Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A long time ago in a computing lab far, far away….Jeffery L. Johnson, R. H. Ettinger & Timothy L. Hubbard - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):670-670.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The evolved mind.Harry J. Jerison - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):763-764.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evolution of the flowchart.Harry J. Jerison - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):451-452.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Epistemic Role of Core Cognition.Zoe Jenkin - 2020 - Philosophical Review 129 (2):251-298.
    According to a traditional picture, perception and belief have starkly different epistemic roles. Beliefs have epistemic statuses as justified or unjustified, depending on how they are formed and maintained. In contrast, perceptions are “unjustified justifiers.” Core cognition is a set of mental systems that stand at the border of perception and belief, and has been extensively studied in developmental psychology. Core cognition's borderline states do not fit neatly into the traditional epistemic picture. What is the epistemic role of these states? (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Cognitive Penetrability: Modularity, Epistemology, and Ethics.Zoe Jenkin & Susanna Siegel - 2015 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 6 (4):531-545.
    Introduction to Special Issue of Review of Philosophy and Psychology. Overview of the central issues in cognitive architecture, epistemology, and ethics surrounding cognitive penetrability. Special issue includes papers by philosophers and psychologists: Gary Lupyan, Fiona Macpherson, Reginald Adams, Anya Farennikova, Jona Vance, Francisco Marchi, Robert Cowan.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Linguistic Intuitions.Steven Gross Jeffrey Maynes - 2013 - Philosophy Compass 8 (8):714-730.
    Linguists often advert to what are sometimes called linguistic intuitions. These intuitions and the uses to which they are put give rise to a variety of philosophically interesting questions: What are linguistic intuitions – for example, what kind of attitude or mental state is involved? Why do they have evidential force and how might this force be underwritten by their causal etiology? What light might their causal etiology shed on questions of cognitive architecture – for example, as a case study (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Brain mechanisms of conscious experience and voluntary action.Herbert H. Jasper - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):543-543.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Nonlinear trends in the evolution of the complexity of nervous systems, group size, and communication systems: A general feature in biology.Klaus Jaffe & Grace Chacon - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):386-386.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What is a concept, that a person may grasp it?Ray Jackendoff - 1989 - Mind and Language 4 (1-2):68-102.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Qualia for propositional attitudes?Frank Jackson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):52-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Pluripotentiality, epigenesis, and language acquisition.Bob Jacobs & Lori Larsen - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):639-639.
    Müller provides a valuable synthesis of neurobiological evidence on the epigenetic development of neural structures involved in language acquisition. The pluripotentiality of developing neural tissue crucially constrains linguistic/cognitive theorizing about supposedly innate neural mechanisms and contributes significantly to our understanding of experience–dependent processes involved in language acquisition. Without this understanding, any proposed explanation of language acquisition is suspect.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is self-knowledge compatible with externalism?Pierre Jacob - 2001 - Mind and Society 2 (1):59-75.
    Externalism is the view that the contents of many of a person’s propositional attitudes and perhaps sensory experiences are extrinsic properties of the person’s brain: they involve relations between the person’s brain and properties instantiated in his or her present or past environment. Privileged self-knowledge is the view that every human being is able to know directly or non-inferentially, in a way unavailable to anybody else, what he or she thinks or experiences. Now, if what I think is not in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Introspective physicalism as an approach to the science of consciousness.Anthony I. Jack & T. Shallice - 2001 - Cognition 79 (1):161-196.
    Most ?theories of consciousness? are based on vague speculations about the properties of conscious experience. We aim to provide a more solid basis for a science of consciousness. We argue that a theory of consciousness should provide an account of the very processes that allow us to acquire and use information about our own mental states ? the processes underlying introspection. This can be achieved through the construction of information processing models that can account for ?Type-C? processes. Type-C processes can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • In Defense of Theory.Ray Jackendoff - 2017 - Cognitive Science 41 (S2):185-212.
    Formal theories of mental representation have receded from the importance they had in the early days of cognitive science. I argue that such theories are crucial in any mental domain, not just for their own sake, but to guide experimental inquiry, as well as to integrate the domain into the mind as a whole. To illustrate the criteria of adequacy for theories of mental representation, I compare two theoretical approaches to language: classical generative grammar (Chomsky, 1965, 1981, 1995) and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Empathy, Primitive Reactions and the Modularity of Emotion.Anne J. Jacobson - 2006 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36 (sup1):95-113.
    Are emotion-producing processes modular? Jerry Fodor, in his classic introduction of the notion of modularity, holds that its most important feature is cognitive impenetrability or information encapsulation. If a process possesses this feature, then, as standardly understood, “what we want or believe makes no difference to how [it] works”.In this paper, we will start with the issue of the cognitive impenetrability of emotion-producing processes. It turns out that, while there is abundant evidence of emotion-producing processes that are not cognitively impenetrable, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Embodying the Mind by Extending It.Pierre Jacob - 2012 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 3 (1):33-51.
    To subscribe to the embodied mind (or embodiment) framework is to reject the view that an individual’s mind is realized by her brain alone. As Clark ( 2008a ) has argued, there are two ways to subscribe to embodiment: bodycentrism (BC) and the extended mind (EM) thesis. According to BC, an embodied mind is a two-place relation between an individual’s brain and her non-neural bodily anatomy. According to EM, an embodied mind is a threeplace relation between an individual’s brain, her (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Eliminativism, meaning, and qualitative states.Henry Jacoby - 1985 - Philosophical Studies 47 (March):257-70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Data and interpretation in comparative color vision.Gerald H. Jacobs - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):40-41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Coping with informational atomism - one of Jerry Fodor’s legacies.Pierre Jacob - 2020 - Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia 11 (1):19-41.
    : Fodor was passionately unwilling to compromise. Of his several commitments, I focus here on informational atomism. Fodor staunchly rejected semantic holism for two conspiring reasons. He took it to threaten his commitment to the nomic character of psychological explanation. He also took it to pave the way towards relativism, which he found deeply offensive. In this paper, I reconstruct the strands of Fodor’s commitment to the computational version of the representational theory of mind that led him to informational atomism. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Monogamy, contraception and the cultural and reproductive success hypothesis.William Irons - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):295-296.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Attentional orienting precedes conscious identification.Albrecht Werner Inhoff - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):35-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Limits of preconscious processing.Albrecht Werner Inhoff - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):680-681.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Architecture and algorithms: Power sharing for mental models.Robert Inder - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):354-354.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The narrative practice hypothesis: Clarifications and implications.Daniel D. Hutto - 2008 - Philosophical Explorations 11 (3):175 – 192.
    The Narrative Practice Hypothesis (NPH) is a recently conceived, late entrant into the contest of trying to understand the basis of our mature folk psychological abilities, those involving our capacity to explain ourselves and comprehend others in terms of reasons. This paper aims to clarify its content, importance and scientific plausibility by: distinguishing its conceptual features from those of its rivals, articulating its philosophical significance, and commenting on its empirical prospects. I begin by clarifying the NPH's target explanandum and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • The cultural ecosystem of human cognition.Edwin Hutchins - 2014 - Philosophical Psychology 27 (1):1-16.
    Everybody knows that humans are cultural animals. Although this fact is universally acknowledged, many opportunities to exploit it are overlooked. In this article, I propose shifting our attention from local examples of extended mind to the cultural-cognitive ecosystems within which human cognition is embedded. I conclude by offering a set of conjectures about the features of cultural-cognitive ecosystems.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • Knowing what? Radical versus conservative enactivism.Daniel D. Hutto - 2005 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 4 (4):389-405.
    The binary divide between traditional cognitivist and enactivist paradigms is tied to their respective commitments to understanding cognition as based on knowing that as opposed to knowing how. Using O’Regan’s and No¨e’s landmark sensorimotor contingency theory of perceptual experience as a foil, I demonstrate how easy it is to fall into conservative thinking. Although their account is advertised as decidedly ‘skill-based’, on close inspection it shows itself to be riddled with suppositions threatening to reduce it to a rules-and-representations approach. To (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • If she is conscious, what is she?Trevor Hussey - 2020 - Nursing Philosophy 21 (2):e12248.
    What is consciousness? What is its importance and how is it to be described? The paper looks at some of the principal theories and their attempts to solve the “hard problem” of how consciousness is produced by nervous tissue, and attempts to close the “explanatory gap” between such (apparently) profoundly different things as subjective awareness and a physical brain. It ends with a tentative suggestion that, despite centuries of philosophical frustration, recent appeals to quantum physics may offer a glimmer of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Evolution and nursing.Trevor Hussey - 2002 - Nursing Philosophy 3 (3):240-251.
    Evolutionary theory has been a very popular topic in recent years and it has been claimed that it can make a major contribution to the advance of several sciences such as medicine, psychology, psychopathology and sociology: even providing them with new paradigms. This paper explores the possibility that nursing could benefit similarly by adopting an evolutionary perspective. After sketching the scientific and philosophical background to the recent developments concerning evolution, and briefly mentioning the chief features of evolutionary theory, the paper (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The view of a computational animal.Anya Hurlbert - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):39-40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Perception and action: Alternative views.Susan Hurley - 2001 - Synthese 129 (1):3-40.
    A traditional view of perception and action makestwo assumptions: that the causal flow betweenperception and action is primarily linear or one-way,and that they are merely instrumentally related toeach other, so that each is a means to the other.Either or both of these assumptions can be rejected. Behaviorism rejects the instrumental but not theone-way aspect of the traditional view, thus leavingitself open to charges of verificationism. Ecologicalviews reject the one-way aspect but not theinstrumental aspect of the traditional view, so thatperception and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • Some memory, but no mind.Lawrence E. Hunter - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):37-38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • SOAR as a world view, not a theory.Earl Hunt & R. Duncan Luce - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):447-448.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On the relationship between neuropsychology and cognitive psychology.Earl Hunt - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):450-451.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evidence for and against modularity.Earl Hunt - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):19-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychometric considerations in the evaluation of intraspecies differences in intelligence.Lloyd G. Humphreys - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):668.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • 2. Information Processing Systems Which Embody Computational Rules: The Connectionist Approach.Glyn W. Humphreys - 1986 - Mind and Language 1 (3):201-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Go with the flow but mind the details.Glyn W. Humphreys & M. Jane Riddoch - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):71-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reliability, pragmatic and epistemic.Robert G. Hudson - 1994 - Erkenntnis 40 (1):71 - 86.
    Experimental data are often acclaimed on the grounds that they can be consistently generated. They are, it is said, reproducible. In this paper I describe how this feature of experimental-data (their pragmatic reliability) leads to their epistemic worth (their epistemic reliability). An important part of my description is the supposition that experimental procedures are to certain extent fixed and stable. Various illustrations from the actual practice of science are introduced, the most important coming at the end of the paper with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Phenomenal Causality II: Integration and Implication. [REVIEW]Timothy L. Hubbard - 2013 - Axiomathes 23 (3):485-524.
    The empirical literature on phenomenal causality (the notion that causality can be perceived) is reviewed. Different potential types of phenomenal causality and variables that influence phenomenal causality were considered in Part I (Hubbard 2012b) of this two-part series. In Part II, broader questions regarding properties of phenomenal causality and connections of phenomenal causality to other perceptual or cognitive phenomena (different types of phenomenal causality, effects of spatial and temporal variance, phenomenal causality in infancy, effects of object properties, naïve physics, spatial (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Further Correspondences and Similarities of Shamanism and Cognitive Science: Mental Representation, Implicit Processing, and Cognitive Structures.Timothy L. Hubbard - 2003 - Anthropology of Consciousness 14 (1):40-74.
    Properties of mental representation are related to findings in cognitive science and ideas in shamanism. A selective review of research in cognitive science suggests visual images and spatial memory preserve important functional information regarding physical principles and the behavior of objects in the natural world, and notions of second‐order isomorphism and the perceptual cycle developed to account for such findings are related to shamanic experience. Possible roles of implicit processes in shamanic cognition, and the idea that shamanic experience may involve (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Auditory representational momentum: Musical schemata and modularity.Timothy L. Hubbard - 1993 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 31 (3):201-204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can massive modularity explain human intelligence? Information control problem and implications for cognitive architecture.Linus Ta-Lun Huang - 2021 - Synthese 198 (9):8043-8072.
    A fundamental task for any prospective cognitive architecture is information control: routing information to the relevant mechanisms to support a variety of tasks. Jerry Fodor has argued that the Massive Modularity Hypothesis cannot account for flexible information control due to its architectural commitments and its reliance on heuristic information processing. I argue instead that the real trouble lies in its commitment to nativism—recent massive modularity models, despite incorporating mechanisms for learning and self-organization, still cannot learn to control information flexibly enough. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A functional approach to movement analysis and error identification in sports and physical education.Ernst-Joachim Hossner, Frank Schiebl & Ulrich Göhner - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • What Does the Frame Problem Tell us About Moral Normativity?Terry Horgan & Mark Timmons - 2009 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 12 (1):25-51.
    Within cognitive science, mental processing is often construed as computation over mental representations—i.e., as the manipulation and transformation of mental representations in accordance with rules of the kind expressible in the form of a computer program. This foundational approach has encountered a long-standing, persistently recalcitrant, problem often called the frame problem; it is sometimes called the relevance problem. In this paper we describe the frame problem and certain of its apparent morals concerning human cognition, and we argue that these morals (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The epistemic relevance of morphological content.Terry Horgan & Matjaž Potrč - 2010 - Acta Analytica 25 (2):155-173.
    Morphological content is information that is implicitly embodied in the standing structure of a cognitive system and is automatically accommodated during cognitive processing without first becoming explicit in consciousness. We maintain that much belief-formation in human cognition is essentially morphological : i.e., it draws heavily on large amounts of morphological content, and must do so in order to tractably accommodate the holistic evidential relevance of background information possessed by the cognitive agent. We also advocate a form of experiential evidentialism concerning (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Particularist semantic normativity.Terry Horgan & Matjaž Potrč - 2006 - Acta Analytica 21 (1):45-61.
    We sketch the view we call contextual semantics. It asserts that truth is semantically correct affirmability under contextually variable semantic standards, that truth is frequently an indirect form of correspondence between thought/language and the world, and that many Quinean commitments are not genuine ontological commitments. We argue that contextualist semantics fits very naturally with the view that the pertinent semantic standards are particularist rather than being systematizable as exceptionless general principles.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Pr cis of connectionism and the philosophy of psychology.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1997 - Philosophical Psychology 10 (3):337 – 356.
    Connectionism was explicitly put forward as an alternative to classical cognitive science. The questions arise: how exactly does connectionism differ from classical cognitive science, and how is it potentially better? The classical “rules and representations” conception of cognition is that cognitive transitions are determined by exceptionless rules that apply to the syntactic structure of symbols. Many philosophers have seen connectionism as a basis for denying structured symbols. We, on the other hand, argue that cognition is too rich and flexible to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Jennifer Hornsby.Jennifer Hornsby - 2005 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 79 (1):107-130.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Analytic functionalism without representational functionalism.Terence Horgan - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):51-51.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Evolution of Inclusive Folk-Biological Labels and the Cultural Maintenance of Meaning.Ze Hong - 2023 - Human Nature 34 (2):177-201.
    How is word meaning established, and how do individuals acquire it? What ensures the uniform understanding of word meaning in a linguistic community? In this paper I draw from cultural attraction theory and use folk biology as an example domain and address these questions by treating meaning acquisition as an inferential process. I show that significant variation exists in how individuals understand the meaning of inclusive biological labels such as “plant” and “animal” due to variation in their salience in contemporary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark