Switch to: References

Citations of:

Parts of recognition

Cognition 18 (1-3):65-96 (1984)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Are spatial representations flattish?J. B. Deregowski - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):243-244.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Constraining tag-assignment from above and below.Michael R. W. Dawson - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):400-402.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Facial Attention and Spacetime Fragments.T. N. Davies & D. D. Hoffman - 2003 - Global Philosophy 13 (3-4):303-327.
    Inverting a face impairs perception of its features and recognition of its identity. Whether faces are special in this regard is a current topic of research and debate. Kanizsa studied the role of facial features and environmental context in perceiving the emotion and identity of upright and inverted faces. He found that observers are biased to interpret faces in a retinal coordinate frame, and that this bias is readily overruled by increased realism of facial features, but not easily overruled by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Generative versus nongenerative thought.Michael C. Corballis - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):242-243.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Visual attention and beyond.Kyle R. Cave - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):400-400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Representational advantages.Roberto Casati - 2003 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 103 (3):281–298.
    Descriptive metaphysics investigates our naïve ontology as this is articulated in the content of our perception or of our pre-reflective thought about the world. But is access to such content reliable? Sceptics about the standard modes of access (introspection, or language-driven intuitions) may think that investigations in descriptive metaphysics can be aided by the controlled findings of cognitive science. Cognitive scientists have studied a promising range of representational advantages, that is, ways in which cognition favours one type of entity over (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Do we need an early locus of attention to resolve illusory conjunctions?Brian E. Butler - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):398-400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Frames of reference in the spatial representation system.David J. Bryant - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):241-242.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The role of cerebral lateralization in expression of spatial cognition.Halle D. Brown - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):240-241.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Spatial and cognitive vision differentiate at low levels, but not in language.Bruce Bridgeman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):240-240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Modeling separate processing pathways for spatial and object vision.Bruce Bridgeman - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):398-398.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Recognition-by-components: A theory of human image understanding.Irving Biederman - 1987 - Psychological Review 94 (2):115-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   534 citations  
  • On the relation between Kanizsa's bias towards convexity and the gestaltists prägnanz from the perspective of current in shape recognition.Irving Biederman - 2003 - Axiomathes 13 (3-4):329-346.
    What is the relation between Kanizsa's bias towards convexity and the Gestaltists' demonstrations that perceptual organization obeys a principle of pragnänz, or simplicity? Why should either kind of bias exist? Textbook accounts assign no functional role for these biases. Geon theory (Biederman 1987) proposes that we can understand these biases in terms of fundamental processes by which complex objects are decomposed into convex (or singly concave) regions at points of matched cusps according to the transversality regularity (Hoffman and Richards 1985). (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The shape of holes.Marco Bertamini & Camilla J. Croucher - 2003 - Cognition 87 (1):33-54.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • There is more to location than prepositions.David C. Bennett - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):239-239.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Seeing Shape: Shape Appearances and Shape Constancy.David J. Bennett - 2012 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 63 (3):487-518.
    A coin rotating back in depth in some sense presents a changing, elliptical shape. How are we to understand such (in this case) ‘appearances of ellipticality’? How is the experiential sense of such shifting shape appearances related to the experiential sense of enduring shape definitive of perceived shape constancy? Is the experiential recovery of surface shape based on the prior (perhaps more fundamental) recovery of point or element 3D spatial locations?—or is the perception of shape a largely independent perceptual achievement? (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Determination of visual figure and ground in dynamically deforming shapes.Elan Barenholtz & Jacob Feldman - 2006 - Cognition 101 (3):530-544.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Detection of change in shape: an advantage for concavities.Elan Barenholtz, Elias H. Cohen, Jacob Feldman & Manish Singh - 2003 - Cognition 89 (1):1-9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The emergence of events.Judith Avrahami & Yaakov Kareev - 1994 - Cognition 53 (3):239-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Synchrony of spikes and attention in visual cortex.F. Aiple & B. Fischer - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):397-397.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Surfaces, holes, shadows.Roberto Casati - 2009 - In Robin Le Poidevin, Simons Peter, McGonigal Andrew & Ross P. Cameron (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Metaphysics. New York: Routledge. pp. 382--388.
    Minor entities provide an interesting testbed for metaphysical theories, but also for investigating the structure of concepts, as their concepts appear to be tributary of different representational systems.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Perspectival Character of Perception.Kevin J. Lande - 2018 - Journal of Philosophy 115 (4):187-214.
    You can perceive things, in many respects, as they really are. For example, you can correctly see a coin as circular from most angles. Nonetheless, your perception of the world is perspectival. The coin looks different when slanted than when head-on, and there is some respect in which the slanted coin looks similar to a head-on ellipse. Many hold that perception is perspectival because you perceive certain properties that correspond to the “looks” of things. I argue that this view is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Talking to yourself about what is where: What is the vocabulary of preattentive vision?Jeremy M. Wolfe - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):254-255.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “What” and “where” in spatial language and spatial cognition.Barbara Landau & Ray Jackendoff - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):217-238.
    Fundamental to spatial knowledge in all species are the representations underlying object recognition, object search, and navigation through space. But what sets humans apart from other species is our ability to express spatial experience through language. This target article explores the language ofobjectsandplaces, asking what geometric properties are preserved in the representations underlying object nouns and spatial prepositions in English. Evidence from these two aspects of language suggests there are significant differences in the geometric richness with which objects and places (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • Using movement and intentions to understand simple events.Jeffrey M. Zacks - 2004 - Cognitive Science 28 (6):979-1008.
    In order to understand ongoing activity, observers segment it into meaningful temporal parts. Segmentation can be based on bottom‐up processing of distinctive sensory characteristics, such as movement features. Segmentation may also be affected by top‐down effects of knowledge structures, including information about actors' intentions. Three experiments investigated the role of movement features and intentions in perceptual event segmentation, using simple animations. In all conditions, movement features significantly predicted where participants segmented. This relationship was stronger when participants identified larger units than (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Perceiving, remembering, and communicating structure in events.Jeffrey M. Zacks, Barbara Tversky & Gowri Iyer - 2001 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 130 (1):29.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Attention to detail?Malcolm P. Young, Ian R. Paterson & David I. Perrett - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):417-418.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Perceptual influence of elementary three-dimensional geometry: objectness.Florentin Wörgötter, Rahel M. Sutterlütti & Minija Tamosiunaite - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Where's the psychological reality?C. Philip Winder - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):417-417.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Superordinate shape classification using natural shape statistics.John Wilder, Jacob Feldman & Manish Singh - 2011 - Cognition 119 (3):325-340.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Local contour symmetry facilitates scene categorization.John Wilder, Morteza Rezanejad, Sven Dickinson, Kaleem Siddiqi, Allan Jepson & Dirk B. Walther - 2019 - Cognition 182 (C):307-317.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Parts and Wholes in Expression Recognition.Murray White - 2000 - Cognition and Emotion 14 (1):39-60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Is extension to perception of real-world objects and scenes possible?J. Wagemans, K. Verfaillie, P. De Graef & K. Lamberts - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):415-417.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From observations on language to theories of visual perception.Johan Wagemans - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):253-254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward a biased competition account of object-based segregation and attention.Shaun P. Vecera - 2000 - Brain and Mind 1 (3):353-384.
    Because the visual system cannot process all of the objects, colors, and features present in a visual scene, visual attention allows some visual stimuli to be selected and processed over others. Most research on visual attention has focused on spatial or location-based attention, in which the locations occupied by stimuli are selected for further processing. Recent research, however, has demonstrated the importance of objects in organizing (or segregating) visual scenes and guiding attentional selection. Because of the long history of spatial (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Reasoning about Space: The Hole Story.Achille C. Varzi - 1996 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 4:3-39.
    This is a revised and extended version of the formal theory of holes outlined in the Appendix to the book "Holes and Other Superficialities". The first part summarizes the basic framework (ontology, mereology, topology, morphology). The second part emphasizes its relevance to spatial reasoning and to the semantics of spatial prepositions in natural language. In particular, I discuss the semantics of ‘in’ and provide an account of such fallacious arguments as “There is a hole in the sheet. The sheet is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • On Perceiving Abs nces.Achille C. Varzi - 2022 - Gestalt Theory 44 (3):213-242.
    Can we really perceive absences, i.e., missing things? Sartre tells us that when he arrived late for his appointment at the café, he saw the absence of his friend Pierre. Is that really what he saw? Where was it, exactly? Why didn’t Sartre see the absence of other people who were not there? Why did other people who were there not see the absence of Pierre? The perception of absences gives rise to a host of conundrums and is constantly on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aligning pictorial descriptions: An approach to object recognition.Shimon Ullman - 1989 - Cognition 32 (3):193-254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Prepositions aren't places.Barbara Tversky & Herbert H. Clark - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):252-253.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A contour propagation approach to surface filling-in and volume formation.Peter Ulric Tse - 2002 - Psychological Review 109 (1):91-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ordinal structure in the visual perception and cognition of smoothly curved surfaces.James T. Todd & Francene D. Reichel - 1989 - Psychological Review 96 (4):643-657.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • From perception to cognition.Michael J. Tarr - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):251-252.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mapping attractor fields in face space: the atypicality bias in face recognition.J. Tanaka - 1998 - Cognition 68 (3):199-219.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Perceptual influence of elementary three-dimensional geometry: (2) fundamental object parts.Minija Tamosiunaite, Rahel M. Sutterlütti, Simon C. Stein & Florentin Wörgötter - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is the tag necessary?Ron Sun & Emmanuel Schalit - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):415-415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The value of modeling visual attention.Gary W. Strong & Bruce A. Whitehead - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):419-433.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The lemon illusion: seeing curvature where there is none.Lars Strother, Kyle W. Killebrew & Gideon P. Caplovitz - 2015 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A solution to the tag-assignment problem for neural networks.Gary W. Strong & Bruce A. Whitehead - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):381-397.
    Purely parallel neural networks can model object recognition in brief displays – the same conditions under which illusory conjunctions have been demonstrated empirically. Correcting errors of illusory conjunction is the “tag-assignment” problem for a purely parallel processor: the problem of assigning a spatial tag to nonspatial features, feature combinations, and objects. This problem must be solved to model human object recognition over a longer time scale. Our model simulates both the parallel processes that may underlie illusory conjunctions and the serial (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   175 citations  
  • Thinking, Experiencing and Rethinking Mereological Interdependence.Michael W. Stadler - 2019 - Gestalt Theory 41 (1):31-46.
    Summary The present article is a partly ontological, partly Gestalt-psychological discussion of the thinkability of structures in which parts and whole are interdependent (MI). In the first section, I show that in the framework of E. Husserl’s formal part–whole ontology, the conceptualization of such an interdependence leads to (mereo)logical problems. The second section turns to and affirms the experience of this interplay between parts and whole, exemplified with B. Pinna’s recent research on meaningful Gestalt perception. In the final section, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is spatial language a special case?Dan I. Slobin - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):249-251.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark