories arise. Our approach suggests that there need not be a contradiction between instances of the same emotion being sometimes consistent and sometimes variable. Similarly, there need (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Desiderata for cognitive architectures.Ron Sun - 2004 - Philosophical Psychology 17 (3):341-373.
    This article addresses issues in developing cognitive architectures--generic computational models of cognition. Cognitive architectures are believed to be essential in advancing understanding of the mind, and therefore, developing cognitive architectures is an extremely important enterprise in cognitive science. The article proposes a set of essential desiderata for developing cognitive architectures. It then moves on to discuss in detail some of these desiderata and their associated concepts and ideas relevant to developing better cognitive architectures. It argues for the importance of taking (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Criteria for naturalness in conceptual spaces.Corina Strößner - 2022 - Synthese 200 (2):1-36.
    Conceptual spaces are a frequently applied framework for representing concepts. One of its central aims is to find criteria for what makes a concept natural. A prominent demand is that natural concepts cover convex regions in conceptual spaces. The first aim of this paper is to analyse the convexity thesis and the arguments that have been advanced in its favour or against it. Based on this, I argue that most supporting arguments focus on single-domain concepts (e.g., colours, smells, shapes). Unfortunately, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Life and Death of a Metaphor, or the Metaphysics of Metaphor.Josef Stern - 2007 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 3.
    This paper addresses two issues: what it is for a metaphor to be either alive or dead and what a metaphor must be in order to be either alive or dead. Both issues, in turn, bear on the contemporary debate whether metaphor is a pragmatic or semantic phenomenon and on the dispute between Contextualists and Literalists. In the first part of the paper, I survey examples of what I take to be live metaphors and dead metaphors in order to establish (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Salvaging parts of the “classical theory” of categorization.Dan Sperber - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):668-668.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Category differences/automaticity.Edward E. Smith - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):667-667.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theory-laden concepts: Great, but what is the next step?Charles P. Shimp - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):666-667.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A probabilistic model of cross-categorization.Patrick Shafto, Charles Kemp, Vikash Mansinghka & Joshua B. Tenenbaum - 2011 - Cognition 120 (1):1-25.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • When Do Misunderstandings Matter? Evidence From Survey Interviews About Smoking.Michael F. Schober, Anna L. Suessbrick & Frederick G. Conrad - 2018 - Topics in Cognitive Science 10 (2):452-484.
    Schober et al. describe two studies on how survey interview respondents misunderstand interview questions. After answering a survey, participants are given standardized definitions of the questions they have just answered. Even apparently simple questions such as “Have you smoked more than 100 cigarettes?” are interpreted very differently by participants. Moreover, clarifying the meaning of the definitions with the interviewer does not always help resolve the miscommunication.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The learning of function and the function of learning.Roger C. Schank, Gregg C. Collins & Lawrence E. Hunter - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):672-686.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Transcending inductive category formation in learning.Roger C. Schank, Gregg C. Collins & Lawrence E. Hunter - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):639-651.
    The inductive category formation framework, an influential set of theories of learning in psychology and artificial intelligence, is deeply flawed. In this framework a set of necessary and sufficient features is taken to define a category. Such definitions are not functionally justified, are not used by people, and are not inducible by a learning system. Inductive theories depend on having access to all and only relevant features, which is not only impossible but begs a key question in learning. The crucial (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Diagnostic recognition: task constraints, object information, and their interactions.Philippe G. Schyns - 1998 - Cognition 67 (1-2):147-179.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • A Modular Neural Network Model of Concept Acquisition.Philippe G. Schyns - 1991 - Cognitive Science 15 (4):461-508.
    Previous neural network models of concept learning were mainly implemented with supervised learning schemes. However, studies of human conceptual memory have shown that concepts may be learned without a teacher who provides the category name to associate with exemplars. A modular neural network architecture that realizes concept acquisition through two functionally distinct operations, categorizing and naming, is proposed as an alternative. An unsupervised algorithm realizes the categorizing module by constructing representations of categories compatible with prototype theory. The naming module associates (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Knowledge Organization, Categories, and Ad Hoc Groups: Folk Medical Models among Mexican Migrants in Nashville.Norbert Ross, Jonathan Maupin & Catherine A. Timura - 2011 - Ethos: Journal of the Society for Psychological Anthropology 39 (2):165-188.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Cumulative semantic interference for associative relations in language production.Sebastian Benjamin Rose & Rasha Abdel Rahman - 2016 - Cognition 152 (C):20-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Analogical reminding and the storage of experience: the paradox of Hofstadter-Sander.Stephen E. Robbins - 2017 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 16 (3):355-385.
    In their exhaustive study of the cognitive operation of analogy, Hofstadter and Sander arrive at a paradox: the creative and inexhaustible production of analogies in our thought must derive from a “reminding” operation based upon the availability of the detailed totality of our experience. Yet the authors see no way that our experience can be stored in the brain in such detail nor do they see how such detail could be accessed or retrieved such that the innumerable analogical remindings we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A Goal-Directed Bayesian Framework for Categorization.Francesco Rigoli, Giovanni Pezzulo, Raymond Dolan & Karl Friston - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Splitting concepts.Gualtiero Piccinini & Sam Scott - 2006 - Philosophy of Science 73 (4):390-409.
    A common presupposition in the concepts literature is that concepts constitute a sin- gular natural kind. If, on the contrary, concepts split into more than one kind, this literature needs to be recast in terms of other kinds of mental representation. We offer two new arguments that concepts, in fact, divide into different kinds: (a) concepts split because different kinds of mental representation, processed independently, must be posited to explain different sets of relevant phenomena; (b) concepts split because different kinds (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Approaches, assumptions, and goals in modeling cognitive behavior.Richard E. Pastore & David G. Payne - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):665-666.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The psychology of category learning: Current status and future prospect.Gregory L. Murphy - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):664-665.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are Sensory-Motor Relationships Encoded ad hoc or by Default?: An ERP Study.Yurena Morera, Maartje van der Meij, Manuel de Vega & Horacio A. Barber - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Of what use categories?Ruth Garrett Millikan - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):663-664.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Looking for Arguments.Hugo Mercier - 2012 - Argumentation 26 (3):305-324.
    Abstract How do people find arguments while engaged in a discussion? Following an analogy with visual search, a mechanism that performs this task is described. It is a metarepresentational device that examines representations in a mostly serial manner until it finds a good enough argument supporting one’s position. It is argued that the mechanism described in dual process theories as ‘system 2’, or analytic reasoning fulfills these requirements. This provides support for the hypothesis that reasoning serves an argumentative function. Content (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Prediction‐Based Learning and Processing of Event Knowledge.Ken McRae, Kevin S. Brown & Jeffrey L. Elman - 2021 - Topics in Cognitive Science 13 (1):206-223.
    McRae, Brown and Elman argue against the view that events are structured as frequently‐occurring sequences of world stimuli. They underline the importance of temporal structure defining event types and advance a more complex temporal structure, which allows for some variance in the component elements.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Crossing the Associative/Inferential Divide: Ad hoc Concepts and the Inferential Power of Schemata.Marco Mazzone - 2014 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 5 (4):583-599.
    How do we construct ad hoc concepts, especially those characterised by emergent properties? A reasonable hypothesis, suggested both in psychology and in pragmatics , is that some sort of inferential processing must be involved. I argue that this inferential processing can be accounted for in associative terms. My argument is based on the notion of inference as associative pattern completion based on schemata, with schemata being conceived in turn as patterns of concepts and their relationships. The possible role of conscious (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Superordinate principles in reasoning with causal and deontic conditionals.K. I. Manktelow & N. Fairley - 2000 - Thinking and Reasoning 6 (1):41 – 65.
    We propose that the pragmatic factors that mediate everyday deduction, such as alternative and disabling conditions (e.g. Cummins et al., 1991) and additional requirements (Byrne, 1989) exert their effects on specific inferences because of their perceived relevance to more general principles, which we term SuperPs. Support for this proposal was found first in two causal inference experiments, in which it was shown that specific inferences were mediated by factors that are relevant to a more general principle, while the same inferences (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Judgment dissociation theory: An analysis of differences in causal, counterfactual and covariational reasoning.David R. Mandel - 2003 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 132 (3):419.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Categorization is modulated by transcranial direct current stimulation over left prefrontal cortex.Gary Lupyan, Daniel Mirman, Roy Hamilton & Sharon L. Thompson-Schill - 2012 - Cognition 124 (1):36-49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Measure of Perceived Similarity Between Faces: Old Issues for a New Method.Ludovica Lorusso, Luca Pulina & Enrico Grosso - 2015 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 6 (2):317-339.
    Measuring perceived similarity is an important issue in visual perception of faces, since a measure of the perceived similarity between faces may be used to investigate fundamental tasks like face categorization and recognition. Despite its fundamental role, measuring perceived similarity between faces is not trivial from both a theoretical and methodological point of view. In this paper we present theoretical arguments that undermine the method currently most used to measure perceived similarity between faces in visual perception, and we propose an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Examples as persuasive argument in popular management literature.Alon Lischinsky - 2008 - Discourse and Communication 2 (3):243-269.
    In this article we take the use of examples as a means to explore the processes of persuasion and consensus-construction involved in the legitimation of popular management knowledge. Examples, as concrete instances or events used to substantiate a wider argument, have been variedly regarded in different research traditions. Classical logic and rhetoric have considered them an inferior form of argument, useful for pedagogic or public debate but inadequate for higher forms of thought. This spirit still permeates much psychological research on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • About as boring as flossing sharks: Cognitive accounts of irony and the family of approximate comparison constructions in American English.Claudia Lehmann - 2021 - Cognitive Linguistics 32 (1):133-158.
    This paper reports a case study on a family of American English constructions that will be called the family of approximate comparison constructions. This family has three members, all of which follow the syntactic pattern about as X as Y with X being an adjective, but which allow three related functions: literal comparison, simile and irony. Two cognitive frameworks concern themselves with irony, the cognitive modelling approach and viewpoint approach, and the paper will show that, while the ironic approximate comparison (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • When explanation is too hard (or understanding hijacking for novices).Michael Lebowitz - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):662-663.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • New failures to learn.Barbara Landau - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):660-661.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Induction and explanation: Complementary models of learning.Pat Langley - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):661-662.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Building machines that learn and think like people.Brenden M. Lake, Tomer D. Ullman, Joshua B. Tenenbaum & Samuel J. Gershman - 2017 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 40.
    Recent progress in artificial intelligence has renewed interest in building systems that learn and think like people. Many advances have come from using deep neural networks trained end-to-end in tasks such as object recognition, video games, and board games, achieving performance that equals or even beats that of humans in some respects. Despite their biological inspiration and performance achievements, these systems differ from human intelligence in crucial ways. We review progress in cognitive science suggesting that truly human-like learning and thinking (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations