Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Introducing Kurt Gödel [review of Gödel, Collected Works, Vol. 1: Publications, 1929-1936 ].Billy Joe Lucas - 1989 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 9 (1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Circumscriptive theories: A logic-based framework for knowledge representation. [REVIEW]Vladimir Lifshitz - 1988 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 17 (4):391 - 441.
    The use of circumscription for formalizing commonsense knowledge and reasoning requires that a circumscription policy be selected for each particular application: we should specify which predicates are circumscribed, which predicates and functions are allowed to vary, and what priorities between the circumscribed predicates are established. The circumscription policy is usually described either informally or using suitable metamathematical notation. In this paper we propose a simple and general formalism which permits describing circumscription policies by axioms, included in the knowledge base along (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap.Joseph Levine - 1983 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64 (October):354-61.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   715 citations  
  • Partial monotonic protothetics.François Lepage - 2000 - Studia Logica 66 (1):147-163.
    This paper has four parts. In the first part, I present Leniewski's protothetics and the complete system provided for that logic by Henkin. The second part presents a generalized notion of partial functions in propositional type theory. In the third part, these partial functions are used to define partial interpretations for protothetics. Finally, I present in the fourth part a complete system for partial protothetics. Completeness is proved by Henkin's method [4] using saturated sets instead of maximally saturated sets. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • That principia mathematica, first edition, has a predicative interpretation after all.Hugues Leblanc - 1975 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 4 (1):67 - 70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Matters of relevance.Hugues Leblanc - 1972 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 1 (3/4):269 - 286.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Intuitionist type theory and foundations.J. Lambek & P. J. Scott - 1981 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 10 (1):101 - 115.
    A version of intuitionistic type theory is presented here in which all logical symbols are defined in terms of equality. This language is used to construct the so-called free topos with natural number object. It is argued that the free topos may be regarded as the universe of mathematics from an intuitionist's point of view.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Dunn’s relevant predication, real properties and identity.Philip Kremer - 1997 - Erkenntnis 47 (1):37-65.
    We critically investigate and refine Dunn's relevant predication, his formalisation of the notion of a real property. We argue that Dunn's original dialectical moves presuppose some interpretation of relevant identity, though none is given. We then re-motivate the proposal in a broader context, considering the prospects for a classical formalisation of real properties, particularly of Geach's implicit distinction between real and ''Cambridge'' properties. After arguing against these prospects, we turn to relevance logic, re-motivating relevant predication with Geach's distinction in mind. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Strong logics of first and second order.Peter Koellner - 2010 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 16 (1):1-36.
    In this paper we investigate strong logics of first and second order that have certain absoluteness properties. We begin with an investigation of first order logic and the strong logics ω-logic and β-logic, isolating two facets of absoluteness, namely, generic invariance and faithfulness. It turns out that absoluteness is relative in the sense that stronger background assumptions secure greater degrees of absoluteness. Our aim is to investigate the hierarchies of strong logics of first and second order that are generically invariant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Standard Formalization.Jeffrey Ketland - 2022 - Axiomathes 32 (3):711-748.
    A standard formalization of a scientific theory is a system of axioms for that theory in a first-order language (possibly many-sorted; possibly with the membership primitive $$\in$$ ). Suppes (in: Carvallo M (ed) Nature, cognition and system II. Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1992) expressed skepticism about whether there is a “simple or elegant method” for presenting mathematicized scientific theories in such a standard formalization, because they “assume a great deal of mathematics as part of their substructure”. The major difficulties amount to these. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Characterizing all models in infinite cardinalities.Lauri Keskinen - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (3):230-250.
    Fix a cardinal κ. We can ask the question: what kind of a logic L is needed to characterize all models of cardinality κ up to isomorphism by their L-theories? In other words: for which logics L it is true that if any models A and B of cardinality κ satisfy the same L-theory then they are isomorphic?It is always possible to characterize models of cardinality κ by their Lκ+,κ+-theories, but we are interested in finding a “small” logic L, i.e., (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Analyticity versus fuzziness.John G. Kemeny - 1963 - Synthese 15 (1):57 - 80.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Domains of Sciences, Universes of Discourse and Omega Arguments.Jose M. Saguillo - 1999 - History and Philosophy of Logic 20 (3-4):267-290.
    Each science has its own domain of investigation, but one and the same science can be formalized in different languages with different universes of discourse. The concept of the domain of a science and the concept of the universe of discourse of a formalization of a science are distinct, although they often coincide in extension. In order to analyse the presuppositions and implications of choices of domain and universe, this article discusses the treatment of omega arguments in three very different (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The compactness of first-order logic:from gödel to lindström.John W. Dawson - 1993 - History and Philosophy of Logic 14 (1):15-37.
    Though regarded today as one of the most important results in logic, the compactness theorem was largely ignored until nearly two decades after its discovery. This paper describes the vicissitudes of its evolution and transformation during the period 1930-1970, with special attention to the roles of Kurt Gödel, A. I. Maltsev, Leon Henkin, Abraham Robinson, and Alfred Tarski.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Reduction and Tarski's Definition of Logical Consequence.Jim Edwards - 2003 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 44 (1):49-62.
    In his classic 1936 paper Tarski sought to motivate his definition of logical consequence by appeal to the inference form: P(0), P(1), . . ., P(n), . . . therefore ∀nP(n). This is prima facie puzzling because these inferences are seemingly first-order and Tarski knew that Gödel had shown first-order proof methods to be complete, and because ∀nP(n) is not a logical consequence of P(0), P(1), . . ., P(n), . . . by Taski's proposed definition. An attempt to resolve (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Boolean-Valued Second-Order Logic.Daisuke Ikegami & Jouko Väänänen - 2015 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 56 (1):167-190.
    In so-called full second-order logic, the second-order variables range over all subsets and relations of the domain in question. In so-called Henkin second-order logic, every model is endowed with a set of subsets and relations which will serve as the range of the second-order variables. In our Boolean-valued second-order logic, the second-order variables range over all Boolean-valued subsets and relations on the domain. We show that under large cardinal assumptions Boolean-valued second-order logic is more robust than full second-order logic. Its (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On second-order characterizability.T. Hyttinen, K. Kangas & J. Vaananen - 2013 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 21 (5):767-787.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Probabilities on Sentences in an Expressive Logic.Marcus Hutter, John W. Lloyd, Kee Siong Ng & William T. B. Uther - 2013 - Journal of Applied Logic 11 (4):386-420.
    Automated reasoning about uncertain knowledge has many applications. One difficulty when developing such systems is the lack of a completely satisfactory integration of logic and probability. We address this problem directly. Expressive languages like higher-order logic are ideally suited for representing and reasoning about structured knowledge. Uncertain knowledge can be modeled by using graded probabilities rather than binary truth-values. The main technical problem studied in this paper is the following: Given a set of sentences, each having some probability of being (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The semantic view of theories and higher-order languages.Laurenz Hudetz - 2019 - Synthese 196 (3):1131-1149.
    Several philosophers of science construe models of scientific theories as set-theoretic structures. Some of them moreover claim that models should not be construed as structures in the sense of model theory because the latter are language-dependent. I argue that if we are ready to construe models as set-theoretic structures (strict semantic view), we could equally well construe them as model-theoretic structures of higher-order logic (liberal semantic view). I show that every family of set-theoretic structures has an associated language of higher-order (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Truth definitions, Skolem functions and axiomatic set theory.Jaakko Hintikka - 1998 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 4 (3):303-337.
    §1. The mission of axiomatic set theory. What is set theory needed for in the foundations of mathematics? Why cannot we transact whatever foundational business we have to transact in terms of our ordinary logic without resorting to set theory? There are many possible answers, but most of them are likely to be variations of the same theme. The core area of ordinary logic is by a fairly common consent the received first-order logic. Why cannot it take care of itself? (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Quantifiers vs. Quantification Theory.Jaakko Hintikka - 1973 - Dialectica 27 (3‐4):329-358.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • On göde's philosophical assumptions.Jaakko Hintikka - 1998 - Synthese 114 (1):13-23.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Independence-friendly logic and axiomatic set theory.Jaakko Hintikka - 2004 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 126 (1-3):313-333.
    In order to be able to express all possible patterns of dependence and independence between variables, we have to replace the traditional first-order logic by independence-friendly (IF) logic. Our natural concept of truth for a quantificational sentence S says that all the Skolem functions for S exist. This conception of truth for a sufficiently rich IF first-order language can be expressed in the same language. In a first-order axiomatic set theory, one can apparently express this same concept in set-theoretical terms, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Carnap's work in the foundations of logic and mathematics in a historical perspective.Jaakko Hintikka - 1992 - Synthese 93 (1-2):167 - 189.
    Carnap's philosophy is examined from new viewpoints, including three important distinctions: (i) language as calculus vs language as universal medium; (ii) different senses of completeness: (iii) standard vs nonstandard interpretations of (higher-order) logic. (i) Carnap favored in 1930-34 the "formal mode of speech," a corollary to the universality assumption. He later gave it up partially but retained some of its ingredients, e.g., the one-domain assumption. (ii) Carnap's project of creating a universal self-referential language is encouraged by (ii) and by the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • A revolution in the foundations of mathematics?Jaakko Hintikka - 1997 - Synthese 111 (2):155-170.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The discovery of my completeness proofs.Leon Henkin - 1996 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2 (2):127-158.
    §1. Introduction. This paper deals with aspects of my doctoral dissertation which contributed to the early development of model theory. What was of use to later workers was less the results of my thesis, than the method by which I proved the completeness of first-order logic—a result established by Kurt Gödel in his doctoral thesis 18 years before.The ideas that fed my discovery of this proof were mostly those I found in the teachings and writings of Alonzo Church. This may (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Russell's 1925 logic.A. P. Hazen & J. M. Davoren - 2000 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78 (4):534 – 556.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Second-Order Logic of Paradox.Allen P. Hazen & Francis Jeffry Pelletier - 2018 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 59 (4):547-558.
    The logic of paradox, LP, is a first-order, three-valued logic that has been advocated by Graham Priest as an appropriate way to represent the possibility of acceptable contradictory statements. Second-order LP is that logic augmented with quantification over predicates. As with classical second-order logic, there are different ways to give the semantic interpretation of sentences of the logic. The different ways give rise to different logical advantages and disadvantages, and we canvass several of these, concluding that it will be extremely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Pecularities of Some Three- and Four-Valued Second Order Logics.Allen P. Hazen & Francis Jeffry Pelletier - 2018 - Logica Universalis 12 (3-4):493-509.
    Logics that have many truth values—more than just True and False—have been argued to be useful in the analysis of very many philosophical and linguistic puzzles. In this paper, which is a followup to, we will start with a particularly well-motivated four-valued logic that has been studied mainly in its propositional and first-order versions. And we will then investigate its second-order version. This four-valued logic has two natural three-valued extensions: what is called a “gap logic”, and what is called a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Zur Axiomatisierung der k‐zahlig allgemeingültigen Ausdrücke des Stufenkalküls.Gisbert Hasenjaeger - 1958 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 4 (12‐16):175-177.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Zur Axiomatisierung derk-zahlig allgemeingültigen Ausdrücke des Stufenkalküls.Gisbert Hasenjaeger - 1958 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 4 (12-16):175-177.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The three arrows of Zeno.Craig Harrison - 1996 - Synthese 107 (2):271 - 292.
    We explore the better known paradoxes of Zeno including modern variants based on infinite processes, from the point of view of standard, classical analysis, from which there is still much to learn (especially concerning the paradox of division), and then from the viewpoints of non-standard and non-classical analysis (the logic of the latter being intuitionist).The standard, classical or Cantorian notion of the continuum, modeled on the real number line, is well known, as is the definition of motion as the time (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Mathematical modal logic: A view of its evolution.Robert Goldblatt - 2003 - Journal of Applied Logic 1 (5-6):309-392.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • An Admissible Semantics for Propositionally Quantified Relevant Logics.Robert Goldblatt & Michael Kane - 2010 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 39 (1):73-100.
    The Routley-Meyer relational semantics for relevant logics is extended to give a sound and complete model theory for many propositionally quantified relevant logics (and some non-relevant ones). This involves a restriction on which sets of worlds are admissible as propositions, and an interpretation of propositional quantification that makes ∀ pA true when there is some true admissible proposition that entails all p -instantiations of A . It is also shown that without the admissibility qualification many of the systems considered are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Forcing, Downward Löwenheim-Skolem and Omitting Types Theorems, Institutionally.Daniel Găină - 2014 - Logica Universalis 8 (3-4):469-498.
    In the context of proliferation of many logical systems in the area of mathematical logic and computer science, we present a generalization of forcing in institution-independent model theory which is used to prove two abstract results: Downward Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem and Omitting Types Theorem . We instantiate these general results to many first-order logics, which are, roughly speaking, logics whose sentences can be constructed from atomic formulas by means of Boolean connectives and classical first-order quantifiers. These include first-order logic , logic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kripke models and the (in)equational logic of the second-order λ-calculus.Jean Gallier - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 84 (3):257-316.
    We define a new class of Kripke structures for the second-order λ-calculus, and investigate the soundness and completeness of some proof systems for proving inequalities as well as equations. The Kripke structures under consideration are equipped with preorders that correspond to an abstract form of reduction, and they are not necessarily extensional. A novelty of our approach is that we define these structures directly as functors A: → Preor equipped with certain natural transformations corresponding to application and abstraction . We (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • General Models and Entailment Semantics for Independence Logic.Pietro Galliani - 2013 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 54 (2):253-275.
    We develop a semantics for independence logic with respect to what we will call general models. We then introduce a simpler entailment semantics for the same logic, and we reduce the validity problem in the former to the validity problem in the latter. Then we build a proof system for independence logic and prove its soundness and completeness with respect to entailment semantics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Semantical investigations on non-classical logics with recovery operators: negation.David Fuenmayor - forthcoming - Logic Journal of the IGPL.
    We investigate mathematical structures that provide natural semantics for families of (quantified) non-classical logics featuring special unary connectives, known as recovery operators, that allow us to ‘recover’ the properties of classical logic in a controlled manner. These structures are known as topological Boolean algebras, which are Boolean algebras extended with additional operations subject to specific conditions of a topological nature. In this study, we focus on the paradigmatic case of negation. We demonstrate how these algebras are well-suited to provide a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An Expressive First-Order Logic with Flexible Typing for Natural Language Semantics.Chris Fox & Shalom Lappin - 2004 - Logic Journal of the Interest Group in Pure and Applied Logics 12 (2):135--168.
    We present Property Theory with Curry Typing (PTCT), an intensional first-order logic for natural language semantics. PTCT permits fine-grained specifications of meaning. It also supports polymorphic types and separation types. We develop an intensional number theory within PTCT in order to represent proportional generalized quantifiers like “most.” We use the type system and our treatment of generalized quantifiers in natural language to construct a type-theoretic approach to pronominal anaphora that avoids some of the difficulties that undermine previous type-theoretic analyses of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the algebraization of Henkin‐type second‐order logic.Miklós Ferenczi - 2022 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 68 (2):149-158.
    There is an extensive literature related to the algebraization of first‐order logic. But the algebraization of full second‐order logic, or Henkin‐type second‐order logic, has hardly been researched. The question arises: what kind of set algebra is the algebraic version of a Henkin‐type model of second‐order logic? The question is investigated within the framework of the theory of cylindric algebras. The answer is: a kind of cylindric‐relativized diagonal restricted set algebra. And the class of the subdirect products of these set algebras (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The seven virtues of simple type theory.William M. Farmer - 2008 - Journal of Applied Logic 6 (3):267-286.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A simple type theory with partial functions and subtypes11Supported by the MITRE-Sponsored Research program. Presented at the 9th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science held in Uppsala, Sweden, August 7-14, 1991. [REVIEW]William M. Farmer - 1993 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 64 (3):211-240.
    Simple type theory is a higher-order predicate logic for reasoning about truth values, individuals, and simply typed total functions. We present in this paper a version of simple type theory, called PF*, in which functions may be partial and types may have subtypes. We define both a Henkin-style general models semantics and an axiomatic system for PF*, and we prove that the axiomatic system is complete with respect to the general models semantics. We also define a notion of an interpretation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A Simple Type Theory With Partial Functions And Subtypes.William M. Farmer - 1993 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 64 (3):211-240.
    Simple type theory is a higher-order predicate logic for reasoning about truth values, individuals, and simply typed total functions. We present in this paper a version of simple type theory, called PF*, in which functions may be partial and types may have subtypes. We define both a Henkin-style general models semantics and an axiomatic system for PF*, and we prove that the axiomatic system is complete with respect to the general models semantics. We also define a notion of an interpretation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Am anfang war die tat.Wilhelm K. Essler - 1996 - Erkenntnis 44 (3):257 - 277.
    First, the paper argues that Tarski's theory of language levels is best understood not only as a method for avoiding semantic paradoxes by rigidly restricting the expressive power of a language, but as a natural expression of an epistemological process of reflection which is more adequately understood as a process and not by its result. Second, it is argued that the apparent philosophical controversy between materialism and idealism dissolves whithin this process of reflection. If one has raised above the lowest (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Lewisian Naturalness and a new Sceptical Challenge.Matej Drobňák - forthcoming - Logic and Logical Philosophy:3-28.
    The criterion of naturalness represents David Lewis’s attempt to answer some of the sceptical arguments in semantics by comparing the naturalness of meaning candidates. Recently, the criterion has been challenged by a new sceptical argument. Williams argues that the criterion cannot rule out the candidates which are not permuted versions of an intended interpretation. He presents such a candidate – the arithmetical interpretation semantics by comparing the naturalness of meaning candidates. Recently, the criterion has been challenged by a new sceptical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • To Be F Is To Be G.Cian Dorr - 2016 - Philosophical Perspectives 30 (1):39-134.
    This paper is an investigation of the general logic of "identifications", claims such as 'To be a vixen is to be a female fox', 'To be human is to be a rational animal', and 'To be just is to help one's friends and harm one's enemies', many of which are of great importance to philosophers. I advocate understanding such claims as expressing higher-order identity, and discuss a variety of different general laws which they might be thought to obey. [New version: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   172 citations  
  • Leśniewski's Systems of Logic and Foundations of Mathematics.Rafal Urbaniak - 2013 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
    With material on his early philosophical views, his contributions to set theory and his work on nominalism and higher-order quantification, this book offers a uniquely expansive critical commentary on one of analytical philosophy’s great ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Logica Universalis: Towards a General Theory of Logic.Jean-Yves Béziau (ed.) - 2007 - Boston: Birkhäuser Basel.
    Universal Logic is not a new logic, but a general theory of logics, considered as mathematical structures. The name was introduced about ten years ago, but the subject is as old as the beginning of modern logic: Alfred Tarski and other Polish logicians such as Adolf Lindenbaum developed a general theory of logics at the end of the 1920s based on consequence operations and logical matrices. The subject was revived after the flowering of thousands of new logics during the last (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Age of Alternative Logics: Assessing Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics Today.Johan van Benthem, Gerhard Heinzman, M. Rebushi & H. Visser (eds.) - 2006 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    This book explores the interplay between logic and science, describing new trends, new issues and potential research developments.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Games: Unifying Logic, Language, and Philosophy.Ondrej Majer, Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen & Tero Tulenheimo (eds.) - 2009 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag.
    This volume presents mathematical game theory as an interface between logic and philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark